take notes as a personal guide for responding to the writing prompts, the journal summary, and topics/questions for the group discussion. Submit these notes as a simple bulleted list that follows the content and your thought process as you read through it.
Skilling Saws and Absorbent Catalogs
Kenneth FitzGerald
Originally published in Emigre Magazine
Included in the collection Volume: Writings on
Graphic Design, Music, Art, and Culture
ISBN: 9781568989648
Emigre Magazine:
https://www.emigre.com/Essays/Magazine/SkillingSawsandAbsorbentCatalogs
FitzGerald, Kenneth. “Skilling Saws and Absorbent Catalogs.” Emigre, no. 48, 1998, pp. 29-39.
CSULB Library Permalink:
https://csu-lb.primo.exlibrisgroup.com/permalink/01CALS_ULB/d7ul0l/alma991053822269702901
FitzGerald, Kenneth. Volume: Writings on Graphic Design, Music, Art, and Culture. 1st ed.,
Princeton Architectural Press, 2010.
discussion of our visual culture.
More than conceiving new theory, we need to identify and disassemble the many ill-constructed conceptions
between and within art and design. Ultimately, consilience is a radical action for both fields. For art,
consilience challenges a position at the top of the cultural food-chain. A major threat for design is to the
stature of designers whose regard within the field depends upon peer ignorance of art.
The paradox of design is that the more it tries to distance itself from art and assert independence, the more
art-like it becomes. Conversely, prominent efforts to (re)connect design to art have only served to devalue
design and produce a legion of irascible practitioners.
Articulating a substantive difference between art and design is impracticable. In terms of forms, process,
intent, causality, or response, the activities are identical. Difference lies in the sector of consumer culture one
wishes to operate in, and the cultural role we feel most comfortable playing.
IT IS CLEAR THAT ART IS USELESS, THAT PERCEIVER AND ARTIST ARE ARROGANT AND
INDIFFERENT. … ART TELLS US NOTHING ABOUT THE WORLD THAT WE CANNOT FIND
ELSEWHERE AND MORE RELIABLY. ART DOES NOT MAKE US BETTER CITIZENS, OR MORE
MORAL, OR MORE HONEST. IT MAY CONCEIVABLY MAKE US WORSE
Morse Peckham
THE PRESUMPTION OF ART’S ESSENTIAL “GOODNESS” IS A CONVENTIONAL TROPE. IT
DESCRIBES NOTHING. ART EDUCATION IS NOT REDEEMING FOR THE VAST MAJORITY OF
STUDENTS, NOR IS ART PRACTICE REDEEMING FOR THE VAST MAJORITY OF ARTISTS. THE
“GOOD” WORKS OF ART THAT RESIDE IN OUR MUSEUMS RESIDE THERE NOT BECAUSE
THEY ARE “GOOD,” BUT BECAUSE WE LOVE THEM…(THIS) IS THE ARGUMENT: ART IS
GOOD, SORT OF, IN A VAGUE, GENERAL WAY. SEDUCING ONESELF INTO BELIEVING IN
ART’S INTRINSIC “GOODNESS,” HOWEVER, IS SIMPLY BAD RELIGION, NO MATTER WHAT
THE REWARDS.’
Dave Hickey
THE CAP A, DROPPED
The immediate obstacle in talking about art is locating which one you’re talking about. Is it the personal, the
pop cultural, or academic definition? The calling or the art culture industry? As described by art historian
Donald Preziosi, the academic meaning is constantly in flux. “The broad amalgam of complementary fields in
which the modern discipline of art history is positioned never achieved fixed or uniform institutional
integration. Nevertheless, in the long run its looseness…proved particularly effective in naturalizing and
validating the very idea of art as a ‘universal’ human phenomenon.”
Transition is the requisite state. A conditional answer is all that is possible. (Want design to be art? Wait a
few minutes.) With the expansion of what art history considers its field of study, excluding anything – not
simply design – is problematic. Selecting out design becomes a matter of personal taste or prejudice. These
motivations continue to be the most powerful influences on discourse.
A more fundamental complication in debating art is the origin of the term. The structure of our language
precludes arriving at a functional definition. When Aristotle and Plato carved up reality, art was the Other. Art
is what’s left when you can’t categorize something as useful. To paraphrase Lacan, l’art il n’existe pas. Rather
than being elevating and resplendent, the term is a linguistic black hole. Calling something art effectively
removes it from our universe altogether. The activity collapses into a realm we can only speculate upon.
Those speculations are essentially mystical. Art is venerated for its ability to produce transcendent
experiences. Attributed to art are virtues and verities that are as profound as they are ineffable. While these
art apotheoses are likely very real for their recipients, we may still question their cause. All attempts to locate
“artness” within objects or their producers have proved failures. Describing the art experience is more rightly
the province of perception theory and cultural study.
Morse Peckham describes art in terms of role playing. The purpose of studying art is to instruct us in how to
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 29
THE TEACHER TRIES TO MAKE THE ASPECTS OF GRAPHIC DESIGN INTERESTING BUT HE
REALLY CAN’T BECAUSE THEY ARE BORING.
Art student’s evaluation of Foundation Graphic Design course, Spring 1997, Kenneth FitzGerald, Instructor
THE MATTER WITH TWO MINDS
Designers have an art conflict. When attempting to establish design quality, discussions customarily enter –
some say intrude into – the region of art. Is design an art overall? Is great design art? For the latter question,
the answer’s usually “yes,” no matter what designer you ask. For the former question, the answer seems
invariably to be “no.”
Paul Rand himself couldn’t arrive at a consistent, coherent answer to those questions. Depending upon
where his theorizing wandered, design was or was not art. Neither author nor editor cared (or dared) resolve
the internal inconsistency created by contradictory claims. To Rand’s legacy we may add this art-
schizophrenia. Design desires to be art and not-art simultaneously – and fears it’s nothing.
While it is futile to argue what is and isn’t art or design, we will gain from studying the origin and operation
of the terms. By revealing our need for such terms, we may move to a healthy method of evaluation. The goal is
not to “elevate” design to art’s level but to relocate both. It’s a given that art has a higher cultural station,
however nebulous and undeserved. Establishing this hierarchy is an evaluating function based entirely upon
self-image rather than objective criteria. People want the prestige that derives either from producing art or
knowing it when they see it. This despite the fact that there is not, never has been, and never will be a
consensus on what art is. Art is all aura – wondrous but unable to sustain itself under the spotlight.
Challenging stock convictions may move us toward what Edward O. Wilson calls a “consilience.” This obscure
1840 word derives from William Whewell’s book The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. Wilson describes the
word as meaning “…literally a ‘jumping together’ of knowledge as a result of the linking of facts and fact-based
theory across disciplines to create a common groundwork of explanation.” As art and design are intellectual
constructs, we can never prove any assertions. We may, however, establish a more realistic foundation for
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS
B y K e n n e t h F i t z G e r a l d
T Y P E F A C E S U S E D I N T H I S A R T I C L E :
Running heads and folios set in 7 point Tarzana Narrow Bold Italic. Tracking 20.
Headline set in 18 point Tarzana Narrow Bold Italic. Tracking 20.
By line set in 10 point Tarzana Wide Bold Italic. Tracking 20.
Feature article set in 10/14 point Tarzana Narrow Regular, Bold, and Italic. Tracking 5.
Quotes inside text set in 9/13 Filosofia Regular. Tracking 5.
Quotes set in 14/13 Tarzana Narrow Bold Italic.
discussion of our visual culture.
More than conceiving new theory, we need to identify and disassemble the many ill-constructed conceptions
between and within art and design. Ultimately, consilience is a radical action for both fields. For art,
consilience challenges a position at the top of the cultural food-chain. A major threat for design is to the
stature of designers whose regard within the field depends upon peer ignorance of art.
The paradox of design is that the more it tries to distance itself from art and assert independence, the more
art-like it becomes. Conversely, prominent efforts to (re)connect design to art have only served to devalue
design and produce a legion of irascible practitioners.
Articulating a substantive difference between art and design is impracticable. In terms of forms, process,
intent, causality, or response, the activities are identical. Difference lies in the sector of consumer culture one
wishes to operate in, and the cultural role we feel most comfortable playing.
IT IS CLEAR THAT ART IS USELESS, THAT PERCEIVER AND ARTIST ARE ARROGANT AND
INDIFFERENT. … ART TELLS US NOTHING ABOUT THE WORLD THAT WE CANNOT FIND
ELSEWHERE AND MORE RELIABLY. ART DOES NOT MAKE US BETTER CITIZENS, OR MORE
MORAL, OR MORE HONEST. IT MAY CONCEIVABLY MAKE US WORSE
Morse Peckham
THE PRESUMPTION OF ART’S ESSENTIAL “GOODNESS” IS A CONVENTIONAL TROPE. IT
DESCRIBES NOTHING. ART EDUCATION IS NOT REDEEMING FOR THE VAST MAJORITY OF
STUDENTS, NOR IS ART PRACTICE REDEEMING FOR THE VAST MAJORITY OF ARTISTS. THE
“GOOD” WORKS OF ART THAT RESIDE IN OUR MUSEUMS RESIDE THERE NOT BECAUSE
THEY ARE “GOOD,” BUT BECAUSE WE LOVE THEM…(THIS) IS THE ARGUMENT: ART IS
GOOD, SORT OF, IN A VAGUE, GENERAL WAY. SEDUCING ONESELF INTO BELIEVING IN
ART’S INTRINSIC “GOODNESS,” HOWEVER, IS SIMPLY BAD RELIGION, NO MATTER WHAT
THE REWARDS.’
Dave Hickey
THE CAP A, DROPPED
The immediate obstacle in talking about art is locating which one you’re talking about. Is it the personal, the
pop cultural, or academic definition? The calling or the art culture industry? As described by art historian
Donald Preziosi, the academic meaning is constantly in flux. “The broad amalgam of complementary fields in
which the modern discipline of art history is positioned never achieved fixed or uniform institutional
integration. Nevertheless, in the long run its looseness…proved particularly effective in naturalizing and
validating the very idea of art as a ‘universal’ human phenomenon.”
Transition is the requisite state. A conditional answer is all that is possible. (Want design to be art? Wait a
few minutes.) With the expansion of what art history considers its field of study, excluding anything – not
simply design – is problematic. Selecting out design becomes a matter of personal taste or prejudice. These
motivations continue to be the most powerful influences on discourse.
A more fundamental complication in debating art is the origin of the term. The structure of our language
precludes arriving at a functional definition. When Aristotle and Plato carved up reality, art was the Other. Art
is what’s left when you can’t categorize something as useful. To paraphrase Lacan, l’art il n’existe pas. Rather
than being elevating and resplendent, the term is a linguistic black hole. Calling something art effectively
removes it from our universe altogether. The activity collapses into a realm we can only speculate upon.
Those speculations are essentially mystical. Art is venerated for its ability to produce transcendent
experiences. Attributed to art are virtues and verities that are as profound as they are ineffable. While these
art apotheoses are likely very real for their recipients, we may still question their cause. All attempts to locate
“artness” within objects or their producers have proved failures. Describing the art experience is more rightly
the province of perception theory and cultural study.
Morse Peckham describes art in terms of role playing. The purpose of studying art is to instruct us in how to
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 29
THE TEACHER TRIES TO MAKE THE ASPECTS OF GRAPHIC DESIGN INTERESTING BUT HE
REALLY CAN’T BECAUSE THEY ARE BORING.
Art student’s evaluation of Foundation Graphic Design course, Spring 1997, Kenneth FitzGerald, Instructor
THE MATTER WITH TWO MINDS
Designers have an art conflict. When attempting to establish design quality, discussions customarily enter –
some say intrude into – the region of art. Is design an art overall? Is great design art? For the latter question,
the answer’s usually “yes,” no matter what designer you ask. For the former question, the answer seems
invariably to be “no.”
Paul Rand himself couldn’t arrive at a consistent, coherent answer to those questions. Depending upon
where his theorizing wandered, design was or was not art. Neither author nor editor cared (or dared) resolve
the internal inconsistency created by contradictory claims. To Rand’s legacy we may add this art-
schizophrenia. Design desires to be art and not-art simultaneously – and fears it’s nothing.
While it is futile to argue what is and isn’t art or design, we will gain from studying the origin and operation
of the terms. By revealing our need for such terms, we may move to a healthy method of evaluation. The goal is
not to “elevate” design to art’s level but to relocate both. It’s a given that art has a higher cultural station,
however nebulous and undeserved. Establishing this hierarchy is an evaluating function based entirely upon
self-image rather than objective criteria. People want the prestige that derives either from producing art or
knowing it when they see it. This despite the fact that there is not, never has been, and never will be a
consensus on what art is. Art is all aura – wondrous but unable to sustain itself under the spotlight.
Challenging stock convictions may move us toward what Edward O. Wilson calls a “consilience.” This obscure
1840 word derives from William Whewell’s book The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. Wilson describes the
word as meaning “…literally a ‘jumping together’ of knowledge as a result of the linking of facts and fact-based
theory across disciplines to create a common groundwork of explanation.” As art and design are intellectual
constructs, we can never prove any assertions. We may, however, establish a more realistic foundation for
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS
B y K e n n e t h F i t z G e r a l d
T Y P E F A C E S U S E D I N T H I S A R T I C L E :
Running heads and folios set in 7 point Tarzana Narrow Bold Italic. Tracking 20.
Headline set in 18 point Tarzana Narrow Bold Italic. Tracking 20.
By line set in 10 point Tarzana Wide Bold Italic. Tracking 20.
Feature article set in 10/14 point Tarzana Narrow Regular, Bold, and Italic. Tracking 5.
Quotes inside text set in 9/13 Filosofia Regular. Tracking 5.
Quotes set in 14/13 Tarzana Narrow Bold Italic.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 31
backward and archaic. Rather than responding to the critiques of their models – in other words, recognizing
any of the art made in the latter half of this century – Rand and his followers dismiss them. Their neglect of art
begins at about the time when Dwiggins coins the term “graphic design.” It’s almost as if the birth of design
meant the end of art. Or that design is heir to the true, historical art.
“To poke fun at form or formalism is to poke fun at… the philosophy called aesthetics,” Rand wrote in his
essay “From Cassandra to Chaos.” The problem is, art had been debunking aesthetics his entire adult life. In his
books, Rand referenced outdated doctrines, peppered his text with quotes yanked out of context, and
constructed a philosophy ultimately dependent upon his status in his field. Only within design could you find
regard for these declarations.
Of course, Rand’s books were self-promotions. The theory’s ultimate end is creating a noble lineage into
which he inserts his work. Like David Carson’s The End of Print, these books theorize to self-aggrandize. An
objective, critical analysis is nowhere on the agenda. The art interpretations made by design-star
hagiographer Lewis Blackwell in David Carson’s name supervene Rand’s in shallowness and distortion. Both
theorize from surface readings. Carson considers his work as having “similarity” with “Outsider Art/Art Brut” in
2nd Sight. The statement sounds learned but is more empty romanticism. Ignored, as always, are the quite
separate historic, intellectual and cultural circumstances that brought these artistic conceits into fashion.
The former construction, “outsider art,” is a self-negating term (if it’s outside art, it’s not art) which
denigrates, not celebrates, the activity. Carson’s “outsider” stance is similar to a career politician claiming to
be a “Washington outsider.”
Rand was entitled to formulate his own version of art history. For the majority of people, Rand’s claims
sound succinct, sensible and lyrical. This is due to the fact that they are concise bursts of received knowledge.
Everyone knows these things. It is, however, comforting to hear them intoned by the Oracle. If someone with his
stature lives by these beliefs, there must be something to them. Designers forget that design conferred his
stature, creating a self-reinforcing system. It also doesn’t hurt to write your own monograph.
