for aplus writer only

please use attachments !!!!!

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

Discussion One

Aristotle says that the virtues are necessary for humans to attain happiness, but he means this in terms of something we might call “flourishing” or “living well”, which he considers quite different than simply feeling good.  Thus, according to Aristotle some people might feel that they are happy, but because they lack the virtues they are not truly flourishing. However, imagine someone that is deceitful, selfish, greedy, self-indulgent, and yet enjoys great pleasure and appears to be quite happy.  Is someone like this “flourishing” or not?  Explain your answer this by referring to this week’s readings and media, and if possible provide examples from real life and/or from literature, film, TV, etc.

Discussion TWO 

What are 2 virtues that you believe are important to living a flourishing or successful life in Aristotle’s sense of the term?  Explain what goods in human life these virtues enable their possessor to fulfill.  Provide examples of characteristic behavior that manifests these virtues, and contrast that with behavior that displays a lack of virtue.  Do your examples confirm Aristotle’s view that a virtue is a mean between extremes of excess and defect?  If so, explain what those extremes are; if not, explain why.  Refer to this week’s readings and media to illustrate and support your claims.

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

• Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Book One 1-5, 7; Book Two 1-4, 6, 7.

o The full text can be read and/or downloaded here:

http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.html
o A more contemporary translation of chapter 1 can be read and/or downloaded here:

http://catdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam032/99036947
o A more contemporary translation of chapter 2 is available in the Ashford Library by

searching for “Nicomachean Ethics AND AU Taylor AND PT eBook” (without
quotes), or using this link after signing into the Library site:
http://site.ebrary.com.proxy-library.ashford.edu/lib/ashford/Doc?id=10194247

Nicomachean
 Ethics
 

 

 

By
 Aristotle
 
 

 

Written
 350
 B.C.E
 
 

 

Translated
 by
 W.
 D.
 Ross
 

 

BOOK
 I
 

1
 
 

 
Every
 art
 and
 every
 inquiry,
 and
 similarly
 every
 action
 and
 pursuit,
 is
 thought
 to
 aim
 at
 some
 good;
 and
 
for
 this
 reason
 the
 good
 has
 rightly
 been
 declared
 to
 be
 that
 at
 which
 all
 things
 aim…
 
2
 
 

 
If,
 then,
 there
 is
 some
 end
 of
 the
 things
 we
 do,
 which
 we
 desire
 for
 its
 own
 sake
 (everything
 else
 being
 
desired
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 this),
 and
 if
 we
 do
 not
 choose
 everything
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 something
 else
 (for
 at
 
that
 rate
 the
 process
 would
 go
 on
 to
 infinity,
 so
 that
 our
 desire
 would
 be
 empty
 and
 vain),
 clearly
 this
 
must
 be
 the
 good
 and
 the
 chief
 good.
 Will
 not
 the
 knowledge
 of
 it,
 then,
 have
 a
 great
 influence
 on
 life?
 
Shall
 we
 not,
 like
 archers
 who
 have
 a
 mark
 to
 aim
 at,
 be
 more
 likely
 to
 hit
 upon
 what
 is
 right?
 If
 so,
 we
 
must
 try,
 in
 outline
 at
 least,
 to
 determine
 what
 it
 is,
 and
 of
 which
 of
 the
 sciences
 or
 capacities
 it
 is
 the
 
object.
 
 

 
3
 
 

 
Our
 discussion
 will
 be
 adequate
 if
 it
 has
 as
 much
 clearness
 as
 the
 subject-­‐matter
 admits
 of,
 for
 precision
 
is
 not
 to
 be
 sought
 for
 alike
 in
 all
 discussions,
 any
 more
 than
 in
 all
 the
 products
 of
 the
 crafts…We
 must
 
be
 content,
 then,
 in
 speaking
 of
 such
 subjects
 [as
 fine
 and
 just
 actions
 and
 other
 goods]
 and
 with
 such
 
premisses
 to
 indicate
 the
 truth
 roughly
 and
 in
 outline,
 and
 in
 speaking
 about
 things
 which
 are
 only
 for
 
the
 most
 part
 true
 and
 with
 premisses
 of
 the
 same
 kind
 to
 reach
 conclusions
 that
 are
 no
 better.
 In
 the
 
same
 spirit,
 therefore,
 should
 each
 type
 of
 statement
 be
 received;
 for
 it
 is
 the
 mark
 of
 an
 educated
 man
 
to
 look
 for
 precision
 in
 each
 class
 of
 things
 just
 so
 far
 as
 the
 nature
 of
 the
 subject
 admits;
 it
 is
 evidently
 
equally
 foolish
 to
 accept
 probable
 reasoning
 from
 a
 mathematician
 and
 to
 demand
 from
 a
 rhetorician
 
scientific
 proofs.
 
 

 
Now
 each
 man
 judges
 well
 the
 things
 he
 knows,
 and
 of
 these
 he
 is
 a
 good
 judge.
 And
 so
 the
 man
 who
 
has
 been
 educated
 in
 a
 subject
 is
 a
 good
 judge
 of
 that
 subject,
 and
 the
 man
 who
 has
 received
 an
 all-­‐

round
 education
 is
 a
 good
 judge
 in
 general.
 Hence
 a
 young
 man
 is
 not
 a
 proper
 hearer
 of
 lectures
 on
 
political
 science;
 for
 he
 is
 inexperienced
 in
 the
 actions
 that
 occur
 in
 life,
 but
 its
 discussions
 start
 from
 
these
 and
 are
 about
 these;
 and,
 further,
 since
 he
 tends
 to
 follow
 his
 passions,
 his
 study
 will
 be
 vain
 and
 
unprofitable,
 because
 the
 end
 aimed
 at
 is
 not
 knowledge
 but
 action.
 And
 it
 makes
 no
 difference
 
whether
 he
 is
 young
 in
 years
 or
 youthful
 in
 character;
 the
 defect
 does
 not
 depend
 on
 time,
 but
 on
 his
 
living,
 and
 pursuing
 each
 successive
 object,
 as
 passion
 directs.
 For
 to
 such
 persons,
 as
 to
 the
 incontinent,
 
knowledge
 brings
 no
 profit;
 but
 to
 those
 who
 desire
 and
 act
 in
 accordance
 with
 a
 rational
 principle
 
knowledge
 about
 such
 matters
 will
 be
 of
 great
 benefit.
 
 

 
These
 remarks
 about
 the
 student,
 the
 sort
 of
 treatment
 to
 be
 expected,
 and
 the
 purpose
 of
 the
 inquiry,
 
may
 be
 taken
 as
 our
 preface.
 
 

 
4
 
 

 
Let
 us
 resume
 our
 inquiry
 and
 state,
 in
 view
 of
 the
 fact
 that
 all
 knowledge
 and
 every
 pursuit
 aims
 at
 
some
 good,
 what
 it
 is
 that
 we
 say
 political
 science
 aims
 at
 and
 what
 is
 the
 highest
 of
 all
 goods
 achievable
 
by
 action.
 Verbally
 there
 is
 very
 general
 agreement;
 for
 both
 the
 general
 run
 of
 men
 and
 people
 of
 
superior
 refinement
 say
 that
 it
 is
 happiness,
 and
 identify
 living
 well
 and
 doing
 well
 with
 being
 happy;
 but
 
with
 regard
 to
 what
 happiness
 is
 they
 differ,
 and
 the
 many
 do
 not
 give
 the
 same
 account
 as
 the
 wise…
 
 

Presumably,
 then,
 we
 must
 begin
 with
 things
 known
 to
 us.
 Hence
 any
 one
 who
 is
 to
 listen
 intelligently
 to
 
lectures
 about
 what
 is
 noble
 and
 just,
 and
 generally,
 about
 the
 subjects
 of
 political
 science
 must
 have
 
been
 brought
 up
 in
 good
 habits.
 For
 the
 fact
 is
 the
 starting-­‐point,
 and
 if
 this
 is
 sufficiently
 plain
 to
 him,
 
he
 will
 not
 at
 the
 start
 need
 the
 reason
 as
 well;
 and
 the
 man
 who
 has
 been
 well
 brought
 up
 has
 or
 can
 
easily
 get
 starting
 points.
 And
 as
 for
 him
 who
 neither
 has
 nor
 can
 get
 them,
 let
 him
 hear
 the
 words
 of
 
Hesiod:
 
 

 
Far
 best
 is
 he
 who
 knows
 all
 things
 himself;
 
 
Good,
 he
 that
 hearkens
 when
 men
 counsel
 right;
 
 
But
 he
 who
 neither
 knows,
 nor
 lays
 to
 heart
 
 
Another’s
 wisdom,
 is
 a
 useless
 wight.
 