Rand’s theories require review because of how they continue to shape the sensibilities of designers. In a
recent AIGA Journal article, Elizabeth Resnick describes the response of design students to a new film on Rand.
All show enthusiasm and admiration for his insistence that design is art. However, those students will become
even more marginalized and disenchanted with their work and status if they attempt to define themselves by
Rand’s fallacies. Omitted from his theories were the wholly subjective and situational-specific circumstances
surrounding the acceptance of his work. (That corporate America has turned to designers who are formally
antithetical to Rand was seen by him as evidence of a CEO dumb-down. What it actually demonstrates is that
the CEOs are shrewd enough to recognize how to utilize design styles to signal contemporiety. No matter how
aesthetically “correct,” business will junk design that doesn’t signify what consumers respond to.) Rather than
investing in the ideas of their times, the students accept inculcation into an illusory legacy.
Today, it is a common opinion of designers that everything went to hell with art in this century. For many
people, art of the last half-century has been progressively appalling. Art stopped being about the visual and
became ideas – masturbatory and ridiculous ones at that. Once the province of genius practitioners and
unquestioned aesthetics, academics hijacked art and stifled it under incomprehensible jargon. Artist-manqués
were only too happy to join the game.
There is merit in some of these arguments. Unfortunately, designers lack critical substance to expose any
conceit due to their fundamental misinterpretations of past art activity. Art has always been about ideas. It is
designers who focus on the visual nature of the works and assume the surface is what art’s about. As Dave
Hickey says, “Junior professors (!) began explaining to me that non-portable, non-object art had arisen during
the nineteen sixties as a means of ‘conceptualizing’ the practice of art in response to ‘commodification’ and the
‘commercialization’ of the art object during the postwar era. This would have been a wonderful argument if a
painting by Edward Ruscha or Jean-Louis David were any less ‘conceptual’ than a pile of dirt on the museum
floor….”
The complex iconography that makes up so many great paintings was the incomprehensible artspeak of
yesterday. If you hold that art of earlier times was “about” the visual aspect, all painting is ruined.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 30
play the role of art appreciator. When presented with what we recognize as an art appreciation situation
(almost exclusively the gallery or museum), we know to adopt the art viewer role and anticipate the art ex-
perience. A great work of art is one that best meets our anticipation of what an artwork should be. The rigidity
or flexibility of our expectations determines what we will consider art. The inherent nature of the work is, at
best, secondary.
Our reaction to art is hardly spontaneous – culture instills it. That art exists is a teaching of culture. We
respond as a result of training. The profundity of our reaction depends upon how seriously we take our role.
Everything we today regard as art – whether it be a Renoir or a Koons – was once non-art and was rationalized
into the definition.
Art is also purported to be our vanguard of culture and a vital experience. As prevalent the belief is that art
anticipates culture, little evidence can be found as proof. Art objects may be catalysts for and products of
social change. However, all artifacts of our material culture possess these qualities.
The means by which art enlivens existence are a matter of faith. Billions of people have and continue to live
without exposure to anything considered art and are no worse for it. A better case may be made that the ex-
perience of art is detrimental. It either proposes an unobtainable fantasy or twists the mundane into
distressing phantasmagoria. Assuming, that is, you are able to comprehend the work. And, of course, there’s
always a bottom line. If you get addicted and want to possess some art, the costs are exorbitant. Is it
expensive because it’s art or art because it’s expensive?
Then there’s the disturbance of interacting with artists. Certainly, no one can claim the makers of art are de
facto a saintly breed. The popular conception insists just the opposite. One of the most bizarre and insupport-
able contentions of our culture is that only reprehensible persons have the ability to generate the art ex-
perience. Though possessed of a self-image as exemplary humans, artists are no better than most, likely worse
on average. And in their emulation of artists, designers adopt their most offensive traits. They regularly fuse
aesthetic superciliousness with an arrogance born of considering themselves masters of their profession. In art
as in design, this conceited attitude likely compensates for a bitter realization. Society considers their activity
a marginal, self-indulgent pursuit. Artists receive adoration from the greater public only in the abstract.
BE REGULAR AND ORDERLY IN YOUR LIFE…
SO THAT YOU MAY BE VIOLENT AND ORIGINAL IN YOUR WORK.
Gustave Flaubert
THE DESIGNERS’ ART
Designers consider themselves creatively aware and often study within art programs. However, designers are no
more in touch with art than your average Joan. When designers talk about art they rarely deal with the reality
of contemporary art practice or theory. The art of the past seems a more commodious area to opine in.
However, comfort doesn’t bring clarity. Misinterpretation and misrepresentation are common when designers
engage past activity. Art is rarely looked at rationally. The people, process and product all become
romanticized.
When referring to art, designers usually settle in one of two historical eras. For those of a more traditional
bent, nothing seems to have happened in art – or be worthy of attention – since about 1940. The more
progressive-minded designers will, however, accept up to 1955. What often distinguishes a conservative from a
progressive designer is which outmoded conception of art they prefer. Art after 1960 is largely ignored, even
though conceptually, it’s more interesting for designers.
The former, larger group of designers see art as high aesthetic activity. The lineage that Paul Rand created
in his books were classic demonstrations of this model. Art is artifacts of transcendent genius that stir
profound emotion in the human soul. A masterly manipulation of formal elements moves these artifacts to a
rarefied plane. Only the finest of design may claim this level of achievement, though all should aspire to it. The
requirement is awareness of and strict adherence to aesthetic rules consistent throughout history.
This model is no more arguable than any that has evolved since. However, the fact is that it is historically
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 31
backward and archaic. Rather than responding to the critiques of their models – in other words, recognizing
any of the art made in the latter half of this century – Rand and his followers dismiss them. Their neglect of art
begins at about the time when Dwiggins coins the term “graphic design.” It’s almost as if the birth of design
meant the end of art. Or that design is heir to the true, historical art.
“To poke fun at form or formalism is to poke fun at… the philosophy called aesthetics,” Rand wrote in his
essay “From Cassandra to Chaos.” The problem is, art had been debunking aesthetics his entire adult life. In his
books, Rand referenced outdated doctrines, peppered his text with quotes yanked out of context, and
constructed a philosophy ultimately dependent upon his status in his field. Only within design could you find
regard for these declarations.
Of course, Rand’s books were self-promotions. The theory’s ultimate end is creating a noble lineage into
which he inserts his work. Like David Carson’s The End of Print, these books theorize to self-aggrandize. An
objective, critical analysis is nowhere on the agenda. The art interpretations made by design-star
hagiographer Lewis Blackwell in David Carson’s name supervene Rand’s in shallowness and distortion. Both
theorize from surface readings. Carson considers his work as having “similarity” with “Outsider Art/Art Brut” in
2nd Sight. The statement sounds learned but is more empty romanticism. Ignored, as always, are the quite
separate historic, intellectual and cultural circumstances that brought these artistic conceits into fashion.
The former construction, “outsider art,” is a self-negating term (if it’s outside art, it’s not art) which
denigrates, not celebrates, the activity. Carson’s “outsider” stance is similar to a career politician claiming to
be a “Washington outsider.”
Rand was entitled to formulate his own version of art history. For the majority of people, Rand’s claims
sound succinct, sensible and lyrical. This is due to the fact that they are concise bursts of received knowledge.
Everyone knows these things. It is, however, comforting to hear them intoned by the Oracle. If someone with his
stature lives by these beliefs, there must be something to them. Designers forget that design conferred his
stature, creating a self-reinforcing system. It also doesn’t hurt to write your own monograph.
Rand’s theories require review because of how they continue to shape the sensibilities of designers. In a
recent AIGA Journal article, Elizabeth Resnick describes the response of design students to a new film on Rand.
All show enthusiasm and admiration for his insistence that design is art. However, those students will become
even more marginalized and disenchanted with their work and status if they attempt to define themselves by
Rand’s fallacies. Omitted from his theories were the wholly subjective and situational-specific circumstances
surrounding the acceptance of his work. (That corporate America has turned to designers who are formally
antithetical to Rand was seen by him as evidence of a CEO dumb-down. What it actually demonstrates is that
the CEOs are shrewd enough to recognize how to utilize design styles to signal contemporiety. No matter how
aesthetically “correct,” business will junk design that doesn’t signify what consumers respond to.) Rather than
investing in the ideas of their times, the students accept inculcation into an illusory legacy.
Today, it is a common opinion of designers that everything went to hell with art in this century. For many
people, art of the last half-century has been progressively appalling. Art stopped being about the visual and
became ideas – masturbatory and ridiculous ones at that. Once the province of genius practitioners and
unquestioned aesthetics, academics hijacked art and stifled it under incomprehensible jargon. Artist-manqués
were only too happy to join the game.
There is merit in some of these arguments. Unfortunately, designers lack critical substance to expose any
conceit due to their fundamental misinterpretations of past art activity. Art has always been about ideas. It is
designers who focus on the visual nature of the works and assume the surface is what art’s about. As Dave
Hickey says, “Junior professors (!) began explaining to me that non-portable, non-object art had arisen during
the nineteen sixties as a means of ‘conceptualizing’ the practice of art in response to ‘commodification’ and the
‘commercialization’ of the art object during the postwar era. This would have been a wonderful argument if a
painting by Edward Ruscha or Jean-Louis David were any less ‘conceptual’ than a pile of dirt on the museum
floor….”
The complex iconography that makes up so many great paintings was the incomprehensible artspeak of
yesterday. If you hold that art of earlier times was “about” the visual aspect, all painting is ruined.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 30
play the role of art appreciator. When presented with what we recognize as an art appreciation situation
(almost exclusively the gallery or museum), we know to adopt the art viewer role and anticipate the art ex-
perience. A great work of art is one that best meets our anticipation of what an artwork should be. The rigidity
or flexibility of our expectations determines what we will consider art. The inherent nature of the work is, at
best, secondary.
Our reaction to art is hardly spontaneous – culture instills it. That art exists is a teaching of culture. We
respond as a result of training. The profundity of our reaction depends upon how seriously we take our role.
Everything we today regard as art – whether it be a Renoir or a Koons – was once non-art and was rationalized
into the definition.
Art is also purported to be our vanguard of culture and a vital experience. As prevalent the belief is that art
anticipates culture, little evidence can be found as proof. Art objects may be catalysts for and products of
social change. However, all artifacts of our material culture possess these qualities.
The means by which art enlivens existence are a matter of faith. Billions of people have and continue to live
without exposure to anything considered art and are no worse for it. A better case may be made that the ex-
perience of art is detrimental. It either proposes an unobtainable fantasy or twists the mundane into
distressing phantasmagoria. Assuming, that is, you are able to comprehend the work. And, of course, there’s
always a bottom line. If you get addicted and want to possess some art, the costs are exorbitant. Is it
expensive because it’s art or art because it’s expensive?
Then there’s the disturbance of interacting with artists. Certainly, no one can claim the makers of art are de
facto a saintly breed. The popular conception insists just the opposite. One of the most bizarre and insupport-
able contentions of our culture is that only reprehensible persons have the ability to generate the art ex-
perience. Though possessed of a self-image as exemplary humans, artists are no better than most, likely worse
on average. And in their emulation of artists, designers adopt their most offensive traits. They regularly fuse
aesthetic superciliousness with an arrogance born of considering themselves masters of their profession. In art
as in design, this conceited attitude likely compensates for a bitter realization. Society considers their activity
a marginal, self-indulgent pursuit. Artists receive adoration from the greater public only in the abstract.
BE REGULAR AND ORDERLY IN YOUR LIFE…
SO THAT YOU MAY BE VIOLENT AND ORIGINAL IN YOUR WORK.
Gustave Flaubert
THE DESIGNERS’ ART
Designers consider themselves creatively aware and often study within art programs. However, designers are no
more in touch with art than your average Joan. When designers talk about art they rarely deal with the reality
of contemporary art practice or theory. The art of the past seems a more commodious area to opine in.
However, comfort doesn’t bring clarity. Misinterpretation and misrepresentation are common when designers
engage past activity. Art is rarely looked at rationally. The people, process and product all become
romanticized.
When referring to art, designers usually settle in one of two historical eras. For those of a more traditional
bent, nothing seems to have happened in art – or be worthy of attention – since about 1940. The more
progressive-minded designers will, however, accept up to 1955. What often distinguishes a conservative from a
progressive designer is which outmoded conception of art they prefer. Art after 1960 is largely ignored, even
though conceptually, it’s more interesting for designers.
The former, larger group of designers see art as high aesthetic activity. The lineage that Paul Rand created
in his books were classic demonstrations of this model. Art is artifacts of transcendent genius that stir
profound emotion in the human soul. A masterly manipulation of formal elements moves these artifacts to a
rarefied plane. Only the finest of design may claim this level of achievement, though all should aspire to it. The
requirement is awareness of and strict adherence to aesthetic rules consistent throughout history.
This model is no more arguable than any that has evolved since. However, the fact is that it is historically
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 33
THE BIG EXPRESS
The ultimate artistic license is personal expression. Designers will be forever distinct from artists because they
must present someone else’s message. To free themselves from corporate/modernist shackles, designers strive
to inject their own personality into their work.
At this year’s Fuse98 conference, Erik Spiekermann received a round of applause for stating he designed to
solve his clients’ problems, not his own. He offered the comment while reviewing presentations by other
designers whose speculative nature he saw as bordering on the artistic. (“Artistic” meaning, in this context,
impractical and useless.)
On the latter side, Lewis Blackwell again imparts David Carson with the legacy of the rebel Americans.
In 2nd Sight, Blackwell explains of Carson, “He doesn’t go to a psychoanalyst to express himself – he designs.”
Here Blackwell attempts to link Carson with Big Art while disparaging critics who have read something other
than The End of Print. Of course, Pollock painted and went to the psychoanalyst.
This idea of self-expressiveness permeates design’s conception of art. Within art, dispute of the rhetoric of
expressionism came soon after its inception. Once more, design seems bent on rearguing constructs art moved
beyond decades ago.
In The Expressive Fallacy, Hal Foster demonstrates expressionism to be just another fabrication.
“(E)xpressionism is a paradox: a type of representation that asserts presence – of the artist, of the real. This
presence is by proxy only (the expressive marks of the artist, the indexical traces of the hand), and yet it is easy
to fall into the fallacy: for example, we commonly say an expressionist like Kandinsky ‘broke through’
representation, when in fact he replaced (or superimposed) one form with another – a representation oriented
not to reality (the coded, realist outer world) but to expression (the coded, symbolist inner world). After all,
formlessness does not dissolve convention or suspend mediation; as the expressionist trope for feeling, it is a
rhetorical form too.”
As examples of the artistic reaction against expressionism, Foster details a succession of painters beginning
with Jasper Johns (Target with Plaster Casts) in 1955, to Roy Lichtenstein (his brushstroke paintings), and,
more recently, Gerhard Richter. In other art media, self-expression acts primarily as a conceit to work against.
As we draw closer to contemporary times, artwork in form and concerns move closer to design, and, finally, art
must coexist with design to have import. Foster cites Jenny Holzer and Peter Nadin’s artist book Eating Friends,
which “debunks” expression with a literal obsession with “inner life”: texts and images (the stuff graphic
design is made of), focusing on internal organs.
Still, designers regularly travel extended rhetorical distances in form to arrive at art. Usually, designers
aspire to painting – the traditional art medium. Frequently, designers express a desire to “paint with type.”
The implication is of scattering letterforms as expressively and directly as Pollock splattered enamel on
canvas. However, as Foster points out above, the process of abstract painters is just as intentional as
representational painters. The gestural, immediate style of painting is merely a point in the artistic continuum.
Deliberate, systematized painting routines – ones that resemble common typographical practice – have been
the dominant method. If you can’t find a painting approach that matches your design process, you haven’t
looked hard enough. The aspiration to type-paint is less a desired working method than another longing for
artistic legitimacy.
Self-expression stands as another attempt to signify truth through formal means alone. For design, however,
the effort is ironic. Expressionism long ago became a language appropriated by consumer culture. As Foster
suggests, “…we must open up (expressionism) to include the expressionist rhetoric of psychology and
consumerist society in general. Express yourself, we are exhorted – but only via the type, only via the
commodity.” Striving to elude “commodification” through self-expression, designers charge headfirst into its
maw. Meanwhile, the expressionist desire to create a public, formal language was likely usurped by design.
Culture has for a time defined itself through mass media: the realm of design.
The point being made here is not that one must be absolutely contemporary in their art metaphors. The past
should be neither venerated nor rejected. The issue is that designers continue to work from a romantic ideal of
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 32
Design can only suffer in comparison to this popular construction of High Art. The ideal is unattainable not
because of a designer’s cupidity, indifference, or hack status. It’s because the artist ideal is wholly fictional.
The closer you examine art activity, the more diverse a behavior it becomes. If it resembles any contemporary
activity, it’s design.
HE HAD NEVER REALIZED THAT HE HAD PRODUCED QUITE THIS MANY THINGS.
WHY, SOME PEOPLE MIGHT CONSIDER HIM AN ACTUAL ARTIST, BY PROFESSION. WAS
THAT POSSIBLE? HE PICTURED ALL THOSE HOURS SPENT ALONE IN HIS ROOM,
PATIENTLY FITTING TOGETHER TINY SCRAPS, FEVERISHLY HUNTING UP THE PROPER
TEXTURES, POUNDING IN A ROW OF THUMBTACKS UNTIL THE BACK OF HIS NECK ACHED
– ALL THAT DRUDGERY. IT WASN’T THE WAY HE PICTURED THE LIFE OF AN ARTIST.
Anne Tyler, Celestial Navigation
THE ARCHETYPE-CAST
The artist beau ideal is that of a loner pursuing a personal agenda. Design is said to be different because
of its collaborative nature. Often, a team accomplishes design projects. Credit usually goes to the principal
designer, of course, obscuring the process. The determination to produce under one person’s name
(e.g., Kenneth FitzGerald Design) intends to appropriate the artist’s cultural authority. When a designer
stresses that they are a “one-person shop,” the intimation is one of greater creative distinction – working like,
being, an artist.
The fact is that most artists past and present operated as a firm. For hundreds of years, artists apprenticed
in shops, working under masters. Whether it was painting portraits, frescoes or blacksmithing, you weren’t
working alone. The goal was to set up your own shop then make your underlings do things your way. Rather than
temples of individual attainment, museums are show houses of art direction. The Rembrandt Project – the
ongoing research effort to identify “authentic” paintings by the master – displays the normative situation, not
an aberration. “The Great Masters” was a collection of schools; art firms directed by principals. The
devaluation of works only partially executed by Rembrandt speaks more to our culture’s skewed values than
the paintings’ intrinsic worth.
Social and cultural changes did occasion a more specialized art commodity provider. These individuals
desired a higher social status, as did the purchasers of their wares. From here, the art idea as we know it began
to form. However, the lone genius remains the exception. It’s almost a truism that to find an artist working
alone in a garret was (and is) to find a failure. Today’s major-selling fine artist is still regularly a company in
every way. Assistants fabricate the bulk, if not the entirety, of pieces. They stretch the canvas, paint the
content, then wash the Range Rover. It’s a plum job for aspiring artists, and has been for centuries.
In process, art is like design is like fashion is like scientific research is like most human activity: the labor of
many to the glorification of one. The solitary creator myth, however, still dominates inside and out of the art
world. I remember my disdain when, as an art school undergraduate, I first read of an artist’s assistants. This
pseudo-revelation is regularly roto-tilled up by the popular media as an exposé of contemporary art avarice
and hypocrisy. My naïveté resulted from the reinforcing art school indoctrination and a wholly visual definition
of art activity. The dissimulation lies with our culture. We demand mass commodities with the aura of
exclusivity.
Alternating, and often mixed, with the Great Master model is one inspired by the heroic artists of abstract
expressionism: Pollock, de Kooning. These American (native or adopted) painters wrested the art world from
European dominance in the 1950s. Combined with the lust-for-life archetype of the late 19th century (Van
Gogh, Gaugin, et al.), the artist became a tormented soul. Art now was an intensely personal self-investigation
of the psyche. Artists make art to purge their demons. It is a representation shared widely within our culture,
though the movement was brief and problematic. Designers, for all their claims of practicality, buy into the
romance. They either play against it to assert their creative sobriety, or conjure its spirit to siphon off
artistic aura.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 33
THE BIG EXPRESS
The ultimate artistic license is personal expression. Designers will be forever distinct from artists because they
must present someone else’s message. To free themselves from corporate/modernist shackles, designers strive
to inject their own personality into their work.
At this year’s Fuse98 conference, Erik Spiekermann received a round of applause for stating he designed to
solve his clients’ problems, not his own. He offered the comment while reviewing presentations by other
designers whose speculative nature he saw as bordering on the artistic. (“Artistic” meaning, in this context,
impractical and useless.)
On the latter side, Lewis Blackwell again imparts David Carson with the legacy of the rebel Americans.
In 2nd Sight, Blackwell explains of Carson, “He doesn’t go to a psychoanalyst to express himself – he designs.”
Here Blackwell attempts to link Carson with Big Art while disparaging critics who have read something other
than The End of Print. Of course, Pollock painted and went to the psychoanalyst.
This idea of self-expressiveness permeates design’s conception of art. Within art, dispute of the rhetoric of
expressionism came soon after its inception. Once more, design seems bent on rearguing constructs art moved
beyond decades ago.
In The Expressive Fallacy, Hal Foster demonstrates expressionism to be just another fabrication.
“(E)xpressionism is a paradox: a type of representation that asserts presence – of the artist, of the real. This
presence is by proxy only (the expressive marks of the artist, the indexical traces of the hand), and yet it is easy
to fall into the fallacy: for example, we commonly say an expressionist like Kandinsky ‘broke through’
representation, when in fact he replaced (or superimposed) one form with another – a representation oriented
not to reality (the coded, realist outer world) but to expression (the coded, symbolist inner world). After all,
formlessness does not dissolve convention or suspend mediation; as the expressionist trope for feeling, it is a
rhetorical form too.”
As examples of the artistic reaction against expressionism, Foster details a succession of painters beginning
with Jasper Johns (Target with Plaster Casts) in 1955, to Roy Lichtenstein (his brushstroke paintings), and,
more recently, Gerhard Richter. In other art media, self-expression acts primarily as a conceit to work against.
As we draw closer to contemporary times, artwork in form and concerns move closer to design, and, finally, art
must coexist with design to have import. Foster cites Jenny Holzer and Peter Nadin’s artist book Eating Friends,
which “debunks” expression with a literal obsession with “inner life”: texts and images (the stuff graphic
design is made of), focusing on internal organs.
Still, designers regularly travel extended rhetorical distances in form to arrive at art. Usually, designers
aspire to painting – the traditional art medium. Frequently, designers express a desire to “paint with type.”
The implication is of scattering letterforms as expressively and directly as Pollock splattered enamel on
canvas. However, as Foster points out above, the process of abstract painters is just as intentional as
representational painters. The gestural, immediate style of painting is merely a point in the artistic continuum.
Deliberate, systematized painting routines – ones that resemble common typographical practice – have been
the dominant method. If you can’t find a painting approach that matches your design process, you haven’t
looked hard enough. The aspiration to type-paint is less a desired working method than another longing for
artistic legitimacy.
Self-expression stands as another attempt to signify truth through formal means alone. For design, however,
the effort is ironic. Expressionism long ago became a language appropriated by consumer culture. As Foster
suggests, “…we must open up (expressionism) to include the expressionist rhetoric of psychology and
consumerist society in general. Express yourself, we are exhorted – but only via the type, only via the
commodity.” Striving to elude “commodification” through self-expression, designers charge headfirst into its
maw. Meanwhile, the expressionist desire to create a public, formal language was likely usurped by design.
Culture has for a time defined itself through mass media: the realm of design.
The point being made here is not that one must be absolutely contemporary in their art metaphors. The past
should be neither venerated nor rejected. The issue is that designers continue to work from a romantic ideal of
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 32
Design can only suffer in comparison to this popular construction of High Art. The ideal is unattainable not
because of a designer’s cupidity, indifference, or hack status. It’s because the artist ideal is wholly fictional.
The closer you examine art activity, the more diverse a behavior it becomes. If it resembles any contemporary
activity, it’s design.
HE HAD NEVER REALIZED THAT HE HAD PRODUCED QUITE THIS MANY THINGS.
WHY, SOME PEOPLE MIGHT CONSIDER HIM AN ACTUAL ARTIST, BY PROFESSION. WAS
THAT POSSIBLE? HE PICTURED ALL THOSE HOURS SPENT ALONE IN HIS ROOM,
PATIENTLY FITTING TOGETHER TINY SCRAPS, FEVERISHLY HUNTING UP THE PROPER
TEXTURES, POUNDING IN A ROW OF THUMBTACKS UNTIL THE BACK OF HIS NECK ACHED
– ALL THAT DRUDGERY. IT WASN’T THE WAY HE PICTURED THE LIFE OF AN ARTIST.
Anne Tyler, Celestial Navigation
THE ARCHETYPE-CAST
The artist beau ideal is that of a loner pursuing a personal agenda. Design is said to be different because
of its collaborative nature. Often, a team accomplishes design projects. Credit usually goes to the principal
designer, of course, obscuring the process. The determination to produce under one person’s name
(e.g., Kenneth FitzGerald Design) intends to appropriate the artist’s cultural authority. When a designer
stresses that they are a “one-person shop,” the intimation is one of greater creative distinction – working like,
being, an artist.
The fact is that most artists past and present operated as a firm. For hundreds of years, artists apprenticed
in shops, working under masters. Whether it was painting portraits, frescoes or blacksmithing, you weren’t
working alone. The goal was to set up your own shop then make your underlings do things your way. Rather than
temples of individual attainment, museums are show houses of art direction. The Rembrandt Project – the
ongoing research effort to identify “authentic” paintings by the master – displays the normative situation, not
an aberration. “The Great Masters” was a collection of schools; art firms directed by principals. The
devaluation of works only partially executed by Rembrandt speaks more to our culture’s skewed values than
the paintings’ intrinsic worth.
Social and cultural changes did occasion a more specialized art commodity provider. These individuals
desired a higher social status, as did the purchasers of their wares. From here, the art idea as we know it began
to form. However, the lone genius remains the exception. It’s almost a truism that to find an artist working
alone in a garret was (and is) to find a failure. Today’s major-selling fine artist is still regularly a company in
every way. Assistants fabricate the bulk, if not the entirety, of pieces. They stretch the canvas, paint the
content, then wash the Range Rover. It’s a plum job for aspiring artists, and has been for centuries.
In process, art is like design is like fashion is like scientific research is like most human activity: the labor of
many to the glorification of one. The solitary creator myth, however, still dominates inside and out of the art
world. I remember my disdain when, as an art school undergraduate, I first read of an artist’s assistants. This
pseudo-revelation is regularly roto-tilled up by the popular media as an exposé of contemporary art avarice
and hypocrisy. My naïveté resulted from the reinforcing art school indoctrination and a wholly visual definition
of art activity. The dissimulation lies with our culture. We demand mass commodities with the aura of
exclusivity.
Alternating, and often mixed, with the Great Master model is one inspired by the heroic artists of abstract
expressionism: Pollock, de Kooning. These American (native or adopted) painters wrested the art world from
European dominance in the 1950s. Combined with the lust-for-life archetype of the late 19th century (Van
Gogh, Gaugin, et al.), the artist became a tormented soul. Art now was an intensely personal self-investigation
of the psyche. Artists make art to purge their demons. It is a representation shared widely within our culture,
though the movement was brief and problematic. Designers, for all their claims of practicality, buy into the
romance. They either play against it to assert their creative sobriety, or conjure its spirit to siphon off
artistic aura.
E M I G R E # 7 0 : T H E L O O K B A C K I S S U E | 8 | 1 9 9 8E M I G R E # 7 0 : T H E L O O K B A C K I S S U E | 7 | 1 9 9 8
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 35
neutral grid, the gallery is an ideological space – and receptive to commerce. Willingly complicit is the artist.
O’Doherty writes, “The economic model in place for a hundred years…is product, filtered through galleries,
offered to collectors and public institutions, written about in magazines partially supported by the galleries,
and drifting towards the academic apparatus that stabilizes ‘history’ – certifying much as banks do, the holding
of its major repository, the museum. History in art is, ultimately, worth money. Thus do we get not the art we
deserve but the art we pay for. This comfortable system went virtually unquestioned by the key figure it is based
upon: the artist.” All art is in the marketplace. It must be to be considered art; its validating establishment
resides there.
The fiction of the artist as victim of these forces – and not devoted accessory – is a component of the
modernist construction of the avant-garde. To command authority, artists must claim a privileged status in
society. They must be above crass commercialism and defend culture. Art must be kept pure. But someone must
take the fall. That would be designers.
Nevertheless, a look at the most prominent art stars shows individuals responding to markets and making no
(or little) pretense to making commodities. To afford his epic Cremaster videos, Matthew Barney has to up-
front please people with money. Damien Hirst conceived floating a shark in a tank of formaldehyde but it took
the financing of a Saatchi to do it. The Physical Impossibility of Death in the Mind of Someone Living is as much
a brochure for its patron as was the Mona Lisa for whoever commissioned that vanity item. Commissioning a
work of art has historically been a public declaration of virtue and wealth. Why is it different if your claimed
virtue is the making of a beverage?
AN ARTIST’S DESIGN
It isn’t necessary to detail the scorn most artists have for designers. In an interview in Emigre #46, the
designers of Orangeflux relate a typical story of artists dismissing their work: “…when we show Rust Belt with-
in the art community they tell us it’s not art, it’s design. They can’t see beyond the type.” The ongoing
marginalization of fine artists in our culture drives their determination to keep designers in a lower status.
These are attitudes within the arts deserving mention. They relate to the way design dispels certain works as
not being design but art. In keeping with its art schizophrenia, design can’t decide if having your work called
art is condemnation or acclaim. It depends, of course, if you respect the designer or not.
As Orangeflux learned, the art world is not a commodious place for daring designers. The work condemned
as art by designers is a non-starter for artists. Art industrialists who champion the most difficult, challenging
art become obstinate conventionalists in their design concerns. For every Walker Art Center, there’s one
hundred museums that can’t get enough 12 pt. Helvetica. The preferred exhibition announcement is a template
design: color photo of the art piece on the front (always white bordered, like a frame, so you know it isn’t just a
design) and easy to read centered type (Helvetica, Gill, Garamond) on the back. To violate this design space is
like stepping outside the gallery, which the card emulates. You risk not being taken seriously.
At a presentation to fine art graduate students, I garnered the expected response to contemporary
“cutting-edge” design. The reaction to the art school publications I brought for the students’ appraisal –
P. Scott Makela’s Minnesota College of Art & Design catalogs, ReVerb’s Otis and CalArts works – was almost
uniform. They regarded the publications as incomprehensible indulgences that failed to meet their
fundamental purpose. Students expressed their opinions with a startling passion. They recoiled from a repre-
sentational disturbance they assiduously cultivated in their own work.
It’s only slightly ironic that artists are the most vehement defenders of conservative design. Design is
different, they’ll say, it’s about relaying facts, information. It’s about communication. Though this would seem
to be a harsh judgment on art – that it is uncommunicative – it certainly proves true. Arguably, art isn’t about
communication – at least, no more than design is.