 

 

7
 
 

 
Let
 us
 again
 return
 to
 the
 good
 we
 are
 seeking,
 and
 ask
 what
 it
 can
 be.
 It
 seems
 different
 in
 different
 
actions
 and
 arts;
 it
 is
 different
 in
 medicine,
 in
 strategy,
 and
 in
 the
 other
 arts
 likewise.
 What
 then
 is
 the
 
good
 of
 each?
 Surely
 that
 for
 whose
 sake
 everything
 else
 is
 done.
 In
 medicine
 this
 is
 health,
 in
 strategy
 
victory,
 in
 architecture
 a
 house,
 in
 any
 other
 sphere
 something
 else,
 and
 in
 every
 action
 and
 pursuit
 
the
 end;
 for
 it
 is
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 this
 that
 all
 men
 do
 whatever
 else
 they
 do.
 Therefore,
 if
 there
 is
 an
 end
 
for
 all
 that
 we
 do,
 this
 will
 be
 the
 good
 achievable
 by
 action,
 and
 if
 there
 are
 more
 than
 one,
 these
 will
 
be
 the
 goods
 achievable
 by
 action.
 
 

 
So
 the
 argument
 has
 by
 a
 different
 course
 reached
 the
 same
 point;
 but
 we
 must
 try
 to
 state
 this
 even
 
more
 clearly.
 Since
 there
 are
 evidently
 more
 than
 one
 end,
 and
 we
 choose
 some
 of
 these
 (e.g.
 wealth,
 
flutes,
 and
 in
 general
 instruments)
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 something
 else,
 clearly
 not
 all
 ends
 are
 final
 ends;
 but
 
the
 chief
 good
 is
 evidently
 something
 final.
 Therefore,
 if
 there
 is
 only
 one
 final
 end,
 this
 will
 be
 what
 we
 
are
 seeking,
 and
 if
 there
 are
 more
 than
 one,
 the
 most
 final
 of
 these
 will
 be
 what
 we
 are
 seeking.
 Now
 we
 
call
 that
 which
 is
 in
 itself
 worthy
 of
 pursuit
 more
 final
 than
 that
 which
 is
 worthy
 of
 pursuit
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 
something
 else,
 and
 that
 which
 is
 never
 desirable
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 something
 else
 more
 final
 than
 the
 
things
 that
 are
 desirable
 both
 in
 themselves
 and
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 that
 other
 thing,
 and
 therefore
 we
 call
 
final
 without
 qualification
 that
 which
 is
 always
 desirable
 in
 itself
 and
 never
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 
something
 else.
 
 

 
Now
 such
 a
 thing
 happiness,
 above
 all
 else,
 is
 held
 to
 be;
 for
 this
 we
 choose
 always
 for
 self
 and
 never
 for
 
the
 sake
 of
 something
 else,
 but
 honour,
 pleasure,
 reason,
 and
 every
 virtue
 we
 choose
 indeed
 for
 
themselves
 (for
 if
 nothing
 resulted
 from
 them
 we
 should
 still
 choose
 each
 of
 them),
 but
 we
 choose
 them
 
also
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 happiness,
 judging
 that
 by
 means
 of
 them
 we
 shall
 be
 happy.
 Happiness,
 on
 the
 
other
 hand,
 no
 one
 chooses
 for
 the
 sake
 of
 these,
 nor,
 in
 general,
 for
 anything
 other
 than
 itself.
 
 

 
From
 the
 point
 of
 view
 of
 self-­‐sufficiency
 the
 same
 result
 seems
 to
 follow;
 for
 the
 final
 good
 is
 thought
 
to
 be
 self-­‐sufficient…[T]he
 self-­‐sufficient
 we
 now
 define
 as
 that
 which
 when
 isolated
 makes
 life
 
desirable
 and
 lacking
 in
 nothing;
 and
 such
 we
 think
 happiness
 to
 be;
 and
 further
 we
 think
 it
 most
 
desirable
 of
 all
 things,
 without
 being
 counted
 as
 one
 good
 thing
 among
 others-­‐
 if
 it
 were
 so
 counted
 it
 
would
 clearly
 be
 made
 more
 desirable
 by
 the
 addition
 of
 even
 the
 least
 of
 goods;
 for
 that
 which
 is
 added
 
becomes
 an
 excess
 of
 goods,
 and
 of
 goods
 the
 greater
 is
 always
 more
 desirable.
 Happiness,
 then,
 is
 
something
 final
 and
 self-­‐sufficient,
 and
 is
 the
 end
 of
 action.
 
 

 
Presumably,
 however,
 to
 say
 that
 happiness
 is
 the
 chief
 good
 seems
 a
 platitude,
 and
 a
 clearer
 account
 of
 
what
 it
 is
 still
 desired.
 This
 might
 perhaps
 be
 given,
 if
 we
 could
 first
 ascertain
 the
 function
 of
 man.
 
For
 just
 as
 for
 a
 flute-­‐player,
 a
 sculptor,
 or
 an
 artist,
 and,
 in
 general,
 for
 all
 things
 that
 have
 a
 function
 or
 
activity,
 the
 good
 and
 the
 ‘well’
 is
 thought
 to
 reside
 in
 the
 function,
 so
 would
 it
 seem
 to
 be
 for
 man,
 if
 he
 
has
 a
 function.
 Have
 the
 carpenter,
 then,
 and
 the
 tanner
 certain
 functions
 or
 activities,
 and
 has
 man
 
none?
 Is
 he
 born
 without
 a
 function?
 Or
 as
 eye,
 hand,
 foot,
 and
 in
 general
 each
 of
 the
 parts
 evidently
 
has
 a
 function,
 may
 one
 lay
 it
 down
 that
 man
 similarly
 has
 a
 function
 apart
 from
 all
 these?
 What
 then
 
can
 this
 be?
 Life
 seems
 to
 be
 common
 even
 to
 plants,
 but
 we
 are
 seeking
 what
 is
 peculiar
 to
 man.
 Let
 us
 
exclude,
 therefore,
 the
 life
 of
 nutrition
 and
 growth.
 Next
 there
 would
 be
 a
 life
 of
 perception,
 but
 it
 also
 
seems
 to
 be
 common
 even
 to
 the
 horse,
 the
 ox,
 and
 every
 animal.
 There
 remains,
 then,
 an
 active
 life
 of
 
the
 element
 that
 has
 a
 rational
 principle;
 of
 this,
 one
 part
 has
 such
 a
 principle
 in
 the
 sense
 of
 being
 
obedient
 to
 one,
 the
 other
 in
 the
 sense
 of
 possessing
 one
 and
 exercising
 thought.
 And,
 as
 ‘life
 of
 the
 
rational
 element’
 also
 has
 two
 meanings,
 we
 must
 state
 that
 life
 in
 the
 sense
 of
 activity
 is
 what
 we
 
mean;
 for
 this
 seems
 to
 be
 the
 more
 proper
 sense
 of
 the
 term.
 Now
 if
 the
 function
 of
 man
 is
 an
 