Artists thrive on the avant-garde notion that it is their role to critique and experiment with cultural forms.
A designer investigating these ideas is an offense against sensibility, against the cultural order. Artists don’t
like this view contested as it leads to prying apart desperately held illusions of relevance.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 34
art. Rather than construct a relevant model for their activity, designers orbit a hoary salon.
Unfortunately, when art isn’t romanticized, design treats it as visual supermarket. Designers unashamedly
investigate art because it offers many graphic ideas to purloin. Design becomes a process of raising movie-set
facades behind which business is conducted.
FILTHY LUCRATIVE
What are the essential, irrefutable particulars separating design from art? People go into design to make
money. Designers prostitute art for business. Designers work for clients, artists work for themselves.
These clichés hold up as well as the other aspects of the art myth. It is a delusion that the activity of fine
artists is divorced from commercial considerations. It isn’t even a matter of degree. All that separates art and
design is the kind of marketplace one chooses to operate in. The direct evidence of this is the art world’s
obsession with sales. No matter how “conceptual” or “non-object” oriented, art can and must be sold.
Economic viability is the preeminent determinant.
The traditional estimation holds that designers are dependent upon having clients and are subservient to
their will. Artists, however, are self-starters who answer only to their muse. To believe this, you must disregard
admissions committees, art faculty, review boards, competition jurors, selection committees, gallery owners,
curators, critics, grant committees, opening attendees, et al. Each of these groups has a profound and often
direct influence on how and what art is made. For artists, these encounters are client meetings. Artists
frequently modify how they make and present their work in the wake of feedback from these groups. The input
of knowledgeable art insiders is craved, not scorned.
The notion that art is an “anything-goes” zone is misinformed. Straying too far from well-delineated
boundaries is hazardous for artists. The field is broad, but often shallow. To gain recognition as an artist, it is
incumbent to exhibit regularly in approved forums. Critical recognition requires first being seen. This means
you must please people, particularly, gallery owners. If they are to be at all successful, gallery owners must
make a basic economic decision about art. Will it sell?
Sales are evidently not a requirement to be an artist. If it was, we must remove the majority of practitioners
from the canon. The large number of artists successful in their time but ignored in contemporary estimation
complicates the situation. Unless we are ready to accept that unseen creations are artworks (just as anything
done in type and image can be design), we must acknowledge that art is mediated by forces exterior to the
artist. Every artist must face the reality that the surest way for their labor to be considered art is to attach a
high price tag to it.
Historically, artworks have always functioned as commodities. Finding clients has concerned artists
throughout history. Jacques-Louis David resented having to accept portrait commissions. The historic epics he
preferred to paint, however, couldn’t find a clientele. Art was born of the marketplace, as was design. Design
was merely a new product line.
Brian O’Doherty takes a scathing look at the “art industry” in Inside the White Cube: The Ideology of the
Gallery Space. The gallery is a showroom floor, displaying manufacturers’ latest models. “For many of us, the
gallery space still gives off negative vibrations when we wander in. Esthetics is turned into a kind of social
elitism – the gallery space is exclusive. Isolated in plots of space, what is on display looks a bit like valuable
scarce goods, jewelry, or silver: esthetics are turned into commerce – the gallery space is expensive. What it
contains is, without mediation, well-nigh incomprehensible – art is difficult. Exclusive audience, rare objects
difficult to comprehend – here we have a social, financial, and intellectual snobbery which models (and at its
worst parodies) our system of limited production, our modes of assigning values, our social habits at large.
Never was a space, designed to accommodate the prejudices and enhance the self-image of the upper middle
classes, so efficiently codified.
“The classic modernist gallery is the limbo between studio and living room, where the conventions of both
meet on a carefully neutralized ground. There the artist’s respect for what he has invented is perfectly super-
imposed on the bourgeois desire for possession. For a gallery is, in the end, a place to sell things – which is O.K.”
The modernist gallery didn’t transform art into commodity. It was always in that state. Like the illusory
E M I G R E # 7 0 : T H E L O O K B A C K I S S U E | 8 | 1 9 9 8E M I G R E # 7 0 : T H E L O O K B A C K I S S U E | 7 | 1 9 9 8
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 35
neutral grid, the gallery is an ideological space – and receptive to commerce. Willingly complicit is the artist.
O’Doherty writes, “The economic model in place for a hundred years…is product, filtered through galleries,
offered to collectors and public institutions, written about in magazines partially supported by the galleries,
and drifting towards the academic apparatus that stabilizes ‘history’ – certifying much as banks do, the holding
of its major repository, the museum. History in art is, ultimately, worth money. Thus do we get not the art we
deserve but the art we pay for. This comfortable system went virtually unquestioned by the key figure it is based
upon: the artist.” All art is in the marketplace. It must be to be considered art; its validating establishment
resides there.
The fiction of the artist as victim of these forces – and not devoted accessory – is a component of the
modernist construction of the avant-garde. To command authority, artists must claim a privileged status in
society. They must be above crass commercialism and defend culture. Art must be kept pure. But someone must
take the fall. That would be designers.
Nevertheless, a look at the most prominent art stars shows individuals responding to markets and making no
(or little) pretense to making commodities. To afford his epic Cremaster videos, Matthew Barney has to up-
front please people with money. Damien Hirst conceived floating a shark in a tank of formaldehyde but it took
the financing of a Saatchi to do it. The Physical Impossibility of Death in the Mind of Someone Living is as much
a brochure for its patron as was the Mona Lisa for whoever commissioned that vanity item. Commissioning a
work of art has historically been a public declaration of virtue and wealth. Why is it different if your claimed
virtue is the making of a beverage?
AN ARTIST’S DESIGN
It isn’t necessary to detail the scorn most artists have for designers. In an interview in Emigre #46, the
designers of Orangeflux relate a typical story of artists dismissing their work: “…when we show Rust Belt with-
in the art community they tell us it’s not art, it’s design. They can’t see beyond the type.” The ongoing
marginalization of fine artists in our culture drives their determination to keep designers in a lower status.
These are attitudes within the arts deserving mention. They relate to the way design dispels certain works as
not being design but art. In keeping with its art schizophrenia, design can’t decide if having your work called
art is condemnation or acclaim. It depends, of course, if you respect the designer or not.
As Orangeflux learned, the art world is not a commodious place for daring designers. The work condemned
as art by designers is a non-starter for artists. Art industrialists who champion the most difficult, challenging
art become obstinate conventionalists in their design concerns. For every Walker Art Center, there’s one
hundred museums that can’t get enough 12 pt. Helvetica. The preferred exhibition announcement is a template
design: color photo of the art piece on the front (always white bordered, like a frame, so you know it isn’t just a
design) and easy to read centered type (Helvetica, Gill, Garamond) on the back. To violate this design space is
like stepping outside the gallery, which the card emulates. You risk not being taken seriously.
At a presentation to fine art graduate students, I garnered the expected response to contemporary
“cutting-edge” design. The reaction to the art school publications I brought for the students’ appraisal –
P. Scott Makela’s Minnesota College of Art & Design catalogs, ReVerb’s Otis and CalArts works – was almost
uniform. They regarded the publications as incomprehensible indulgences that failed to meet their
fundamental purpose. Students expressed their opinions with a startling passion. They recoiled from a repre-
sentational disturbance they assiduously cultivated in their own work.
It’s only slightly ironic that artists are the most vehement defenders of conservative design. Design is
different, they’ll say, it’s about relaying facts, information. It’s about communication. Though this would seem
to be a harsh judgment on art – that it is uncommunicative – it certainly proves true. Arguably, art isn’t about
communication – at least, no more than design is.
Artists thrive on the avant-garde notion that it is their role to critique and experiment with cultural forms.
A designer investigating these ideas is an offense against sensibility, against the cultural order. Artists don’t
like this view contested as it leads to prying apart desperately held illusions of relevance.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 34
art. Rather than construct a relevant model for their activity, designers orbit a hoary salon.
Unfortunately, when art isn’t romanticized, design treats it as visual supermarket. Designers unashamedly
investigate art because it offers many graphic ideas to purloin. Design becomes a process of raising movie-set
facades behind which business is conducted.
FILTHY LUCRATIVE
What are the essential, irrefutable particulars separating design from art? People go into design to make
money. Designers prostitute art for business. Designers work for clients, artists work for themselves.
These clichés hold up as well as the other aspects of the art myth. It is a delusion that the activity of fine
artists is divorced from commercial considerations. It isn’t even a matter of degree. All that separates art and
design is the kind of marketplace one chooses to operate in. The direct evidence of this is the art world’s
obsession with sales. No matter how “conceptual” or “non-object” oriented, art can and must be sold.
Economic viability is the preeminent determinant.
The traditional estimation holds that designers are dependent upon having clients and are subservient to
their will. Artists, however, are self-starters who answer only to their muse. To believe this, you must disregard
admissions committees, art faculty, review boards, competition jurors, selection committees, gallery owners,
curators, critics, grant committees, opening attendees, et al. Each of these groups has a profound and often
direct influence on how and what art is made. For artists, these encounters are client meetings. Artists
frequently modify how they make and present their work in the wake of feedback from these groups. The input
of knowledgeable art insiders is craved, not scorned.
The notion that art is an “anything-goes” zone is misinformed. Straying too far from well-delineated
boundaries is hazardous for artists. The field is broad, but often shallow. To gain recognition as an artist, it is
incumbent to exhibit regularly in approved forums. Critical recognition requires first being seen. This means
you must please people, particularly, gallery owners. If they are to be at all successful, gallery owners must
make a basic economic decision about art. Will it sell?
Sales are evidently not a requirement to be an artist. If it was, we must remove the majority of practitioners
from the canon. The large number of artists successful in their time but ignored in contemporary estimation
complicates the situation. Unless we are ready to accept that unseen creations are artworks (just as anything
done in type and image can be design), we must acknowledge that art is mediated by forces exterior to the
artist. Every artist must face the reality that the surest way for their labor to be considered art is to attach a
high price tag to it.
Historically, artworks have always functioned as commodities. Finding clients has concerned artists
throughout history. Jacques-Louis David resented having to accept portrait commissions. The historic epics he
preferred to paint, however, couldn’t find a clientele. Art was born of the marketplace, as was design. Design
was merely a new product line.
Brian O’Doherty takes a scathing look at the “art industry” in Inside the White Cube: The Ideology of the
Gallery Space. The gallery is a showroom floor, displaying manufacturers’ latest models. “For many of us, the
gallery space still gives off negative vibrations when we wander in. Esthetics is turned into a kind of social
elitism – the gallery space is exclusive. Isolated in plots of space, what is on display looks a bit like valuable
scarce goods, jewelry, or silver: esthetics are turned into commerce – the gallery space is expensive. What it
contains is, without mediation, well-nigh incomprehensible – art is difficult. Exclusive audience, rare objects
difficult to comprehend – here we have a social, financial, and intellectual snobbery which models (and at its
worst parodies) our system of limited production, our modes of assigning values, our social habits at large.
Never was a space, designed to accommodate the prejudices and enhance the self-image of the upper middle
classes, so efficiently codified.
“The classic modernist gallery is the limbo between studio and living room, where the conventions of both
meet on a carefully neutralized ground. There the artist’s respect for what he has invented is perfectly super-
imposed on the bourgeois desire for possession. For a gallery is, in the end, a place to sell things – which is O.K.”
The modernist gallery didn’t transform art into commodity. It was always in that state. Like the illusory
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 37
profound insight on the relationship of art and design. In his article, Buchloh scrutinizes different artistic
strategies to “reject the idea of esthetic autonomy.” To accomplish this, artists have also needed to “…
abandon traditional procedures of artistic production (and, by implication, of course, the cognitive concepts
embedded in them).” To describe this process, Buchloh expands upon a term used by artist Ian Burn:
“deskilling.” Deskilling rejects “manual dexterity” as a principal component of art. To pursue traditional art
practices is to be caught up in their ideological adulteration. New practices with new skills must replace what
has been repudiated. First amongst these new skills is the ability to recognize that factographic forms are
culturally significant, intellectually substantive, and relate directly to the public.
In this way factography is identical to design. Buchloh echoes the rhetoric of design and its impact upon
audiences. The conception that there is an unmediated, objective visual language is still questioned. However,
we can recognize that particular forms popularly signify factuality and objectivity. This indicates a greater
potential for using “style” as signifier. Design work, however, is not universally factographic because of its
form. Design is popularly regarded as more ideologically corrupt than art, and most designers unabashedly
adopt the rhetoric and politics of their clients. Negotiating the problems and potential of design requires novel
skills indeed.
The Guerrilla Girls are other factographers design should make note of. This anonymous group of women
artists and art professionals have arguably made the only truly dangerous art of the past decade. Through a
remarkable series of mostly text-only handbills, the Guerrilla Girls have pointed up the gender and race bias of
the art world. (Like Barbara Kruger, their font of choice is Futura.) Once again, the most cutting and
substantive art uses design as its principal constituent.
Through these works, design demonstrates what Donald Preziosi calls a “carrying capacity” – the ability of a
study object to have art historical significance as a cultural artifact. It also confirms that design artifacts
require a much deeper reading.
Haacke’s influence has already paid significant dividends for graphic design. Ellen Lupton and J. Abbott
Miller studied with Haacke at Cooper Union. Their use of design as a fundamental element in their factography
refers to Haacke’s investigations.
ESTHETICS IS FOR ARTISTS AS ORNITHOLOGY IS FOR THE BIRDS.
Barnett Newman
THE PLEASURES OF THE VORTEXTURE
A cynical opinion about art theory is that its complexity and self-referentiality can justify anything. But rather
than shunning it, designers should investigate and elaborate.
Of course, the basis of art world regard is doctrinal adherence, not theoretical alignment. The goal shouldn’t
be gaining art world acceptance. Designers must add art’s material culture speculations to their data base – if
only to chart wrong directions.
Art is a recent construct historically. The notion of timeless objects being preserved through the centuries
because of their inherent quality is misguided. Art is all “presentism.” Much of what we value was a previous
generation’s excess. And who knows what was lost?
That there is an “art” phenomenon is still pure speculation. As stated by Donald Preziosi, art history has
not only described art, it has shaped it. Artists’ awareness of art history and subsequent desire to be part of
the canon has been the fundamental motivation for art making this century. All other rationales are secondary
at best.
Art history indoctrinates students into the art industry primarily through books and magazines. First-hand
experience of art is still rare and overshadowed by the preponderance of art publications. Artists become
artists because of what they see in print, not in a museum. Ed Ruscha’s determination to be an artist came
from seeing a reproduction of a Jasper Johns painting in Print magazine. For scores of artists, art is a small
repro (frequently in black and white) with an accompanying caption. Art became its representation almost
immediately upon birth. Concrete artifacts were but illustrations of concepts. This, of course, is the truth of all
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 36
FACTOGRAPHIC DESIGN
Design has directed attention to contemporary artists thought to have links with its practice. Barbara Kruger is
cited as a kind of designer-made-good. She’s often looked to for insight on design’s potential as a medium of
cultural commentary. While Kruger’s work is significant, its relevance for design is limited. Her works were
readily acknowledged as art, unlike the magazine layouts she briefly worked on. Acceptance of her work hasn’t
increased regard for design activity. Also, Kruger hardly utilizes the potential of the rhetoric of design. Though
she explored different typefaces in early works (and nothing controversial in design), she has stuck to an extra
bold Futura italic since. In this, she proves more discriminatory than Massimo Vignelli. Considering the
conservatism about design described previously, it may be that Kruger recognized what was unacceptable in
art. Being typographically challenging might prove professionally dangerous.
The artist Hans Haacke provides a crucial insight into the construction of art and design. Critical study of his
work highlights the artificiality of the art/design division. In their content and reception, Haacke’s
installations disclose the overriding commercial concerns of the art industry. By denying what he terms the
“trademark appearance of art,” Haacke constructs a relevant art by constituting it as design.