activity
 of
 soul
 which
 follows
 or
 implies
 a
 rational
 principle,
 and
 if
 we
 say
 ‘so-­‐and-­‐so-­‐and
 ‘a
 good
 so-­‐and-­‐
so’
 have
 a
 function
 which
 is
 the
 same
 in
 kind,
 e.g.
 a
 lyre,
 and
 a
 good
 lyre-­‐player,
 and
 so
 without
 

qualification
 in
 all
 cases,
 eminence
 in
 respect
 of
 goodness
 being
 added
 to
 the
 name
 of
 the
 function
 (for
 
the
 function
 of
 a
 lyre-­‐player
 is
 to
 play
 the
 lyre,
 and
 that
 of
 a
 good
 lyre-­‐player
 is
 to
 do
 so
 well):
 if
 this
 is
 
the
 case,
 and
 we
 state
 the
 function
 of
 man
 to
 be
 a
 certain
 kind
 of
 life,
 and
 this
 to
 be
 an
 activity
 or
 
actions
 of
 the
 soul
 implying
 a
 rational
 principle,
 and
 the
 function
 of
 a
 good
 man
 to
 be
 the
 good
 and
 
noble
 performance
 of
 these,
 and
 if
 any
 action
 is
 well
 performed
 when
 it
 is
 performed
 in
 accordance
 with
 
the
 appropriate
 excellence:
 if
 this
 is
 the
 case,
 human
 good
 turns
 out
 to
 be
 activity
 of
 soul
 in
 
accordance
 with
 virtue,
 and
 if
 there
 are
 more
 than
 one
 virtue,
 in
 accordance
 with
 the
 best
 and
 most
 
complete.
 
 

 
But
 we
 must
 add
 ‘in
 a
 complete
 life.’
 For
 one
 swallow
 does
 not
 make
 a
 summer,
 nor
 does
 one
 day;
 and
 
so
 too
 one
 day,
 or
 a
 short
 time,
 does
 not
 make
 a
 man
 blessed
 and
 happy.
 
 

 

BOOK
 II
 

 

1
 
 

 
Virtue,
 then,
 being
 of
 two
 kinds,
 intellectual
 and
 moral,
 intellectual
 virtue
 in
 the
 main
 owes
 both
 its
 birth
 
and
 its
 growth
 to
 teaching
 (for
 which
 reason
 it
 requires
 experience
 and
 time),
 while
 moral
 virtue
 
comes
 about
 as
 a
 result
 of
 habit,
 whence
 also
 its
 name
 (ethike)
 is
 one
 that
 is
 formed
 by
 a
 slight
 variation
 
from
 the
 word
 ethos
 (habit)….
 
[T]he
 virtues
 we
 get
 by
 first
 exercising
 them,
 as
 also
 happens
 in
 the
 case
 of
 the
 arts
 as
 well.
 For
 the
 
things
 we
 have
 to
 learn
 before
 we
 can
 do
 them,
 we
 learn
 by
 doing
 them,
 e.g.
 men
 become
 builders
 by
 
building
 and
 lyre
 players
 by
 playing
 the
 lyre;
 so
 too
 we
 become
 just
 by
 doing
 just
 acts,
 temperate
 by
 
doing
 temperate
 acts,
 brave
 by
 doing
 brave
 acts…
 

 
[B]y
 doing
 the
 acts
 that
 we
 do
 in
 our
 transactions
 with
 other
 men
 we
 become
 just
 or
 unjust,
 and
 by
 
doing
 the
 acts
 that
 we
 do
 in
 the
 presence
 of
 danger,
 and
 being
 habituated
 to
 feel
 fear
 or
 confidence,
 we
 
become
 brave
 or
 cowardly.
 The
 same
 is
 true
 of
 appetites
 and
 feelings
 of
 anger;
 some
 men
 become
 
temperate
 and
 good-­‐tempered,
 others
 self-­‐indulgent
 and
 irascible,
 by
 behaving
 in
 one
 way
 or
 the
 other
 
in
 the
 appropriate
 circumstances.
 Thus,
 in
 one
 word,
 states
 of
 character
 arise
 out
 of
 like
 activities.
 This
 is
 
why
 the
 activities
 we
 exhibit
 must
 be
 of
 a
 certain
 kind;
 it
 is
 because
 the
 states
 of
 character
 correspond
 
to
 the
 differences
 between
 these.
 It
 makes
 no
 small
 difference,
 then,
 whether
 we
 form
 habits
 of
 one
 
kind
 or
 of
 another
 from
 our
 very
 youth;
 it
 makes
 a
 very
 great
 difference,
 or
 rather
 all
 the
 difference.
 
 

 
2
 
 

 
Since,
 then,
 the
 present
 inquiry
 does
 not
 aim
 at
 theoretical
 knowledge
 like
 the
 others
 (for
 we
 are
 
inquiring
 not
 in
 order
 to
 know
 what
 virtue
 is,
 but
 in
 order
 to
 become
 good,
 since
 otherwise
 our
 inquiry
 

would
 have
 been
 of
 no
 use),
 we
 must
 examine
 the
 nature
 of
 actions,
 namely
 how
 we
 ought
 to
 do
 them;
 
for
 these
 determine
 also
 the
 nature
 of
 the
 states
 of
 character
 that
 are
 produced,
 as
 we
 have
 said…
 

 
First,
 then,
 let
 us
 consider
 this,
 that
 it
 is
 the
 nature
 of
 such
 things
 to
 be
 destroyed
 by
 defect
 and
 excess,
 
as
 we
 see
 in
 the
 case
 of
 strength
 and
 of
 health
 (for
 to
 gain
 light
 on
 things
 imperceptible
 we
 must
 use
 the
 
evidence
 of
 sensible
 things);
 both
 excessive
 and
 defective
 exercise
 destroys
 the
 strength,
 and
 similarly
 
drink
 or
 food
 which
 is
 above
 or
 below
 a
 certain
 amount
 destroys
 the
 health,
 while
 that
 which
 is
 
proportionate
 both
 produces
 and
 increases
 and
 preserves
 it.
 So
 too
 is
 it,
 then,
 in
 the
 case
 of
 temperance
 
and
 courage
 and
 the
 other
 virtues.
 For
 the
 man
 who
 flies
 from
 and
 fears
 everything
 and
 does
 not
 stand
 
his
 ground
 against
 anything
 becomes
 a
 coward,
 and
 the
 man
 who
 fears
 nothing
 at
 all
 but
 goes
 to
 
meet
 every
 danger
 becomes
 rash;
 and
 similarly
 the
 man
 who
 indulges
 in
 every
 pleasure
 and
 abstains
 
from
 none
 becomes
 self-­‐indulgent,
 while
 the
 man
 who
 shuns
 every
 pleasure,
 as
 boors
 do,
 becomes
 in
 a
 
way
 insensible;
 temperance
 and
 courage,
 then,
 are
 destroyed
 by
 excess
 and
 defect,
 and
 preserved
 
by
 the
 mean…
 

 
3
 
 