Haacke – a German-born artist who has resided in the U.S. since 1965 – has been one of the most
significantly controversial artists of the past two decades. (“Significantly” means that the controversies have
not centered on political distractions such as obscenity and flag-burning.) Originally allied with conceptual
art movements in the 1960s, he turned to a political art at the start of the 1970s. His works blandly document
“…the institutional, discursive and economic apparatuses of international high art….” Manipulating the
advertisements and collateral of multinational corporations, he exposes their connections to repression and
exploitation. Support for the arts serves as whitewash, not altruism. Art is implicated as another method of
control.
Censorship and cancellations mark Haacke’s exhibition career. Institutional discomfort with the works’
content motivated these actions. Elaborate circumlocutions attempted to draw attention away from
accusations of suppression. Haacke’s work was criticized for its lack of aesthetic pleasure and for being mere
journalism. Curiously, he employs strict (Swiss International Style) modernist design tools to attack modernist
ideals of “…esthetic autonomy and esthetic pleasure.”
Art historian and critic Benjamin Buchloh’s Hans Haacke: Memory and Instrumental Reason, is an important
analysis of the artist’s work and its ramifications not only for art, but our entire visual culture. Buchloh
believes Haacke’s work “…has in fact been marginalized because it represents a turning point – one of those
historical moments in which a set of assumptions about the structures and functions of art are being effectively
challenged (in a way that Heartfield’s work constituted such an instant in the 30s).” Like Heartfield’s, Haacke’s
work utilizes the forms of “commercial art,” using its language to critique society.
To categorize Haacke’s (and other like-minded artists’) work, Buchloh coined the term “factography.”
Factography is an art form that is motivated by a desire to expose economic and political powers manipulating
our society. Factography also attempts to escape and disrupt the corrupted art practices of the past. It takes
as its subject matter a neutral, documentary reportage of facts, such as statistics. This form is regarded
by the public as both participatory and immediate – no art education is required to comprehend its message.
Factography thus denies the typical aesthetic concerns of art and invites challenge as an art practice.
Haacke’s works frequently simulate corporate PR. Billboards and advertisements are restructured with
corporate design precision. Through these simulations, the photographic and textual inversions have great im-
pact. The bland straightforwardness becomes highly charged in ways a more adventurous design could not. An
infamous censored work, Manet-PROJECT ‘74, is chilling in its simplicity. The rejected installation would have
displayed a Manet painting with ten panels tracing the art work’s provenance. These panels, set in Times
Roman, resemble the ubiquitous head-shot/text bios of countless annual reports. (The work was rejected as its
ninth panel revealed “…a prominent figure in the economic establishment of the Nazi government…now
functions as a major cultural benefactor in the liberal democracy of postwar Germany.” )
Along with demonstrating the complexity of meanings attendant in design forms, Haacke’s work leads to a
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 37
profound insight on the relationship of art and design. In his article, Buchloh scrutinizes different artistic
strategies to “reject the idea of esthetic autonomy.” To accomplish this, artists have also needed to “…
abandon traditional procedures of artistic production (and, by implication, of course, the cognitive concepts
embedded in them).” To describe this process, Buchloh expands upon a term used by artist Ian Burn:
“deskilling.” Deskilling rejects “manual dexterity” as a principal component of art. To pursue traditional art
practices is to be caught up in their ideological adulteration. New practices with new skills must replace what
has been repudiated. First amongst these new skills is the ability to recognize that factographic forms are
culturally significant, intellectually substantive, and relate directly to the public.
In this way factography is identical to design. Buchloh echoes the rhetoric of design and its impact upon
audiences. The conception that there is an unmediated, objective visual language is still questioned. However,
we can recognize that particular forms popularly signify factuality and objectivity. This indicates a greater
potential for using “style” as signifier. Design work, however, is not universally factographic because of its
form. Design is popularly regarded as more ideologically corrupt than art, and most designers unabashedly
adopt the rhetoric and politics of their clients. Negotiating the problems and potential of design requires novel
skills indeed.
The Guerrilla Girls are other factographers design should make note of. This anonymous group of women
artists and art professionals have arguably made the only truly dangerous art of the past decade. Through a
remarkable series of mostly text-only handbills, the Guerrilla Girls have pointed up the gender and race bias of
the art world. (Like Barbara Kruger, their font of choice is Futura.) Once again, the most cutting and
substantive art uses design as its principal constituent.
Through these works, design demonstrates what Donald Preziosi calls a “carrying capacity” – the ability of a
study object to have art historical significance as a cultural artifact. It also confirms that design artifacts
require a much deeper reading.
Haacke’s influence has already paid significant dividends for graphic design. Ellen Lupton and J. Abbott
Miller studied with Haacke at Cooper Union. Their use of design as a fundamental element in their factography
refers to Haacke’s investigations.
ESTHETICS IS FOR ARTISTS AS ORNITHOLOGY IS FOR THE BIRDS.
Barnett Newman
THE PLEASURES OF THE VORTEXTURE
A cynical opinion about art theory is that its complexity and self-referentiality can justify anything. But rather
than shunning it, designers should investigate and elaborate.
Of course, the basis of art world regard is doctrinal adherence, not theoretical alignment. The goal shouldn’t
be gaining art world acceptance. Designers must add art’s material culture speculations to their data base – if
only to chart wrong directions.
Art is a recent construct historically. The notion of timeless objects being preserved through the centuries
because of their inherent quality is misguided. Art is all “presentism.” Much of what we value was a previous
generation’s excess. And who knows what was lost?
That there is an “art” phenomenon is still pure speculation. As stated by Donald Preziosi, art history has
not only described art, it has shaped it. Artists’ awareness of art history and subsequent desire to be part of
the canon has been the fundamental motivation for art making this century. All other rationales are secondary
at best.
Art history indoctrinates students into the art industry primarily through books and magazines. First-hand
experience of art is still rare and overshadowed by the preponderance of art publications. Artists become
artists because of what they see in print, not in a museum. Ed Ruscha’s determination to be an artist came
from seeing a reproduction of a Jasper Johns painting in Print magazine. For scores of artists, art is a small
repro (frequently in black and white) with an accompanying caption. Art became its representation almost
immediately upon birth. Concrete artifacts were but illustrations of concepts. This, of course, is the truth of all
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 36
FACTOGRAPHIC DESIGN
Design has directed attention to contemporary artists thought to have links with its practice. Barbara Kruger is
cited as a kind of designer-made-good. She’s often looked to for insight on design’s potential as a medium of
cultural commentary. While Kruger’s work is significant, its relevance for design is limited. Her works were
readily acknowledged as art, unlike the magazine layouts she briefly worked on. Acceptance of her work hasn’t
increased regard for design activity. Also, Kruger hardly utilizes the potential of the rhetoric of design. Though
she explored different typefaces in early works (and nothing controversial in design), she has stuck to an extra
bold Futura italic since. In this, she proves more discriminatory than Massimo Vignelli. Considering the
conservatism about design described previously, it may be that Kruger recognized what was unacceptable in
art. Being typographically challenging might prove professionally dangerous.
The artist Hans Haacke provides a crucial insight into the construction of art and design. Critical study of his
work highlights the artificiality of the art/design division. In their content and reception, Haacke’s
installations disclose the overriding commercial concerns of the art industry. By denying what he terms the
“trademark appearance of art,” Haacke constructs a relevant art by constituting it as design.
Haacke – a German-born artist who has resided in the U.S. since 1965 – has been one of the most
significantly controversial artists of the past two decades. (“Significantly” means that the controversies have
not centered on political distractions such as obscenity and flag-burning.) Originally allied with conceptual
art movements in the 1960s, he turned to a political art at the start of the 1970s. His works blandly document
“…the institutional, discursive and economic apparatuses of international high art….” Manipulating the
advertisements and collateral of multinational corporations, he exposes their connections to repression and
exploitation. Support for the arts serves as whitewash, not altruism. Art is implicated as another method of
control.
Censorship and cancellations mark Haacke’s exhibition career. Institutional discomfort with the works’
content motivated these actions. Elaborate circumlocutions attempted to draw attention away from
accusations of suppression. Haacke’s work was criticized for its lack of aesthetic pleasure and for being mere
journalism. Curiously, he employs strict (Swiss International Style) modernist design tools to attack modernist
ideals of “…esthetic autonomy and esthetic pleasure.”
Art historian and critic Benjamin Buchloh’s Hans Haacke: Memory and Instrumental Reason, is an important
analysis of the artist’s work and its ramifications not only for art, but our entire visual culture. Buchloh
believes Haacke’s work “…has in fact been marginalized because it represents a turning point – one of those
historical moments in which a set of assumptions about the structures and functions of art are being effectively
challenged (in a way that Heartfield’s work constituted such an instant in the 30s).” Like Heartfield’s, Haacke’s
work utilizes the forms of “commercial art,” using its language to critique society.
To categorize Haacke’s (and other like-minded artists’) work, Buchloh coined the term “factography.”
Factography is an art form that is motivated by a desire to expose economic and political powers manipulating
our society. Factography also attempts to escape and disrupt the corrupted art practices of the past. It takes
as its subject matter a neutral, documentary reportage of facts, such as statistics. This form is regarded
by the public as both participatory and immediate – no art education is required to comprehend its message.
Factography thus denies the typical aesthetic concerns of art and invites challenge as an art practice.
Haacke’s works frequently simulate corporate PR. Billboards and advertisements are restructured with
corporate design precision. Through these simulations, the photographic and textual inversions have great im-
pact. The bland straightforwardness becomes highly charged in ways a more adventurous design could not. An
infamous censored work, Manet-PROJECT ‘74, is chilling in its simplicity. The rejected installation would have
displayed a Manet painting with ten panels tracing the art work’s provenance. These panels, set in Times
Roman, resemble the ubiquitous head-shot/text bios of countless annual reports. (The work was rejected as its
ninth panel revealed “…a prominent figure in the economic establishment of the Nazi government…now
functions as a major cultural benefactor in the liberal democracy of postwar Germany.” )
Along with demonstrating the complexity of meanings attendant in design forms, Haacke’s work leads to a
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 39
References
EDWARD O. WILSON, Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge, Knopf, 1998.
The Art of Art History: A Critical Anthology, edited by DONALD PREZIOSI, Oxford University Press, 1998.
MORSE PECKHAM, Man’s Rage for Chaos: Biology, Behavior and the Arts, Schocken Books, 1965.
PAUL RAND, Design, Form, and Chaos, Yale University Press, 1993.
ELIZABETH RESNICK, “Paul Rand: The Movie,” AIGA Journal of Graphic Design, Vol. 16, No. 2, 1998.
DAVE HICKEY, “Air Guitar: Essays on Art & Democracy,” Art Issues. press, 1997.
LEWIS BLACKWELL, David Carson: 2nd Sight: Graphik Design after the End of Print, St. Martin’s Press, 1997.
HAL FOSTER, Recodings: Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics, Bay Press, 1985.
JENNY HOLZER AND PETER NADIN, Eating Friends, Hallwalls, 1986.
For an extended look at the “high & low” dialog, see “High Way Robbery,” MICHAEL DOOLEY, Print, XLV:V, September/October 1991.
BRIAN O’DOHERTY, Inside the White Cube: The Ideology of the Gallery Space, The Lapis Press, 1986.
“Rust Belt,” Emigre 46, Spring 1998.
BENJAMIN BUCHLOH, “Hans Haacke: Memory and Instrumental Reason,” Art in America, February 1988.
MICHAEL DOOLEY, “Ed Words: Ruscha in Print,” Print, XLVIII:V, September/October 1994.
DAMIEN HIRST, I Want to Spend the Rest of My Life Everywhere, with Everyone, One to One, Always, Forever, Now,
Booth-Clibborn Editions, 1998.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 38
art, inadvertently revealed.
With print as the direct vehicle defining art, design becomes the framework for its perception. Rather than
being handmaiden, design is validation. As with the show announcements, it is the design that tells you it’s
real art. Art publications (direct descendants of auction catalogues) don’t support and frame art, they
consume it whole. At best, there is symbiosis.
This design filter has been modernist. However, this structure is breaking down, as is the gallery framework.
Postmodern art within modern frameworks is causing public dissonance. Art needs to reconfigure its perceptual
vehicle, which will also change its nature. This direction leads through design.
A prototype of this eventuality is Jonathan Barnbrook’s design of the Damien Hirst monograph, I Want to
Spend the Rest of My Life Everywhere, with Everyone, One to One, Always, Forever, Now. Barnbrook and Hirst
realize that the “neutral” modernist paradigm for representing art work cannot adequately serve a postmodern
artist. (The “original” works, of course, regularly appear in the modernist White Cube.) Hirst’s problematic
pieces are far more engaging as graphic devices than objects of contemplation. Barnbrook’s inventive and
seductive design comes closest to accounting for the appeal of the morally questionable practice of
segmenting farm animals.
Meanwhile, designers like Paul Rand deserve inclusion in the art canon. This recognition, however, will not
come in the way he would have wanted. As art history gravitates toward visual culture studies, attention will
move toward design. Rand’s logos were the emblematic artifacts of their time. They were of a kind concurrent
with abstract painting and sculpture. Corporations hung and placed those art works in their offices for the
same reason they placed Rand’s symbols on their letterheads. Each signified modernity, efficiency, and was
resolutely neutral. Rand’s aesthetic rationale is dissertation material but not germane to their impact.
Eventually, art comes down to aura. Walter Benjamin predicted that works of art would lose their aura due to
mass reproduction. However, it hasn’t quite turned out that way. During his presentation at Fuse98, Bruce Mau
noted that mass reproduction has caused art to become even more valuable. The Mona Lisa, for instance, now
transcends valuation as a commodity.
What also has happened is an aura for mass produced works with no original. Designed artifacts may
generate an aura due to the various associations people append to them. A personal example is record albums.
It was aura I was experiencing when I picked up certain desired albums. I knew there were millions in circulation
but it didn’t matter. Purchasing one was enough. I still experience the aura when I’m shopping for CDs and run
across a favorite work I already possess. I want to buy it again, to refresh the aura.
ART IS THE ORIENTATION THAT MAKES INNOVATION POSSIBLE.
Morse Peckham
THE ONE IMPORTANT THING I HAVE LEARNT OVER THE YEARS IS THE DIFFERENCE
BETWEEN TAKING ONE’S WORK AND TAKING ONESELF SERIOUSLY.
THE FIRST IS IMPERATIVE AND THE SECOND DISASTROUS.
Margot Fonteyn
ART FOR OUR SAKE
What role do art and design play? For Dave Hickey, art should be a function of democracy. The first step is for
art to admit it is a “bad, silly, frivolous thing to do.” “…We can stop regarding the art world as a ‘world’ or a
‘community’ or a ‘market’ and begin thinking of it as a semi-public, semi-mercantile, semi-institutional agora
– an intermediate institution of civil society, like that of professional sports, within which issues of private
desire and public virtue are negotiated and occasionally resolved.” This is also design’s state. All the aesthetic
rationalizations and informational architecture conceits can’t change the fact that it’s usually self-indulgent
toying with form. And that it’s okay.
Morse Peckham finds a biological necessity in art. Rather than an expression of order, art strives to create
disorder, so we may learn to handle the stress of reality. “Art is exposure to the tensions and problems of a
false world so that man may endure exposing himself to the tensions and problems of the real world.” Peckham
and Hickey come from different directions to agree on art’s frivolity and necessity. Peckham states, “The only
moral justification for the study of the highest level of art…is to take what it can give so seriously, so
passionately, with such conviction that one can learn to do without it.”