 
We
 must
 take
 as
 a
 sign
 of
 states
 of
 character
 the
 pleasure
 or
 pain
 that
 ensues
 on
 acts;
 for
 the
 man
 who
 
abstains
 from
 bodily
 pleasures
 and
 delights
 in
 this
 very
 fact
 is
 temperate,
 while
 the
 man
 who
 is
 annoyed
 
at
 it
 is
 self-­‐indulgent,
 and
 he
 who
 stands
 his
 ground
 against
 things
 that
 are
 terrible
 and
 delights
 in
 this
 or
 
at
 least
 is
 not
 pained
 is
 brave,
 while
 the
 man
 who
 is
 pained
 is
 a
 coward.
 For
 moral
 excellence
 is
 
concerned
 with
 pleasures
 and
 pains;
 it
 is
 on
 account
 of
 the
 pleasure
 that
 we
 do
 bad
 things,
 and
 on
 
account
 of
 the
 pain
 that
 we
 abstain
 from
 noble
 ones.
 Hence
 we
 ought
 to
 have
 been
 brought
 up
 in
 a
 
particular
 way
 from
 our
 very
 youth,
 as
 Plato
 says,
 so
 as
 both
 to
 delight
 in
 and
 to
 be
 pained
 by
 the
 things
 
that
 we
 ought;
 for
 this
 is
 the
 right
 education…
 

 
Again,
 as
 we
 said
 but
 lately,
 every
 state
 of
 soul
 has
 a
 nature
 relative
 to
 and
 concerned
 with
 the
 kind
 of
 
things
 by
 which
 it
 tends
 to
 be
 made
 worse
 or
 better;
 but
 it
 is
 by
 reason
 of
 pleasures
 and
 pains
 that
 men
 
become
 bad,
 by
 pursuing
 and
 avoiding
 these-­‐
 either
 the
 pleasures
 and
 pains
 they
 ought
 not
 or
 when
 
they
 ought
 not
 or
 as
 they
 ought
 not,
 or
 by
 going
 wrong
 in
 one
 of
 the
 other
 similar
 ways
 that
 may
 be
 
distinguished…We
 assume,
 then,
 that
 this
 kind
 of
 excellence
 tends
 to
 do
 what
 is
 best
 with
 regard
 to
 
pleasures
 and
 pains,
 and
 vice
 does
 the
 contrary…
 

 
That
 virtue,
 then,
 is
 concerned
 with
 pleasures
 and
 pains,
 and
 that
 by
 the
 acts
 from
 which
 it
 arises
 it
 is
 
both
 increased
 and,
 if
 they
 are
 done
 differently,
 destroyed,
 and
 that
 the
 acts
 from
 which
 it
 arose
 
are
 those
 in
 which
 it
 actualizes
 itself-­‐
 let
 this
 be
 taken
 as
 said.
 
 

 
4
 
 

 
The
 question
 might
 be
 asked,
 what
 we
 mean
 by
 saying
 that
 we
 must
 become
 just
 by
 doing
 just
 acts,
 and
 
temperate
 by
 doing
 temperate
 acts;
 for
 if
 men
 do
 just
 and
 temperate
 acts,
 they
 are
 already
 just
 and
 
temperate,
 exactly
 as,
 if
 they
 do
 what
 is
 in
 accordance
 with
 the
 laws
 of
 grammar
 and
 of
 music,
 they
 are
 

grammarians
 and
 musicians…
 

 
Again,
 the
 case
 of
 the
 arts
 and
 that
 of
 the
 virtues
 are
 not
 similar;
 for
 the
 products
 of
 the
 arts
 have
 their
 
goodness
 in
 themselves,
 so
 that
 it
 is
 enough
 that
 they
 should
 have
 a
 certain
 character,
 but
 if
 the
 
acts
 that
 are
 in
 accordance
 with
 the
 virtues
 have
 themselves
 a
 certain
 character
 it
 does
 not
 follow
 that
 
they
 are
 done
 justly
 or
 temperately.
 The
 agent
 also
 must
 be
 in
 a
 certain
 condition
 when
 he
 does
 them;
 
in
 the
 first
 place
 he
 must
 have
 knowledge,
 secondly
 he
 must
 choose
 the
 acts,
 and
 choose
 them
 for
 their
 
own
 sakes,
 and
 thirdly
 his
 action
 must
 proceed
 from
 a
 firm
 and
 unchangeable
 character…
 

 
Actions,
 then,
 are
 called
 just
 and
 temperate
 when
 they
 are
 such
 as
 the
 just
 or
 the
 temperate
 man
 would
 
do;
 but
 it
 is
 not
 the
 man
 who
 does
 these
 that
 is
 just
 and
 temperate,
 but
 the
 man
 who
 also
 does
 them
 as
 
just
 and
 temperate
 men
 do
 them.
 It
 is
 well
 said,
 then,
 that
 it
 is
 by
 doing
 just
 acts
 that
 the
 just
 man
 is
 
produced,
 and
 by
 doing
 temperate
 acts
 the
 temperate
 man;
 without
 doing
 these
 no
 one
 would
 have
 
even
 a
 prospect
 of
 becoming
 good.
 
 

 
But
 most
 people
 do
 not
 do
 these,
 but
 take
 refuge
 in
 theory
 and
 think
 they
 are
 being
 philosophers
 and
 
will
 become
 good
 in
 this
 way,
 behaving
 somewhat
 like
 patients
 who
 listen
 attentively
 to
 their
 doctors,
 
but
 do
 none
 of
 the
 things
 they
 are
 ordered
 to
 do.
 As
 the
 latter
 will
 not
 be
 made
 well
 in
 body
 by
 such
 a
 
course
 of
 treatment,
 the
 former
 will
 not
 be
 made
 well
 in
 soul
 by
 such
 a
 course
 of
 philosophy.
 
 

 
6
 
 

 
We
 must,
 however,
 not
 only
 describe
 virtue
 as
 a
 state
 of
 character,
 but
 also
 say
 what
 sort
 of
 state
 it
 is.
 
We
 may
 remark,
 then,
 that
 every
 virtue
 or
 excellence
 both
 brings
 into
 good
 condition
 the
 thing
 of
 
which
 it
 is
 the
 excellence
 and
 makes
 the
 work
 of
 that
 thing
 be
 done
 well;
 e.g.
 the
 excellence
 of
 the
 eye
 
makes
 both
 the
 eye
 and
 its
 work
 good;
 for
 it
 is
 by
 the
 excellence
 of
 the
 eye
 that
 we
 see
 well.
 Similarly
 
the
 excellence
 of
 the
 horse
 makes
 a
 horse
 both
 good
 in
 itself
 and
 good
 at
 running
 and
 at
 carrying
 its
 
rider
 and
 at
 awaiting
 the
 attack
 of
 the
 enemy.
 Therefore,
 if
 this
 is
 true
 in
 every
 case,
 the
 virtue
 of
 man
 
also
 will
 be
 the
 state
 of
 character
 which
 makes
 a
 man
 good
 and
 which
 makes
 him
 do
 his
 own
 work
 well.
 
 

 
How
 this
 is
 to
 happen
 we
 have
 stated
 already,
 but
 it
 will
 be
 made
 plain
 also
 by
 the
 following
 
consideration
 of
 the
 specific
 nature
 of
 virtue.
 In
 everything
 that
 is
 continuous
 and
 divisible
 it
 is
 possible
 
to
 take
 more,
 less,
 or
 an
 equal
 amount,
 and
 that
 either
 in
 terms
 of
 the
 thing
 itself
 or
 relatively
 to
 us;
 and
 
the
 equal
 is
 an
 intermediate
 between
 excess
 and
 defect.
 By
 the
 intermediate
 in
 the
 object
 I
 mean
 that
 
which
 is
 equidistant
 from
 each
 of
 the
 extremes,
 which
 is
 one
 and
 the
 same
 for
 all
 men;
 by
 
the
 intermediate
 relatively
 to
 us
 that
 which
 is
 neither
 too
 much
 nor
 too
 little-­‐
 and
 this
 is
 not
 one,
 nor
 
the
 same
 for
 all.
 For
 instance,
 if
 ten
 is
 many
 and
 two
 is
 few,
 six
 is
 the
 intermediate,
 taken
 in
 terms
 of
 the
 
object;
 for
 it
 exceeds
 and
 is
 exceeded
 by
 an
 equal
 amount;
 this
 is
 intermediate
 according
 to
 arithmetical
 
proportion.
 But
 the
 intermediate
 relatively
 to
 us
 is
 not
 to
 be
 taken
 so;
 if
 ten
 pounds
 are
 too
 much
 for
 a
 
particular
 person
 to
 eat
 and
 two
 too
 little,
 it
 does
 not
 follow
 that
 the
 trainer
 will
 order
 six
 pounds;
 for
 
this
 also
 is
 perhaps
 too
 much
 for
 the
 person
 who
 is
 to
 take
 it,
 or
 too
 little-­‐
 too
 little
 for
 Milo,
 too
 much
 
for
 the
 beginner
 in
 athletic
 exercises.
 The
 same
 is
 true
 of
 running
 and
 wrestling.
 Thus
 a
 master
 of
 any
 art
 

avoids
 excess
 and
 defect,
 but
 seeks
 the
 intermediate
 and
 chooses
 this-­‐
 the
 intermediate
 not
 in
 the
 
object
 but
 relatively
 to
 us.
 