Art offers many theories that suggest it’s in crisis intellectually, but the industry keeps rolling along. (Hans
Haacke is regarded as a major international artist and sells work.) Socially, the art world grows increasingly
marginalized. Art industrialists show little inclination to reverse the trend. Art is a pleasant bourgeois
playground.
Helping to drive this marginalization is design assuming its former status. The ephemera of today will
become tomorrow’s timeless art. Design is the contemporary popular art that mediates for people. Therein lies
its power. Designers hankering after art legitimacy is like rock stars writing operas, symphonies, and musicals.
They crave high culture affirmation, effectively renouncing what came before as frivolity.
The challenge for designers is not to become fluent in artspeak so they have come-backs the next time some
artist disses them. The task is far more difficult than regurgitating theory. It’s about unequivocal honesty
about what you do and why you do it. It’s about looking for that honesty in work, not arbitrary surface
features. It requires putting aside the desire to be seen as doing something “higher” than other people. It’s
wanting to do something meaningful today, not begging history.
And the best part is that you can do it with any materials, in any style, any theory, any job, any time.
Then art isn’t and doesn’t matter.
SO MUCH FOR ART, WHAT OF THOUGHT?
Thomas Pynchon, V.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 39
References
EDWARD O. WILSON, Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge, Knopf, 1998.
The Art of Art History: A Critical Anthology, edited by DONALD PREZIOSI, Oxford University Press, 1998.
MORSE PECKHAM, Man’s Rage for Chaos: Biology, Behavior and the Arts, Schocken Books, 1965.
PAUL RAND, Design, Form, and Chaos, Yale University Press, 1993.
ELIZABETH RESNICK, “Paul Rand: The Movie,” AIGA Journal of Graphic Design, Vol. 16, No. 2, 1998.
DAVE HICKEY, “Air Guitar: Essays on Art & Democracy,” Art Issues. press, 1997.
LEWIS BLACKWELL, David Carson: 2nd Sight: Graphik Design after the End of Print, St. Martin’s Press, 1997.
HAL FOSTER, Recodings: Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics, Bay Press, 1985.
JENNY HOLZER AND PETER NADIN, Eating Friends, Hallwalls, 1986.
For an extended look at the “high & low” dialog, see “High Way Robbery,” MICHAEL DOOLEY, Print, XLV:V, September/October 1991.
BRIAN O’DOHERTY, Inside the White Cube: The Ideology of the Gallery Space, The Lapis Press, 1986.
“Rust Belt,” Emigre 46, Spring 1998.
BENJAMIN BUCHLOH, “Hans Haacke: Memory and Instrumental Reason,” Art in America, February 1988.
MICHAEL DOOLEY, “Ed Words: Ruscha in Print,” Print, XLVIII:V, September/October 1994.
DAMIEN HIRST, I Want to Spend the Rest of My Life Everywhere, with Everyone, One to One, Always, Forever, Now,
Booth-Clibborn Editions, 1998.
SKILLING SAWS AND ABSORBENT CATALOGS 38
art, inadvertently revealed.
With print as the direct vehicle defining art, design becomes the framework for its perception. Rather than
being handmaiden, design is validation. As with the show announcements, it is the design that tells you it’s
real art. Art publications (direct descendants of auction catalogues) don’t support and frame art, they
consume it whole. At best, there is symbiosis.
This design filter has been modernist. However, this structure is breaking down, as is the gallery framework.
Postmodern art within modern frameworks is causing public dissonance. Art needs to reconfigure its perceptual
vehicle, which will also change its nature. This direction leads through design.
A prototype of this eventuality is Jonathan Barnbrook’s design of the Damien Hirst monograph, I Want to
Spend the Rest of My Life Everywhere, with Everyone, One to One, Always, Forever, Now. Barnbrook and Hirst
realize that the “neutral” modernist paradigm for representing art work cannot adequately serve a postmodern
artist. (The “original” works, of course, regularly appear in the modernist White Cube.) Hirst’s problematic
pieces are far more engaging as graphic devices than objects of contemplation. Barnbrook’s inventive and
seductive design comes closest to accounting for the appeal of the morally questionable practice of
segmenting farm animals.
Meanwhile, designers like Paul Rand deserve inclusion in the art canon. This recognition, however, will not
come in the way he would have wanted. As art history gravitates toward visual culture studies, attention will
move toward design. Rand’s logos were the emblematic artifacts of their time. They were of a kind concurrent
with abstract painting and sculpture. Corporations hung and placed those art works in their offices for the
same reason they placed Rand’s symbols on their letterheads. Each signified modernity, efficiency, and was
resolutely neutral. Rand’s aesthetic rationale is dissertation material but not germane to their impact.
Eventually, art comes down to aura. Walter Benjamin predicted that works of art would lose their aura due to
mass reproduction. However, it hasn’t quite turned out that way. During his presentation at Fuse98, Bruce Mau
noted that mass reproduction has caused art to become even more valuable. The Mona Lisa, for instance, now
transcends valuation as a commodity.
What also has happened is an aura for mass produced works with no original. Designed artifacts may
generate an aura due to the various associations people append to them. A personal example is record albums.
It was aura I was experiencing when I picked up certain desired albums. I knew there were millions in circulation
but it didn’t matter. Purchasing one was enough. I still experience the aura when I’m shopping for CDs and run
across a favorite work I already possess. I want to buy it again, to refresh the aura.
ART IS THE ORIENTATION THAT MAKES INNOVATION POSSIBLE.
Morse Peckham
THE ONE IMPORTANT THING I HAVE LEARNT OVER THE YEARS IS THE DIFFERENCE
BETWEEN TAKING ONE’S WORK AND TAKING ONESELF SERIOUSLY.
THE FIRST IS IMPERATIVE AND THE SECOND DISASTROUS.
Margot Fonteyn
ART FOR OUR SAKE
What role do art and design play? For Dave Hickey, art should be a function of democracy. The first step is for
art to admit it is a “bad, silly, frivolous thing to do.” “…We can stop regarding the art world as a ‘world’ or a
‘community’ or a ‘market’ and begin thinking of it as a semi-public, semi-mercantile, semi-institutional agora
– an intermediate institution of civil society, like that of professional sports, within which issues of private
desire and public virtue are negotiated and occasionally resolved.” This is also design’s state. All the aesthetic
rationalizations and informational architecture conceits can’t change the fact that it’s usually self-indulgent
toying with form. And that it’s okay.
Morse Peckham finds a biological necessity in art. Rather than an expression of order, art strives to create
disorder, so we may learn to handle the stress of reality. “Art is exposure to the tensions and problems of a
false world so that man may endure exposing himself to the tensions and problems of the real world.” Peckham
and Hickey come from different directions to agree on art’s frivolity and necessity. Peckham states, “The only
moral justification for the study of the highest level of art…is to take what it can give so seriously, so
passionately, with such conviction that one can learn to do without it.”
Art offers many theories that suggest it’s in crisis intellectually, but the industry keeps rolling along. (Hans
Haacke is regarded as a major international artist and sells work.) Socially, the art world grows increasingly
marginalized. Art industrialists show little inclination to reverse the trend. Art is a pleasant bourgeois
playground.
Helping to drive this marginalization is design assuming its former status. The ephemera of today will
become tomorrow’s timeless art. Design is the contemporary popular art that mediates for people. Therein lies
its power. Designers hankering after art legitimacy is like rock stars writing operas, symphonies, and musicals.
They crave high culture affirmation, effectively renouncing what came before as frivolity.
The challenge for designers is not to become fluent in artspeak so they have come-backs the next time some
artist disses them. The task is far more difficult than regurgitating theory. It’s about unequivocal honesty
about what you do and why you do it. It’s about looking for that honesty in work, not arbitrary surface
features. It requires putting aside the desire to be seen as doing something “higher” than other people. It’s
wanting to do something meaningful today, not begging history.
And the best part is that you can do it with any materials, in any style, any theory, any job, any time.
Then art isn’t and doesn’t matter.
SO MUCH FOR ART, WHAT OF THOUGHT?
Thomas Pynchon, V.
- Title Page
Skilling Saws and Absorbent Catalogs
Kenneth FitzGerald
Originally published in Emigre Magazine
Included in the collection Volume: Writings on Graphic Design, Music, Art, and Culture
Towards Illustration Theory: Robert Weaver, Harold Rosenberg, and the
Action Illustrator?
Jaleen Grove
Published in Art Criticism volume 24
Jaleen Grove Essays:
https://jaleengrove.com/words_pprs1.html
Grove, Jaleen. “Towards Illustration Theory: Robert Weaver, Harold Rosenberg, and the Action Illustrator?” Art Criticism, Donald Kuspit,
editor, vol. 24, no. 1, 2009, pp. 69-84.
Towards Illustration Theory: Harold Rosenberg, Robert
Weaver, and the ”Action Illustrator”? .
Jaleen Grove
Ii is quite contrived to match Harold Rosenberg’s art criticism with
the work of illustrator Robe1t Weaver, whom Rosenberg never mentioned and
perhaps never even knew of. Yet doing so affords two opportunities: to cri
tique Rosenberg’s art criticism, and to bring illustration scholarship into the
arena of ait criticism on its own terms, rather than allowing it to exist merely as
a punching bag for fine art’s vanity. The forced companionship may well turn
out to be a failure, but in failing, at least the question of whether the criticism
of a major theorist of the “high” arts can or ought to be useful in understanding
the “low” will be paitly answered. Perhaps this attempt may find meaningful
insights and new strategies for interpreting the creative practices of both crit
ics and illustrators. Revisit1ng and appropriating the thought of critics such as
Rosenberg is an attempt to redress a critical neglect of illustration in the past. It
also tests the current bel ief that the split between high and low art has col
lapsed – a conclusion that has been perhaps prematurely reached, since de-:
spite Robert Weaver’s work being hailed in the 1950,’s as the synthesis of fine
art and illustration, 1 illustrators are still credited differently in publications2
and excluded from exhibitions, and they continue to express concern over
their artistic status. 3 If such a dialectic presupposes that .some basic premises
are held in common, then there ought to be an affinity hidden within the writ
ings of the old adamantly “elitist” critics that can be brought to bear usefully
on commercial art practices; one that can be exhumed through a critical reap
praisal of their thought from an illustrator’s perspective. This paper returns to
the .year of 1959 to posthumously initiate a scholarly debate on whether illus
tration could be “legitimate” ait; a debate that at that time had excluded illus
trators’ viewpoints.
Rosenberg and Weaver were not such strange bedfellows as the fore
going implies. Harold Rosenberg popularized the term “action painting,” and
furthered the careers of Abstract Expressionists, and Robert Weaver was cred
ited with using Abstract Expressionism to revitalize the illustration industry,
moving illustration from academicism to conceptualism.4 Both men were de
te1mined to be misfits (and were)within their respective fields, yet they held
some beliefs in common: “genuine” art was a special entity, creativity should
vol. 24, no.1 69
7
0
be individualistic, the creator ought to be of his times, and a1tists had a moral
duty to challenge the status quo.5 They both deplored what Weaver referred to
as “artistic Stalinism:”6 institutional determinism largely associated with the
formalist doctrines promoted by Rosenberg’s nemesis Clement Greenberg. Their
primary difference is that Weaver stated, “I see no reason why an illustrator
should not think ofhimselfas a serious contemporary painter,”7 while Rosenberg
asserted, “That genuine art can be created to order in modern times has never
been demonstrated. “8 Robert Weaver ‘s illustrations for Sports Illustrated, Life,
Fortune, and other mass publications challenge the belief that creativity in
mass culture could not be considered mt according to Rosenberg’s own pa
rameters in the 1950’s. This paper uses Weaver’s series of illustrations for an
1959 Esquire mtic.le on John F. Kennedy as a case study to examine whether
such work can be considered art. 9
‘
Weaver is remembered as “the godfather of the new illustration” be
cause of bis avant garde innovations. 10 According to Rosenberg, “an
indispensible ingredient” of the avant garde “is social dissent. … The aim of
vanguard art is to build a new kind of life in an epoch in which fonns have
collapsed or turned into purposeless restrictions.” 11 The fonn that illustration
was seen to have exhausted, and that Weaver challenged, was the academic
realism associated with Westpo1t illustrators in -the vein ofNorman Rockwell
and Al Parker. As for social dissent, in 1965 be said he “would like to bring the
artist’s eye to bear upon more dangerous and volatile aspects of our time.”12
He sarcastically observed in 1959, “A true avant-garde might today proclaim
the return of subject matter!” 13
Regarding the question of subject matter, Rosenberg ‘s definition of
an action painter seemed diametrically opposed to Weaver’s definition of an
illustrator. While Weaver said, “The illustrator may use the ideas of the con
temporary painter; but it is communication that is his ultimate goal,” 14 Rosenberg
denied action painters any goals whatsoever:
At a certain moment the canvas began to appear to one American
painter atler another as an arena in which lo act – rather than a
space in which to reproduce, re-design, analyze, or “express” an
object, actual or imagined. What was to go on the canvas was not
a picture but an event. 15
This method consisted of the mtist engaging with the canvas with no subject in
mind, each new mark based on inspiration derived from the last, thereby pro
voking self-knowledge in the artist (or writer-critic); a process that was for
Rosenberg a superior state:
The materials I use – words, paint, gesture – become the means for
… unveiling the unexpected. It is for thi s reason that a work of art
Art Criticism
that carries out an idea conceived by someone else – as in com
mercial art, or art made under the intellectual prodding of dealers,
critics, or cultural managers – is bound to be interior to art brought
into being through a continuous passage between the mind and
the hand of a free individual. 16
Rosenberg’s reasoning assumed that illustrators always know what they are
doi ng ahead 6f execution, that conditions for surprises do not exist in their
methods, that they are always art directed, that direction, goals, and desiderata
11ecessarily hamper freedom, and that self-knowledge cannot be achieved in
commercial work, Robert Weaver, on the ?ther hand, was skeptical of action
painting, caustically remarking in 1959:
Today’s artist finds himself unattached to society. There is no mu
tual responsibility. He is ‘free’. He likes it that way. Is it not this
very freedom that has vitiated and robbed art of its raison d’etre?
I have noticed that abstract expressionism carried to the most reck
less extremes no longer has the power to shock and disturb even
the most conservative of audiences. Ennui sets in …. ‘Self expres
sion’ is not a purpose, it is an inevitable by-product of [an extrin
sic] purpose. It is at this point that the illustrator-painter should
realize his opportunities. 17•
Weaver had reason to question assumptions like Rosenberg’s because Weaver’s
assignments from publishers were very loosely defined. Weaver was dispatched
to cover a topic-delinquent youth, baseball players, industrial labour,
Kennedy’s presidential campaign-in any way he chose, as a journalist was.
He recalled , ” I was known for the kind of work I did. I rarely had to defend it
or argue for it. They came to me, and they knew what they were going to get.” 18
Visiting actual sites, speaking to real people, sketching on the spot, he devel
oped visual essays as he discovered the subject, not beforehand. Recalling his
first cover job for Fortune magazine, be said,
[Art director Leo] Lionni trusted the artist, and once he picked the
right practitioner, he let him alone …. What I did [for the cover]
was go to the library and look up all the preceding Fortune covers
under his direction. I made up my mind there was a certain kind of
cover that he wanted, which I then proceeded to’ copy …. which
he quickly rejected, saying, “No, no, no, no, do it your way.” He
looked at my sketchbook and picked out a most unexpected draw
ing for a cover. I told him it didn’t look like a Fortune cover, and
he said, ‘”I don’t want it to look like a Fortune cover.”19
The way magazines hoped to benefit from letting artists go wild is conveyed in
vol. 24, no. J Tl
72
an advertisement Esquire ran in 1956. Some of Weaver’s work was repro
duced with copy that read,
Between art and illustration lies the very fine line Robert Weaver
captures on canvas today. His work is a startling translation of the
literal. … It’s a first and an imaginative one – and that’s why
you’re bound to find it first in Esquire. For Esquire is good coun
try for explorers like you … You were the first to step out in the
“chukka” boot . .. first with a portable TV. .. And you ‘ ll always
find firsts like these in Esquire . .. Because Esquire is a showcase
for tomorrow’s mood. 20
It is gag-inducing copy like this that set Rosenberg’s teeth on edge. But com
mercial appropriation of “translation” and ” imagination” does not negate the
fact that those very qualities could have genuinely existed for the illustrator as
he made the work, and that they can be reinstated simply by removing the
images from the text with a pair of scissors, mental or rel;\!.
The crux of Rosenberg’s and Weaver’s conflict was whether creativ
ity could thrive best within or outside of mainstream culture. Although in 1948
he protested against the idea of the romantically “alienated” artist, Rosenberg
still felt the artist was some distance away from the everyday by virtue of his
not being a reified worker.2 1 His poor opinion of popular art was strongly mani
fested in his 1957 essay “Pop Culture: Kitsch Criticism.”22 Here, he wanted to
suppress all critical scholarship on “kitsch” (which included illustration), ex
cept that which denounced it as propaganda in order to “change the landscape.”2
1
He worried that studying it ennobled it above its station, imbued it with mean
ingfulness that he felt was not genuine, and worst of all, that it took precious
intellectual attention away from “real” mt. There was, however, the annoying
fact that fine art and mass art often borrowed from each other. Rosenberg
complained that “kitsch” obligated art to retreat to ever more rarified pastures,
for if”kitsch” came to resemble art (as Weaver was promoting), then art would
become just “a commodity among commodities, kitsch.”24 Accusing mass art
of”looting” fine mt, he jealously defended his pet artists ‘ (Willem De Kooning
and Stuart Davis) use of “billboard type and lips that sell rouge” as “a vac
cine,” to critically point out how “life and kitsch have become inseparable.ms
But this chicken-and-egg debate of who-dunnit-first only showed how divid
ing culture i’nto high and low was ultiinately futile. Faced with this obvious
conclusion but detennined to kee’p art and mass culture apart nonetheless,
Rosenberg then awkwardly denied that art was the “counterconcept” of popu
lar culture:
But if it [art] sharply distinguishes itself . . . it becomes a distur
bance, a risk . . . Dissociated from the experience of millions …
A1t Criticism
the best art of our times restricts its appeal to other artists .. . there
is no audience for contemporary art and no luxury for artists. Both
attention and cash go to kitsch . . .. 16
B , distancing itself, art was supposed to maintain a non-commercial purity
y • ~ • 1· h tt , d to avoid collapse with “kitsch,” but m practice t us t eory was an u er
an • d. • h” h
failure. Distance reinscribed the dialectic rather than transcen mg 1t, w 1c
ironically led to its collapse again; the more rarified it became, the more cash
value such art was awarded. By 1969 Rosenberg would_ be forc.ed _to acknowl
edge that, “Action painting does not escap~ the l~w of ~he. fet1sh1sm of_com-
modities …. as in all art.there i~ inherently mAct1on pamtmg a temptation to
chicanerv . . . once Action painting had left the seclusion of the studio the old
art gam~ was going on as usual.”27 Worse, he wanted “genuine” art to _have
some political resonance (rather than an overt stance) b_ut, as he later adm~t~ed,
dissociated art risk~d being inscrutable and therefore meffectual for poht1cal
radicalism,28 In fact, art reduced to an artistic statement of”no comment” could
have any agenda imposed upon it. This was the fate of”depoliticized” abstract
expressionist works, which as Frances Stonor Saunde~s shows, were embrace?
by the Cl A-friendly Museum of Modern Art and Whitney Muse:1m of Am~n
can Art and paraded internationally from 1946 through the 1950 s, promotmg
American-cultural and economic hegemony abroad.29 Nevertheless, Rosenberg
clung to the ideal of dissociation throughout his career, eventually claimi~g
the artist should be distanced as “a primitive, a naYf’, so his mt could “set m
motion previously uncontrolled, or even undiscovered, powers o_f the mind:”‘
0
Finding the socially disconnected artist and art to be mappropnate
vehicles for meaningful engagement with life, Weaver proposed he “~ould
like to show how ‘art’ and illustration could serve each other.” He contmued,
How can there be vitality without meaning? A much more intellec
tually challenging field of painting is that which includes illus~ra:
tion but is not limited by it. Illustration is essential to great pamt
ing. Abstraction cannot be equated with it; it is merely the gram
mar [original emphasis].31
Weaver was entirely in agreement with Rosenberg that the artist should never
be a mere “reflector.” Instead, “in an atomic era he should be a reactor.” And
just as Rosenberg proposed the mtist should dissoci~te, ~o too did ~ea~~~
demand the illustrator “be outside momentary surface 11lus10ns, observmg. -
Yet how could the aloof observer artist also be a nuclear reactor? Weaver
advocated that the observer be completely immersed in the assignment, and
like Rosenberg, he advocated that the artist define his creativity- his
artistness- on his own tenns: 33
vol. 24, no. I 73
74
Since I am an amateur illustrator as well as a professional one, I
commissioned myself to cover ‘Our Town ‘ [a theatre production].
. . . One of the first problems in this kind of assignment is to be
come an accepted, unobtrusive presence. I had to be close to what
was going on but nqt a distraction for the cast. I was able to ac
complish this by showing up regularly at rehearsals and sitting
around for long hours. The illustrator, too, needs this familiariza
tion. Thus, in a rela,”Xed way, he can draw exactly what he wants to
draw. 34
“Familiarization,” not withdrawal, was the way to artistic empowerment. He
continued to emphasize drawing from life as research, making his students at
the School of Visual Arts draw in public while saying, “Once the initial shock
of life wears off the student can begin to discover the magnitude of the world.”35
The illustrator was a paiticipant observer, and Weaver called his sketchbook
pages “informational notes,” not art. 36 Rosenberg wrote, “The mass-culture
maker, who takes his experience of others, is essentially a reflector of myths,
and lacks concrete experiences to communicate.”37 Cha:llf:nging this totalizing
proclamation, Weaver said of his journalistic approach,
It was not the kind of mythologizing illustration that you saw in
Cosmopolitan. Theirs was not attached to the real world, and that’s
why I liked the journalistic side of it. … I did do some Cosmo
politcm work, a lot of detective stories, which I enjoy doing, but
even that kind of fictional illustration grew out of the real. I used
real data . . .. I based my Cosmo work on a lot of sketches of real
situations . . .. in the interest of credibility.38
ln observing real situations, Weaver synthesized a distinction Rosenberg made
between “fonnulated common experiences which are the substance of mass
culture and the common situations in which hwnan beings find themselves,”
the latter of which was “the genuine work of art” [originalemphasis].39
Rosenberg protested against the concept of the artist becoming the “medium
of a common experience,” and instead claimed, “For individual experience it
is necessary to begin with the individual.” In agreement with him in principle,
but differing on the score of medium, Weaver stated, “I don’t like symbolism.
lt’s very hard to feel emotional about a symbol [in posters] …. I’m using real
and appropriate symbols. The poster 1 worked from is my poster. That’s my
umbrella. The symbols are-appropriate because they effectively represent my
life.”40 However, both men’s claims were contradicted somewhat by the fact
that Weaver loved flags, even i{he appreciated their symbolism ironically: in
a self-portrait his eccentric jacket is made of the American stars and stripes.41
ln fact, common symbols do not close meaning. Rather, they are points of
familiarity people customize and use in defining their identities as simulta-
Art Criticism
neously similar and different. The more mass identity is imposed, the more it
invites subversion .
Rosenberg’s condemnation of kitsch revolved around its supposed
adherence to rules:
Mass art is the product of creative talent put into the service of
a) art that has established rules
b) art that has a predictable audience, predictable efforts, predict
able rewards
Kitsch is art that follows established rules …. Kitsch is thus art
produced in obedience to the basic assumptions of the Art of the
Ages: the assumption that tracjitional fonns can be put to new uses
through technical means; the assumption that these fonns retain
an intrinsic power to move people. Both these assumptions are
correct.42
It is essentially true that avant garde illustration did use new technical means
to reiterate traditional fo1ms in order to profit from their ensuing novelty, the
very tactic that Rosenberg feared could become propaganda. Weaver did not
deny that this possibility existed. He accused illustrators of being unthinking:
That [the illustrator] has not realized [his artistic opportunities] is
borne out by the low opinion in which the illustrator is held in. the
general ‘art world. Many illustrators of today are too little con
cerned with the actualities of their time. Too often they merely aid
and abet the pre-sold illusion of the age. The illustrator who should
be outside momentary surface illusions observing, is himself ob
served as part of the phenomenon by more serious students of the
time.43
Weaver’s belief that most illustration contributed to “illusion” agreed with
Rosenberg’s opinion, but Weaver differed from Rosenberg in that he felt the
problem could be addressed in commissioned work. Although Rosenberg even
tually saw that abstract expressionism found its logical outcome in ennui ,44 the
idea that artists should be “responsible” frightened him. “I should only like to
make sure nobody is bullied by the abstract concept of social responsibility
into becoming useless to himself and to his fellow men, or even becoming a
menace,” he said, referring to the producers of mass culture who while at
tempting to work for the greater good may become totalitarian instead.45 Illus
tration, however, with its “power to move people” and to “be put to new uses
through technicat means,” deserves credit that it might also be used to posi
tively change the landscape, both in its own right and as the cattle-driver of
fine art;46 it is not a foregon4 conclusion that totalitarianism results from de
sign for mass culture. Weaver, like Rosenberg, pointed out that a “cigarette ad
vol. 24, no.I 75
76
[or] Soviet social realism .. . don’t really communicate.”47 Unlike Rosenberg,
he felt illustration did not necessarily equate to propaganda.
Rosenberg would have called Weaver an “Orgman,” one who buys
into the system he works for. 48 In contrast to the Orgman, the intellectual, like
the artist, “defines himself as an intellectual .. . by the sole fact of his inner
dissociation from the organizational universe” [ original emphasis).49 True in
tellectuals were never contained by their job descriptions, were characterized
by philosophical lone wolfism, and could be found in any walk of Ii fe ,5° except
apparently as “mass culture makers,” whom Rosenberg characterized as a face
less, monolithic lot. In this, he was being hypocritical , since he himself was
paradoxically implicated as an Orgrnan and mass culture producer by his thirty
year career as a radio script-writer and poster campaign planner, then Project
Consultant, on the Advertising Council since at least 1945 until 1971 .5′ Al
though the Ad Council promoted itself as a benign entity perfonning public
service duties like the Smoky The Bear campaign, its close financial ties to the
CIA in the l 950 ‘s and central role in disseminating Cold War propaganda, has
been documented by many. 52 Rosenberg’s theory of the intellectual bureaucrat
who dissociates is likely derived from his Ad Council day-job, but that he
never directly acknowledged his daily toil and paycheck in his critical essays
shows a serious gap between his theory and practice. While Rosenberg prob
ably did not know about the CIA involvement at the time,53 there is no way he
could not have known about “The People’s Capitalism,” a piece of propa
ganda originating with his boss Theodor Repplier that was the template for
international visual displays and pamphleteering at home and abroad in South
America, Europe: and Asia, staiting in 1957.54 It promoted the notion that
capitalism was directed by workers, who participated by purchasing stocks
and insurance plans. It is hard to think of anything fmther from Rosenberg ‘s
personal political beliefs. He was probably as openly critical of this enterprise
as he was of another one on the subject of mental health,55 given that he de
rided the kind of centralized global control that The People’s Capitalism ini
tiative was representative of. It is not that he relaxed his standards; it is likely
he was hired to be as critical as possible. Rather, it suggests that compromise
has its positive aspects; he may have believed in other, more positive work the
Council was doing, or that he could be a voice ofreason within the system. It
is unfortm1ate that he was unable to cut the same slack for other mass culture
producers in art that he gave hims~lfin policy-making. The self-directed intel
lectual who psychologically washes his hands of his day job while remaining
materially tied to it participates in furthering hegemony – but – this illustrates
that there may be no choice except t0 work for freedom within a structure of
_hegemony. There is no politically effective position that remains entirely out
side of popular culture. One must work consciously from within, as Weaver
asked illustrators to do.
Art Criticism
Robert Weaver also fit the description of an intellectual wid1in an
organization, in that he taught at the School ofVisual A1ts but quit every year.56
He also hated the Society of Illustrators, and suggested in his acceptance speech
fo r their Lifetime Achievement Award that they were only giving it to him
because _they “preferred to have him in the tent pissing out rather than outside
pissing in.”57 Weaver said that in the l 950 ‘s he felt illustration was the best
way to express himself, and that he could always “find within a manuscript
some way of putting myself into the illustration,”58 an uncanny echo of
Rosenberg’s assurance that the intellectual always finds “cracks” in which “to
crawl around the obstacles.”59 Indeed, in that illustration is handmade, it can
never be considered in a Marxist.paradigm to be totally reified labour. Weaver
wanted his illustrations to stand alone as art apait from the texts they accompa
nied.60 As such, they undercut the text, allowing the reader to interpret them
against the script if desired.
Fighting for the autonomy of the illustrator suggests fine art values
drove Weaver ‘s program, and indeed, Weaver had never planned to become
an illustrator. In l 953 he got his first contract accidentally when he applied for
a designer-consultant position at Town and Country magazine, where the ait
director decided his sketches would look well as illustrations. Said Weaver,
·'[Illustration] had not appealed to me because of the prevalence of the boy/
girl pretty stuff in magazines. No serious artist would ever consider doing
illustration!”61 In light of Weaver ‘s paranoia of being a “mere” illustrator, in
order to claim artistic integrity, he had to do more than just copy the brush
work of abstract expressionism. Weaver ‘s innovation was, according to Steven
Heller, “to push illustration beyond the single image to the essay fonn or to a
dynamic realm that more closely resembled film than magazine art . .. he
rejected literalism and emphasized pure fonn cut with irony.”62 It is in his
development of ambiguity in illustration that Weaver is to be thought of as an
innovator. Illustration traditionally clarifies. Weaver spoke strongly of clarity,
but insisted in a typically cunning way, “rt is possible to be ambiguous clearly
[like Magritte).”63
Rosenberg always laid responsibility solely on the artist to avoid, by
_artistic spontaneity, “the kind of mental forcing out of which can come only
lifeless illustrations of ready-made ideas.”64 He overlooked that the audience
is also responsible for determining the message, and it is in the viewer ‘.1· spon
taneity that we can find room for political agency in commercial art. In order
for it to be said to have occu1Ted, communication must be shared. As a visual
communicator, Weaver considered the reader ‘s experience as well as his own.
The “action illustrator” is then one who, as a nuclear reactor, provokes the
·’action” in the reader-viewer. Weaver avoided totalitarian depictions through
ambiguous dialectic juxtapositions that cracked open the illusionistic front of
illustration and allowed the viewer to engage in free semiosis, what Rosenberg
vol. 24, no. l 77
78
called “set[ting] in motion previously uncontrolled, or even undiscovered
powers of the mind. “65 Discussing his 1959 Esquire spread on then-Senato;
John F. Kennedy, Weaver said,
it can be seen that my pictures sometimes might be said to operate
on two or more levels of meaning. What is visible to the naked eye
in real life does not always tell the ‘ truth;’ so it is sometimes nec
essary to recompose life or juxtapose two widely separated ele
ments in order to make visible and readable a true but invisible
meaning or relationship.(,;
Weaver never disclosed what this invisible meaning might be. He had set out
to “demonstrate that politics is just as visual and colorful as, say, show busi
ness … I was especially interested in the people who surround Kennedy. My
observations have an even sharper edge among the paintings which were not
used in the article.” But he didn’t approve of preaching morality directly. “As
to Kennedy himself, I discovered I could come to no conclusion about the man
and so chose not to do so in the paintings. Let the experts conclude; my job
was to produce pictures.”67
It would be fascinating to know whether the “sharper” images had
been eliminated by Esquire or by Weaver. Marshall Arisman, a longtime friend
of Weaver, says Weaver was left of centre, but apolitical.68 This perhaps in
forms the polyvalent readings possible in the Kennedy series, the ambiguity
that allows readers to interpret freely. In the title page image, a swann of can
didates holding placards that together portray the White House, can be read as
either democracy working collectively for the whole, or as individuals break
ing up the whole into pieces.