 

 
If
 it
 is
 thus,
 then,
 that
 every
 art
 does
 its
 work
 well-­‐
 by
 looking
 to
 the
 intermediate
 and
 judging
 its
 works
 
by
 this
 standard…[A]nd
 if,
 further,
 virtue
 is
 more
 exact
 and
 better
 than
 any
 art…,
 then
 virtue
 must
 have
 
the
 quality
 of
 aiming
 at
 the
 intermediate.
 I
 mean
 moral
 virtue;
 for
 it
 is
 this
 that
 is
 concerned
 with
 
passions
 and
 actions,
 and
 in
 these
 there
 is
 excess,
 defect,
 and
 the
 intermediate.
 For
 instance,
 both
 fear
 
and
 confidence
 and
 appetite
 and
 anger
 and
 pity
 and
 in
 general
 pleasure
 and
 pain
 may
 be
 felt
 both
 
too
 much
 and
 too
 little,
 and
 in
 both
 cases
 not
 well;
 but
 to
 feel
 them
 at
 the
 right
 times,
 with
 reference
 to
 
the
 right
 objects,
 towards
 the
 right
 people,
 with
 the
 right
 motive,
 and
 in
 the
 right
 way,
 is
 what
 is
 both
 
intermediate
 and
 best,
 and
 this
 is
 characteristic
 of
 virtue.
 Similarly
 with
 regard
 to
 actions
 also
 there
 is
 
excess,
 defect,
 and
 the
 intermediate.
 Now
 virtue
 is
 concerned
 with
 passions
 and
 actions,
 in
 which
 excess
 
is
 a
 form
 of
 failure,
 and
 so
 is
 defect,
 while
 the
 intermediate
 is
 praised
 and
 is
 a
 form
 of
 success;
 and
 being
 
praised
 and
 being
 successful
 are
 both
 characteristics
 of
 virtue.
 Therefore
 virtue
 is
 a
 kind
 of
 mean,
 since,
 
as
 we
 have
 seen,
 it
 aims
 at
 what
 is
 intermediate.
 
 

 
Again,
 it
 is
 possible
 to
 fail
 in
 many
 ways…while
 to
 succeed
 is
 possible
 only
 in
 one
 way
 (for
 which
 reason
 
also
 one
 is
 easy
 and
 the
 other
 difficult-­‐
 to
 miss
 the
 mark
 easy,
 to
 hit
 it
 difficult);
 for
 these
 reasons
 also,
 
then,
 excess
 and
 defect
 are
 characteristic
 of
 vice,
 and
 the
 mean
 of
 virtue;
 
 

 
For
 men
 are
 good
 in
 but
 one
 way,
 but
 bad
 in
 many.
 
 

 
Virtue,
 then,
 is
 a
 state
 of
 character
 concerned
 with
 choice,
 lying
 in
 a
 mean,
 i.e.
 the
 mean
 relative
 to
 us,
 
this
 being
 determined
 by
 a
 rational
 principle,
 and
 by
 that
 principle
 by
 which
 the
 man
 of
 practical
 wisdom
 
would
 determine
 it.
 Now
 it
 is
 a
 mean
 between
 two
 vices,
 that
 which
 depends
 on
 excess
 and
 that
 which
 
depends
 on
 defect;
 and
 again
 it
 is
 a
 mean
 because
 the
 vices
 respectively
 fall
 short
 of
 or
 exceed
 what
 is
 
right
 in
 both
 passions
 and
 actions,
 while
 virtue
 both
 finds
 and
 chooses
 that
 which
 is
 intermediate.
 Hence
 
in
 respect
 of
 its
 substance
 and
 the
 definition
 which
 states
 its
 essence
 virtue
 is
 a
 mean,
 with
 regard
 to
 
what
 is
 best
 and
 right
 an
 extreme.
 
 

 

Provided
 by
 The
 Internet
 Classics
 Archive.
 Available
 online
 at
 
 
 
 
 
http://classics.mit.edu//Aristotle/nicomachaen.html
 
 

1 Introducing Philosophy

“It is the mark of an educated mind
to be able to entertain a thought

without accepting it”
—Aristotle

©Terry Why/ Getty Images

6 Traditional Theories of Ethics

You have your way. I have my way. As for
the right way, the correct way, and the only

way, it does not exist.
—Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spake Zarathustra

Federico Caputo/iStock/Thinkstock

mos81165_06_c06.indd 175 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section

6.1 How Should One Act?

Learning Objectives

After reading this chapter, students will be able to:

1. Characterize the classical theories of ethics—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics.

2. Identify some of the problems these theories confront.

3. Describe other metaethical views, such as relativism and egoism.

4. Apply ethical theories to problems that affect both individuals and larger groups, including
environmental challenges.

What We Will Discover

• Philosophers have developed theories to provide support for our claims about right and
wrong.

• Other theories such as egoism and relativism offer alternatives to traditional theories of
ethics.

• Ethics has many specific applications to our lives, from the very personal and specific to
those that affect everyone in society.

6.1 How Should One Act?

Ethics, or moral philosophy, investigates how we can evaluate our behavior in terms of right and wrong, good and bad—in other words, how we
determine what we should do, what we should not
do, and how to tell the difference. After looking at
the three classical ethical views that philosophers have
presented and some of the problems with these theo-
ries, we will explore some alternative approaches.

Utilitarianism

Suppose you and five of your friends are hanging out
one night and decide to order a pizza. You are all
equally hungry and decide to order two pizzas, each
of which has six slices. Thus, when the pizzas are
delivered, it is pretty easy to determine how to divide
the pizzas in a way that is the fairest: Everyone gets
two slices. It may be that one person wanted a third
slice, and someone else may have only wanted one.
Yet without knowing anything else, this arrange-
ment, more than any other, will be the most benefi-
cial to the greatest number of people.

This simple example demonstrates the basic notion at
the heart of the ethical doctrine known as utilitari-
anism. Often associated with the philosophers Jer-
emy Bentham (1748–1822) and John Stuart Mill, utilitarianism offers a very straightforward and
direct way to evaluate behavior. When given a choice between two acts, utilitarianism states that

Photos.com/© Getty Images/Thinkstock

Jeremy Bentham is associated with the
founding of utilitarianism, which states
that given a choice between two acts,
the one that creates greater happiness
for the greatest number of people should
be chosen.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 176 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Read more of
John Stuart
Mill’s ideas

on this topic
in his work

Utilitarianism
in the

Chapter
Readings

section of the

Appendix.

the act that should be chosen is the one that creates the greatest amount of happiness for
the greatest number of people. Philosophers (and economists) often use the term utility
to express this quality. Utility is the satisfaction one gets from something. For instance, if
you like chocolate ice cream more than vanilla ice cream, we can say that chocolate ice
cream has a higher utility for you, relative to vanilla ice cream. In theory, at least, each of
us can rank all of our choices according to a scale that indicates our relative preferences.
Some philosophers, such as Bentham, even attempted to assign numbers to these prefer-
ences. If someone likes chocolate ice cream five times as much as vanilla ice cream, that
person would presumably be willing to accept five vanilla ice cream cones as a substitute
for one chocolate ice cream cone. It should also be noted that utility is regarded in terms
of net utility: The correct moral choice is that which generates the greatest good and also
minimizes unhappiness.

Because utilitarianism considers an act’s consequences in assessing its morality, utilitarian-
ism is also regarded as a consequentialist theory. The basic idea in consequentialism is
to consider the consequences that will result from the choices one confronts: If the conse-
quences of one act produce the greatest net good—or the highest utility—for the great-
est number of people, this is the act one should carry out. Many people find this to be a
rather obvious ethical viewpoint; clearly if we had decided to give all the pizza slices to just
three people and no slices to the other three, this would seem rather unfair. It should also
be clear that utilitarianism offers an approach to scenarios other than distributing pizza
and ice cream. Imagine Mary really loves to dance, but she does not get to go dancing
very often. Mary has three children, with whom she enjoys spending time and who enjoy
spending time with her. One night she is given the option of staying home and spending
time with her children or going dancing. What should she do? The utilitarian might argue
that, on the one hand, the pleasure Mary gets from dancing is greater than staying with
her children. Yet on the other hand, her children will receive great pleasure if she does not
go dancing. Therefore, the “utility calculation” is that the net happiness of Mary and her
three children will be higher if she stays home, even though Mary’s individual happiness
might be slightly lower than it would have been if she had chosen to go dancing.

Utility is often described in terms of pleasure, which can be problematic for utilitarian-
ism. Imagine someone finds pleasure in playing video games and drinking beer all day
long. Given a choice between, say, helping out in a homeless shelter or drinking and
playing the newest video game, a person may well choose the latter, which suggests to
some that utilitarianism has no way to distinguish between different kinds of pleasures.
Presumably, we want our theory to be able to make a distinction between hedonistic and
nobler pleasures. Mill saw this as a potential problem and insisted that pleasure should be
considered not just in terms of quantity but also quality: that certain kinds of pleasures,
or certain ways of satisfying desires, are simply better than others. A pig may be happy
rolling around in the mud and eating garbage, but Mill insisted that people who take that
approach to pleasure fail to develop their potential as human beings (relative to pigs, at
least). According to Mill, it is better to be a dissatisfied Socrates than a satisfied pig. This is
not to say that one should always choose something less pleasurable; rather, it is simply an
indication that pleasures themselves can, or perhaps should, be distinguished from each
other. It is not always easy to say that one pleasure is “superior” to another, and certainly
people have long argued about this issue. However, these kinds of examples indicate a
problem utilitarianism confronts if we evaluate acts solely in terms of their pleasurable
consequences (Mill, 1909).

mos81165_06_c06.indd 177 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Many people find utilitarianism to be an easy and useful approach to making ethical decisions.
When distributing goods, services, or even time, it would seem to be a “no-brainer” to choose
the option that would satisfy or please as many people as possible, compared to any other avail-
able choice. However, philosophers have raised a number of problems in response to utilitarian-
ism, which may make it a less plausible ethical theory than it first appears.

Problems With Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism has what philosophers call an intuitive appeal: It seems to be relatively obvious,
and just plain common sense, to evaluate our actions based on the results those actions pro-
duce. If all we know about a situation is that four kids in a sandbox have one toy, the best option
would be for the children to share that toy, even if each child is quite sure he or she would get
the most pleasure from playing with it alone.

However, many philosophers have objected to utilitarianism, and for a number of reasons. As
we have seen, distinguishing different kinds of pleasures from each other can be difficult. Does
utilitarianism have any way to address the situation of a person who gets pleasure from staring
at the wall or doing something else that most people would find quite unpleasant (something
often called masochism)? Mill (1863) suggests there are “higher” or “more refined” pleasures
and that they should be preferred, but who is to say which is a “higher” pleasure? Is reading
poetry somehow better than watching soap operas? What if someone gains pleasure by sleep-
ing all the time or hitting his thumb over and over with a hammer?

More significant objections to utilitarianism have been posed on the basis of calculating the out-
come, or consequences, of a choice. Suppose you are on a cruise ship that catches fire; you and
19 others are lucky enough to survive on a lifeboat. There is enough water to last for a week or
more, but you have no food and do not know whether you will be rescued. Everyone is aware
of how grim the future looks; as the boat drifts, everyone gets hungrier. It becomes apparent
that everyone is going to die unless your group finds food. The utilitarian in the group poses
the following options: All 20 people die, or 19 people live if one person is killed and eaten! To
justify his position, he cites historical examples of similar cases in which cannibalism helped the
majority survive. However, while this scenario may appear to result in the greatest good for the
greatest number, do we really want an ethical theory that not only allows cannibalism, but actu-
ally endorses it as the fairest and most ethical decision?

Few of us are likely to experience a situation this extreme, but we may find ourselves in situations
where the basic utilitarian calculation actually leads to results that are very unfair and unjust. This
is particularly threatening anytime individuals find themselves in a minority, whether because
of their sex, race, ethnicity, religion, sexual orientation, or any of the other ways in which soci-
ety categorizes people. For example, suppose a local grade school must decide if it should use
taxpayer money to build ramps to make the building accessible to students in wheelchairs. This
tax will likely decrease the pleasure of each taxpayer and may only be used by a few individuals
throughout the year. In this way it would result in a net utility that would favor a decision not to
build the ramps. Would you consider this a fair outcome?

mos81165_06_c06.indd 178 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Tyranny of the Majority
Dating as far back as Plato, political philosophers have often cited the tyranny of the majority,
which is when the interests of the majority are placed above the interests of the minority, and
to their detriment. American history is littered with such stories, whether the minority groups
be African Americans, Native Americans, Jews, homosexuals, or many others. In the original,
Protestant-dominated colonies, for example, Roman Catholics were not allowed to vote or hold
public office. Despite the obvious injustice, this would seem to fit the utilitarian calculation,
because Catholics were a minority at that time. This kind of calculation has been used to jus-
tify a wide range of policies that seem wrong, from slavery to refusing to sell houses in certain
neighborhoods to ethnic and racial minorities. Interestingly, women have also suffered for similar
reasons on the basis of this kind of calculation, despite the fact that they actually make up the
majority of the population.

Mill’s Response
John Stuart Mill and other utilitarians recognized the flaws in an ethical system that had such
unethical and oppressive results. One popular way of addressing these flaws has been to dis-
tinguish between act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism. Act utilitarianism simply involves a
judgment of the act’s consequences: Given a set of choices, which act generates the greatest net
good for the greatest number? Rule utilitarianism, on the other hand, involves an evaluation
of the types of acts involved and proposes that, when followed as a general rule, the act should
produce the greatest net good, or the greatest amount of happiness, for the greatest number.

Great Ideas: The Trolley Problem

A very famous challenge to our ethical intuitions, originated by Philippa Foot, is easy to describe but
more problematic to solve. In Foot’s 1967 essay “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the
Double Effect,” she posed the following scenario known as the trolley problem:

Imagine a runaway trolley hurtling toward five workers on the track. The driver must choose between
staying the course, which would result in the death of the five workers, or divert the trolley to a spur
where just one worker on the track would be killed. Most would say that diverting the trolley to save
five lives while killing only one would be the better of the two options.

Now imagine a similar scenario: What if a doctor could save the lives of five people who needed organ
donations by killing one patient and distributing his organs? Would that be considered a moral act?
If not, why would it be moral to kill the one track worker, but not the one patient? There are many
variations on this basic scenario, which has generated a great deal of debate and discussion.

Reflection Questions:

With this in mind, consider the following questions:

1. Try to posit a situation where it would seem moral to kill (or allow to die) one person in
order to save five people’s lives.

2. What is the relevant moral difference—if there is one—between killing someone and allow-
ing someone to die?

3. Does it make a difference if one could save twenty people by sacrificing one person’s life?
One hundred? One thousand? At what point might our views change due to the relation-
ship between the one person sacrificed and the number of people saved?

mos81165_06_c06.indd 179 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Consider the following example: Bob is taking an important physics test that he needs to pass
to get into medical school. He considers the possibility that if he cheats “successfully,” he gains
a great deal and thus achieves his greatest happiness, or “maximizes his utility” (we will ignore
any feelings of guilt Bob may have). The act utilitarian would suggest that, in this case, cheating
produces the greatest amount of good. The rule utilitarian would offer a different analysis. Bob
may gain the most by cheating, but in general, we could not promote the rule that one should
cheat. If we endorse a rule that says it is okay to cheat to get into medical school, then the rest of
society would be considerably less confident that physicians were trustworthy and deserved their
credentials. This would fail to generate the greatest good for the greatest number; therefore, the
rule utilitarian would tell Bob not to cheat.