In the second image, according to the caption, Kennedy is “poised
symbolically on the threshold” of the Capitol’s Statuary Hall, “with campaign
posters representing the rough-and-tumble way into the serenity of accom
plishment.” The posters outside the door behind Kennedy framino him can ‘ e, – ,
also stand for profane commercial art versus the sanctified fine art inside this
temple, or the inevitable codependence of the two. Kennedy is dwarfed by the
Corinthian columns of the hall, and by founding father figures that include the
seated socialist-leaning Senator Robert Lafollette. Lafollette, despite popu
larity and effectiveness, never made it to the top, so he may be read as a bench
mark for Kennedy or a warning. Weaver includes on the far left signage an
nouncing SHELTER AREA THIS WAY with an arrow, which may be read two
ways. If the arrow is seen to be pointing out of the room and off the page, it is
implying that even if Kennedy makes it into the Hall as a celebrated figure: he
will find no shelter there. If the arrow is read as an invitation to come further
• into the room, it implies the opposite.
The Statuary Hall picture is matched with a small image on the facing
A1t Criticism
page of Kennedy and his rival Nixon eyeing one another in a hallway that
stretches beyond them into infinity; they had rather awkwardly been assigned
onices across from one another. Isolating them together in this barren setting,
Weaver makes them both rivals and brethren. Turning to the next spread, a
large image of supporters watching from the steps of the Capitol building is
paired with a smaller picture ofKetmedy that is positioned on the page so that
it appears as if the supporters are looking at him. The latter shows posters on
poles depicting his face in sections, that together build a solemn portrait of
him, yet they appear to fracture his identity as well. The caption refers to him
as ·’the complex young man who holds [supporters’] hopes” while the pull
quote on the preceding page a~ks, “Can he get the nomination? Will he be
elected? What kind of President would he make?” The shattered portrait can
then be read as questioning whether Kennedy’s mental complexity is a risk, or
else suggesting that his complexity is responsive to the different constituents
who presumably hold the poles aloft.
Compared to the caricaturish handling of the figures of people close
to Kennedy whom Weaver depicts on the following page, the suppmters look
ing from the steps towards the portrait are imbued with dignity, drawn in natu
ralistic poses and body proportions, with individuated faces that for the most
part av~id exaggeration. In his painting of the people smTounding Kennedy,
Weaver has laid identical ” toothpaste” grins onto several men, including
Kennedy, in bright white paint. Their legs are short and rigid, not conyincing,
while the floor falls out from under them in forced perspective. It is in this
piece that we best see Weaver’s negative opinion of the show business of poli
tics, in contrast to his sensitive treatment of the hoi polloi on the steps.
Throughout the series, Weaver draws attention to the role of posters,
TV, film, and banners in the campaign, a prescient move given that Kennedy’s
success was later attributed by many to his deft exploitation of broadcast me
dia. In a small spot-illustration paired with the caricature ofhis team, Kennedy
is shown inside a car, with a wall of posters outside the window. He is holding
a newspaper and it appears he is being esc01ted by police out of the confines of
the posters, one of which prominently spells CIRCU-, possibly circus, lending
. credence to the idea that Weaver was comparing campaigning to show busi
ness.
On the last page, Weaver showed Kennedy on a movie set, with a
false window behind him and studio paraphernalia in the foreground, expos
ing the fakery of it all. This small spot was paired with a half-page bleed of a
theatre screening a film on Kennedy’s life. The film still shows men in suits,
the se”cond one bearing a passing resemblance to Hitler, with the words THE
END ominously dominating. This also acted as a reference to the series itself,
since it was the last illustration in the sequence. Overall, the loose handl ing of
the brush in sketches where the perspective stayed relatively classical implied
vol. 24, no. I 79
that what he captured was objective, while the more contrived compositions
with flattened space and more awkward figures inserted a feeling of self-con
scious subjectivity.The interplay of objectivity and subjectivity created some
thing approximating Rosenberg’s “unique psychic tension” that he held out for
genuine, critical art,69 a tension that could allow the reader to question both the
“truth” and “interpretation” proposed by the illustrations.
Weaver sounded certain that illustration could be artin 1959, but was
no longer sure by 1965: “It is quite possible that illustration and art might one
day merge, at some vanishing point in history, but for the moment their aims
and purposes are quite different,” he claimed.70 ln 1986, Weaver explained, “1
don’t feel [that illustration can be art] now, but in the early days, yes, I felt that
everything I needed to say could be said in illustrations …. Now illustration
has become very constricting.”7 1 The constrictions were both in the industry
and within himself. He remarked:
Illustration is a younger man’s art form. I think one eventually
gets tired of that kind of illustration where you have to make up
solutions to stories that essentially ‘are simplistic. If you really have
an interest in art or ideas, you need some way of letting that come
out, and you can’t do it in illustration alone, unless you’re given a
lot of paper and a lot of time and freedom. 72
The Kennedy assignment was hardly simplistic, but such jobs are not every
day work. After he had mostly stopped taking contracts, in 1979 he argued that
illustration was not y~t art because illustrators had not retained control as art
directors and designers: “For a work to be judged as art there must be an artist
in full command of the medium. Only when he has pushed it as far as it can go
can he be tested fairly by the same critical standards applied to other artists.m3
He defined the medium as “ink, mechanically printed on both sides of the
bound pages of a magazine,” and said, “I think it is possible to extend the
definition of the medium to include an appreciation of the possibilities for
narTative that reside uniquely in the structure of the book.”74 He devoted his
last decades to these “two-story” or “split-level”· books, in which the pages
were divided with different narratives (one could say like text and subtext)
catrying on independently in each section. They invited the reader to synthe
size a third meaning, a clear progression from the ambiguity of his earlier
work in magazines. Famously, fulfilling Rosenberg’s ideal, he refused to ex
hibit or sell them at all, and he gave away extremely few. Yet he still did not
consider himself an artist, because he did not feel he had of anything of impor-
~n~ ~ szy~
1
While Weaver’s art for magazines may be seen as satisfying even
Harold Rosenberg’s criteria for art, Weaver’s abandonment of it for non-com
mercial studio practice suggests Rosenberg’s position holds weight. Indeed,
Att Criticism
the Illustrators Pattnership of America and other industry representatives are
still fighting for illustrators to be recognized as equal to the creative demands
of the early design stages of the projects they are called upon to illustrate. 76 We
must conclude then, that Rosenberg’s insistence that the mass production of
culture conflicts with individual creative input is correct. However, it does not
follow that individual artistic expression is not to be found in illustration. Art
cannot be limited by medium, method, or even message. The question is not
whether “painting” or “illustration” is valid, but whether the practitioner is
achieving what is important to him or her, be it self-realization or social par
ticipation. Weaver himself, even when he denied most illustration was art, still
allowed that “the best practitioners rpay one day be remembered as artists.”77
Despite, or because of, ruffling feathers, Weaver is considered among
illustrators one of the most important of the twentieth century.78 The landscape
Weaver contributed to changing was that of how illustrators think of their
working relationships. As illustrator Leif Peng put it, “I suspect that what Rob
ert Weaver did by leaping into mid-air was show others that it could and should
be done. Someone must take the daring plunge – and survive – to give others
the courage to follow.”79 Weaver showed that base and superstructure are not
in a deterministic relationship so much as a dialectic one, and that the commer
cial artist is uniquely positioned to play both sides.
Notes:
1 Sterling Mclhlany. “The Realism of Robert Weaver,” American Artist, (Sept.
1959): 65.
‘ Debate has occuITed in the New York Times 1\1/agazine offices over whether gallery
arti sts ought to be credited as” Artwork by … ” or “Illustration by … ”
(conversation between Times art directors and attendees ofICON5, The
Illustration Conference, July, 2008).
3 For example, a cover of Varoom magazine (July 2008) by Brad Holland, is filled
with handwriting complaining that “Actors are artists, musicians are artists … it
seems the only people who are not artists are illustrators.”
“Steven Heller, “The End oflllustration?,” 1llustrators ‘Partnership, 2003, http://
www. i 11 ustratorspartnersh i p.org/0 l _topics/article. php?searchterm=00073
(accessed Nov. 23, 2008).
‘ I shall retain the use of “he” throughout my discussion of Rosenberg and Weaver’s
art and writing, since I am primarily discussing a period when women were
invisible in art. This is not to reinscribe their marginalization but to expose it.
” Weaver in Mclhlany, 66.
7 Ib’id.
8 Harold Rosenberg, “The Herd of Independent Minds,” Discovering the Present
(Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1973), 26. Rosenberg’s italics were due to his
allowing that high m1 was made to order in antiquity.
9 In Richard H. Rovere, “Kennedy ‘s Last Chance to be President,” Esquire li1aga-
vol. 24, no. I 81
zine (April. 1959): 63-70. According to Doug B. Dowd. the location of the
original art for these reproductions is unknown.
10 Steven Heller, “The Godfather;· Seeing is Not Believing (Norman Rockwell
Museum, 1997), unpaginated.
11 Rosenberg. “The Concept of Action in Painting.” 223, 227.
12 Weaver in Walt Reed, The Illustrator in America, 1900-1960 :~ (New York:
Reinhold Publishing, 1967): 268.
13 Weaver in Mclhlany, 67. Original italics.
14 Weaver in Reed, 267.
15 Harold Rosenberg, ‘·The American Action Painters,., [ 1953) in Tradition of the
New (New York: McGraw-Hill , 1965): 25.
16 Harold Rosenberg, ·The Concept of Action in Painting,” in Artworks and
Packages (New York: Horizon Press, 1969): 222.
17 Weaver in Mclhlany, 66.
18 Weaver in Steven Heller. innovators of American !llustration (New York: Van
Nostrand Reinhold, 1986) 16.
19 Ibid.
20 l”squire ii.fagazine, “You saw it First in Esquire,” Display ad 217, New York Times
(Nov. 14. 1956): 49.
21 Rosenberg, “The Herd oflndependent Minds;’ in Discovering the Present, 16.
22 Rosenberg. “Pop Culture: Kitsch Criticism,” in Tradition of the New. 259.
23 Ibid., 265.
2• Ibid ., 267.
25 Ibid. , 264, 265.
26 Ibid .. 26 7.
27 Rosenberg, ·’The Concept of Action in Painting,” in Artworks and Packages, 224.
28 Rosenberg, “Art of Bad Conscience”, in Artworks and Packages. l 59.
29 Frances Stonor Saunders, Who Paid the Piper?: The CIA and the Cultural Cold
War (London: Granta Books, 1999), 257-278.
”
0 Rosenberg, ·’Art and Its Double,” in Artworks and Packages, 20-23.
31 Weaver in, Mclhlany, 66.
32 Ibid.
33 “A.n artist is a person who has invented an artist. … Artists are people who
tamper with what makes them ai1ists.” Rosenberg, “Themes,” in Discovering
the Present, 214.
34 Weaver in Mclhlany, 34.
3; Ibid .. 67.
36 Weaver in Heller, Innovators, 18.
;
7 Rosenberg, “The Herd of Independent Minds.” in DiscoverinK the Present. 28.
38 Weaver in /·leller, innovators, 16. –
39 Rosenberg, ‘”The Herd oflndependent Minds,” in Discovering the Present, 18.
•
0 Weaver in Heller, Innovators, 18.
41 Selfporrrait, circa 1960, reproduced in Seeing is Not Believing: The Art of Robert
Weaver, [ exhibition catalogue for The Norman Rockewell Museum and the
School of Visual Arts] (New York and Stockbridge: Visual Arts Press 1997):
unpaginated. The Location of the original art is unknown.
42 Rosenberg, ” Pop Culture: Kitsch Criticism,” in Tradition of the New, 266.
Art Criticism
4-‘ Weaver in Mclhlany, 66.
H Rosenberg, –virtuosos of Boredom,” in Discovering the Present, 120-121 .
• 5 Rosenberg. –The Herd of Independent .Minds,” in Discovering the Present, 28.
•1• A reference to Rosenberg ‘s a<;sertion that mass culture forces fine art to constantly
retreat to more rarified realms, cited above.
“‘ Weaver in Reed, 267.
“Rosenberg, ”The Orgamerican Phantasy,” in Tradition of the New, 271.
•” Rosenberg, “Twi light of the Intellectuals,” ( 1958) in Defining the Present, 173.
w Rosenberg , “The Intellectua l and His Future,” [ 1965] in Defining the Present,
194.
;i Eve Mangurten [for the Advertising Council], to Grove by email on Oct. 30. 2008.
‘ 2 E.e.., Robert Haddow, “Material Culture and the Cold War: International Trade
Fairs and the American Pav11ion at the 1958 Brussels World ‘s Fair” (Ph.D diss.,
University of Minnesota, 1994); Scott Lucas, Freedoms f,flar: The American
Crusade Against the Soviet Union (New York: NYU Press, 1999); Saunders,
Who Paid the Piper?: The CIA and the Culwral Cold War (London: Granta
Books, 1999).
,:, Rosenberg, ··Stopping Communism,” in Defining the Present, 3 IO. In this essay he
lambasts the dishonesty of the CIA in their dealings with intellectuals.
;. Haddow, I 994, 44, 52, 54-56, 61, 317.
;; Archivist’s note, Harold Rosenberg Finding Aid, Getty Institute. Los Angeles.
‘ 6 Marshall Arisman, interview with Grove on October 27, 2008.
;, Ibid.
” Weaver in Heller, Innovators, 16.
”> Rosenberg, “The Intellectual and His Future,” in Defining the Present, 194.
<·0 Weaver in Heller, Innovators, 17.
(,I Ibid.
"2 Steven Heller, "Robert Weaver 1924- I 994; · Print 48.5 (1994): 130.
r,; Robert Weaver, "Robert Weaver's Illustration Issue," Print (Nov-Dec 1979);
reprinted as ” lntrospectives:· in Print 48.5 ( 1994): 116.
,,.i Rosenberg, “AI1 of Bad Conscience,” in Artworks and Packages, 167-168.
“5 Rosenberg, “Art and Its Doub le,’· in Artworks and Packages, 20-23.
”” Weaver in Mclhlany, 35.
”
7 Ibid. , 35, 65.
,,, Arisman in interview with Grove.
“” Rosenberg, ” Pop culture: Kitsch Criticism,” in Tradition of the New, 267.
‘” Weaver in Reed, 267.
71 Weaver in Heller, 16.
72 Ibid. , 19.
73 Weaver, Print ( 1994 ): I l 6.
‘• I.bid. , 117.
,; Arisman in interview with Grove.
7” For essavs on ” the art of illustration.” see the Illustrators Partnership of America,
http:/i~vww. i 11 ustratorspartnership.org/0 I_ topics/topics.php?searchtype=topic
Category&searchterm=artofi l lustrntion&topi cType=category& topicTenn=0 l.
77 Weaver, Print ( 1994 ): 116.
” Conversations with Milton Glaser, Marshall Arisman. Steven Heller. and Walt
vol. 24, no. l 83
- Towards Illustration Theory: Robert Weaver, Harold Rosenberg, and the Action Illustrator?
Jaleen Grove
Published in Art Criticism volume 24