Rule utilitarianism seems to have a better chance of dealing with some of the more obvious
objections we have seen, although it is not entirely clear whether it can successfully treat the
problem of a minority being oppressed by a majority. Mill (1909) seemed to advocate a system
of “proportionate representation,” so minorities would be at least represented, but it is not clear
how this solves the problem. Other objections have also been raised against both act and rule
utilitarianism. For instance, when measuring pleasure, or utility, what time frame should be used:
days, years, decades? Who is included in the idea of the “greatest number”—our family, our
community, our country, our planet? How can one compare one person’s amount of pleasure
with another person’s? Can we really even measure pleasure, or happiness, or utility in a way
that allows us to make these utilitarian calculations?

These are difficult questions to answer, and many philosophers have seen this as a reason to look
elsewhere for a moral theory, one that does not evaluate acts in terms of consequences and does
not measure such things as happiness and utility. The most famous alternative to utilitarianism is
deontology, which is a nonconsequentialist theory.

Deontology

Deontological ethics is usually associated with the philosopher Immanuel Kant. Deontology
comes from the Greek word for “obligation” (or “duty”). In contrast to consequentialist theo-
ries, Kant, and more generally the deontologist, ignores an act’s consequences when evaluating
whether it is a good, bad, or morally neutral act. It is important to remember that deontologists
do not deny that acts have consequences; their point is that those consequences should not
play a role in evaluating the act’s morality. Rather, deontological ethics focuses on the will of the
person acting, the person’s intention in carrying out the act, and particularly, the rule according
to which the act is carried out. Deontology focuses on the duties and obligations one has in car-
rying out actions rather than on the consequences of those actions.

In his Critique of Practical Reason, Kant (1997) claimed that certain kinds of rules established
what he called a categorical imperative. This is a requirement or demand (imperative), and it
has no exceptions (it is categorical). We might contrast this kind of imperative with what Kant
calls a hypothetical imperative, which is illustrated by supposing you are hungry and decide to
eat something; in this case the action (eating) is designed to achieve a goal (making you less
hungry). Yet there is no obligation or demand that you eat; it is just what you do in this specific
situation. Similarly, if you want to pass a course, a hypothetical imperative might tell you to
study. In short, if someone adopts a certain goal, then actions that help achieve that goal are to
be adopted. The categorical imperative, on the other hand, has no exceptions and is something
one must do. As part of the categorical imperative, Kant assumes that being a moral person is a
requirement; it is not merely a goal people may choose to strive for.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 180 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Read
Immanuel

Kant’s
Fundamental

Principles
of the

Metaphysics
of Morals in
the Chapter

Readings
section of the

Appendix.

Kant offers several versions of the categorical imperative. We will look at the first two,
which will give us a rough idea of what kind of rule it is.

1. Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time want that
it should become a universal law. That is, if you choose to do something, would
you desire that everyone in that same circumstance do exactly the same thing?

2. Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, always at the same time as an end and never merely as a
means to an end. In other words, all people—including you—deserve respect. It
would always be wrong to treat people as objects, or as a way of achieving some
goal, or in another way that does not show respect. (Kant 1997, 1998)

These rules may sound similar to that very famous and old Golden Rule: “Do unto others
as you would have them do unto you.” The Golden Rule can be found in many different
civilizations, beginning with the ancient Egyptians and the ancient Greeks, as well as in
many religions, including Buddhism, Christianity, Judaism, and Islam. Yet there is a crucial
distinction that Kant notes between the Golden Rule and the categorical imperative. Kant
insists that rational agents should act in such a way that the rule they adopt can be fol-
lowed universally, or by all rational agents. Otherwise, someone who might enjoy pain (a
masochist) or enjoys inflicting pain (a sadist) might well be following the Golden Rule by
treating others as he or she would like to be treated.

Despite the distinction, there are many circumstances in which the categorical imperative
and the Golden Rule lead to similar results. You do not want to be treated by others as
some kind of “thing,” so you yourself should not treat others that way. This last claim is
essentially what Kant provides as the second version of the categorical imperative.

As we have seen, a simple utilitarian calculation has an intuitive appeal in that it seems
fairly obvious to evaluate an act in terms of whether it produces the greatest net good for
the greatest number. An indication that universal rules of behavior have their own intuitive
appeal is borne out by the number of parents who use such rules with their children. For
example, suppose a mother observes her daughter not sharing a toy with several other
children; she is likely to take her daughter aside and ask, “How would you like it if no
one shared toys with you?” The daughter, of course, would not like it, and—the mother
hopes—the little girl will begin to understand that if she does not like to be treated in a
certain way, then she should not treat others in that way. This question—”How would you
like it if others treated you that way?”—is probably something all of us have heard before
and is indicative of how familiar we are with this version of deontological ethics.

Despite their differences, utilitarianism and deontology often come to the same conclu-
sion, but from alternate directions. In the example of a group of children having one toy
among them, the utilitarian would argue that the greatest net good for the greatest num-
ber is achieved by sharing the toy. The deontologist, on the other hand, would argue that
people should treat others with the same respect they expect to be given, and that is best
achieved by sharing the toy. They both conclude that the children should share, but one
draws this conclusion by looking at the results, whereas the other draws the same conclu-
sion by looking at the rule that should be followed. At the same time, other actions may
generate conflicts between the two perspectives. For instance, a deontologist may adopt
as the universal rule “Never steal.” Yet imagine a family that has no food; the deontologist
may be forced to conclude that it would be wrong for the father to steal food to feed his

mos81165_06_c06.indd 181 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

family. The utilitarian, in contrast, calculates that the unhappiness of the person from whom the
food was stolen is not as great as the happiness achieved by the family getting food. Thus, the
utilitarian may well argue that in this case stealing is not wrong because it produces the greatest
good for the greatest number.

Both utilitarianism and deontology have certain advantages. Utilitarian calculations are, at least
at first glance, fairly easy to devise and provide a quick way to evaluate the moral worth of an
act. Deontology, on the other hand, has the appeal of being easily explained and develops rules
that seem to make sense and are also widely applied. We have already seen that utilitarianism
confronts certain problems that expose how it may lead to results that appear unfair and unjust;
we can now look at some similar kinds of problems that face the deontologist.

Problems With Deontology

Traditionally, critics of deontology have focused on two specific but related issues. First, deontol-
ogy—particularly the Kantian version—seems too sterile and fails to capture some of the com-
plex issues that arise when we confront ethical problems in real life. The second issue (which may
be a result of the first) is that deontology may require one to act in a way that seems obviously
wrong and unethical. As we saw with utilitarianism, any ethical theory that leads to potentially
unethical results is problematic.

We have seen the best known versions of Kant’s categorical imperative: That is, you should
never treat others only as a means to achieve your goals, and you should only do something if
everyone in that same situation would act the same way. The repeated use of the word should
indicates these are normative demands, or moral claims.

In some scenarios, the right course of action seems obvious. Just because you are late for a
movie, you should not run over someone with your car on your way to the theater. No one in a
similar situation should do so either. Following the Golden Rule would lead to the same result;
after all, you would not want to be run over by someone rushing to get to the movies, so you
should not run over someone to do so. Yet are there situations in which these kinds of rules
result in actions that are wrong or even immoral?

The most famous objection to the deontologist’s approach—specifically Kant’s—is the problem
posed by lying. Lying is, of course, intentionally misleading someone to think something is true
when it is false, or false when it is true. Children are taught at an early age never to lie, and most
moral systems prohibit or at least discourage lying. Often, the Ninth Commandment given in
the book of Exodus, “Thou shalt not bear false witness against thy neighbour” (Exodus 20:16),
is interpreted to mean that lying is always wrong. Lying also seems to be a clear example of the
categorical imperative: To lie to someone is to treat them with insufficient respect as a human
being, and since we presumably do not want to be lied to, we should not lie to others.

Still, people lie to each other quite a lot, and often to achieve goals that seem to be appropriate
and moral (or at least not immoral). Consider the following four examples:

1. A husband buys a new shirt that he likes very much and asks his wife if it makes him
look fat. In truth, the shirt does make him look fat. Should the wife tell her husband
the truth? (The wife might avoid lying by not answering, but this may itself indicate her
opinion.)

2. Dan and his friends are throwing an elaborate surprise party for Jody. Jody gets suspi-
cious and asks Dan, “Are you throwing me a surprise party?” If Dan tells the truth, the

mos81165_06_c06.indd 182 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

surprise party is ruined, and all their efforts will have been wasted. Should Dan lie to
Jody?

3. Parents in the United States often tell their children made-up stories, not just about a
jolly fat man who brings them presents at Christmastime, but also about a rabbit that
brings candy at Easter and even a fairy who “buys” the teeth they have lost. Should
parents always tell their children the truth about Santa Claus, the Easter bunny, and
the tooth fairy?

4. Sarah comes to your door and asks you to hide her from an ax-wielding stalker. You
agree without hesitation. Shortly thereafter, a wild-eyed man, holding an ax, asks you
if you have hidden Sarah. Do you tell him the truth? (It is important to note that you
are not being threatened; the man holding the ax asks about Sarah in a very polite and
respectful manner.)

We started with what seemed to be a good, widely accepted rule: “Never lie.” Yet the preced-
ing examples illustrate the complexity of applying this rule. Do the people who lie in the above
examples act immorally? The wife does not want to make her husband feel bad; Dan wants to
make sure Jody enjoys her surprise; parents want their children to be captivated by Santa Claus
and provide incentive for good behavior; and lying to an ax-wielding stalker might save Sarah’s
life.

Kant’s stern rule about never lying, then, seems to force everyone in the above cases to do
something they would prefer not to do. Perhaps the husband, Jody, the children, and the stalker
would prefer to be lied to? One might tinker with Kant’s rule, or suggest that one should not ask
questions unless one expects to be told the truth. One might also say that children are special
cases and have not reached the age where we are always honest with them. Yet this logic results
in a rule that is even more convoluted: “Never lie,” morphs into something like, “Never lie to
those over a certain age, and hope no one asks you questions they really would prefer not be
answered truthfully.” Even this variation on the rule may be problematic; we can probably think
of examples where lying seems to be the right thing to do. Formulating a rule that allows for
those examples is a difficult task.

We have seen the advantages of utilitarianism and deontology, as well as some of their prob-
lems. One other classical, or traditional, theory remains; it does not look at the consequences of
our acts (as in utilitarianism, or consequentialism) or at the acts themselves and the rules that
guide those acts (as in deontology, or nonconsequentialism). Rather, it looks at the character of
the person acting. This is a theory known as virtue ethics.

Virtue Ethics

Virtue ethics is an approach to moral and ethical questions that focuses on a person’s character.
Some discussion of this concept can be found in the writings of Plato, as well as in the teachings
of Chinese philosophers such as Confucius (551–479 bce). However, the classic conception of
virtue ethics in Western philosophy is attributed to Aristotle. For Aristotle, the virtuous person,
or the person of virtuous character, is someone who has admirable characteristics and displays
them in a way that is balanced and harmonious. This person seeks to have an ideal character,
and the virtues that contribute to this goal will all be appropriately related to each other. Ulti-
mately, the person with practical or moral wisdom—what Aristotle calls phronesis—will have
the appropriate virtues, will know how to use them, and will possess moral excellence. Such a
person will achieve the specific kind of happiness Aristotle describes as human flourishing.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 183 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Read more
about virtue

ethics in
Aristotle’s

Nicomachean
Ethics in

the Chapter
Readings

section of the
Appendix.

Some of these virtues are traditional characteristics that we still use to describe a good,
moral, or virtuous person, including courage, generosity, and being a good friend. Accord-
ing to Aristotle, a person may have too little courage, which we would call cowardice.
Another person may have too much courage, resulting in rash behavior. A soldier who
runs from the field of battle when first confronting the enemy might not have enough
courage, whereas the soldier who runs straight into machine-gun fire may have too much.
Aristotle insists that the virtuous person will have the right amount of courage and will
aim at what he calls the golden mean between having too little and having too much
of a given characteristic. Thus, someone who displays little generosity will fall on one end
of the spectrum (miserly); someone who is much too generous will fall on the opposite
end (wasteful); and a moderately generous person falls in the middle and is virtuous. The
person who has the requisite moral wisdom, or phronesis, will know how to act in a given
situation, and those acts will be in harmony with the other virtues that make up this per-
son’s character.

Aristotle also describes two virtues that are a bit more complex. One of these he calls
temperance, or sophrosunë (Aristotle, 2002). A temperate person is moderate and has
self-control. This person is able to control his or her emotions through reason and does not
indulge in the extreme. When it comes to drinking wine, the intemperate person will drink
too much of it, whereas the person who rejects it entirely, in spite of finding it enjoyable,
is regarded as insensible. Temperance, then, is a middle ground between the two excesses
of insensibility and intemperance.

Aristotle also describes a virtue he calls magnanimity, which is how we see ourselves and
how we are regarded by others (Aristotle, 2002). This can involve the respect others give
us and also the kinds of rewards and honors we can receive. Along with justice, Aristotle
considered this to be the highest virtue. Magnanimity is translated from the Greek word
megalopsuchia, which literally means “great soul” or “great mind.” This is a person who
represents excellence, is worthy of being honored by others, and knows that he or she
is worthy. Neither arrogant nor falsely modest, the virtuous person demonstrates mag-
nanimity, and as a virtue, it is possessed in a reasonable amount. People who think too
highly of themselves or who think they deserve more recognition than they actually do
are considered vain. On the other hand, those who believe they deserve no recognition
or appreciation when the opposite is likely true have too little magnanimity, a characteris-
tic Aristotle calls “low-minded.” We might call such a person too self-effacing, or falsely
modest. The truly magnanimous person has this virtue in its proper proportion; such a per-
son will be appropriately modest while appropriately proud of his or her accomplishments.

To see how virtues might interact with and balance against one another, consider the fol-
lowing example. Suppose Nick likes to go to parties, but he drinks too much and acts as if
he is everyone’s best friend. One night a fight breaks out, and Nick tries to stop it by fight-
ing with everyone involved in the original fight. Nick is unable to keep his desires in check
by practical reason; does not live in accordance with the golden mean, and he indulges in
excess. In contrast, Ted never goes to parties; he stays home alone and never has any fun.
Once, when he saw someone steal an elderly woman’s purse, he ran in the opposite direc-
tion. Ted also does not have his desires by reason, does not live in accordance with the
golden mean, and disproportionately deprives himself. Neither Nick nor Ted would qualify
as having a virtuous character. Jennifer, on the other hand, is a good friend; she is coura-
geous; she is modest but takes pride in what she does and accepts the legitimate praise
of others; and she is generous, honest, and moderate. She has what the Greeks called

mos81165_06_c06.indd 184 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

eudaimonia, which can be translated in a variety of ways, including happiness, flourishing, and
well-being. Aristotle would say that because Jennifer’s virtues are in their proper balance and
proportion, she has eudaimonia.

It is easy to get lost in Aristotle’s technical vocabulary, but his basic point is that the person who
makes the right moral choices, or behaves ethically, is a virtuous person and is the kind of person
we admire for that reason. We object to those who are deficient in one or more of the char-
acteristics we have mentioned, but we also object to those who display one or more of these
attributes excessively. The person who has eudaimonia is the person who has acquired the cor-
rect conception of the virtues, individually and as a whole, and as such, offers us an example of
what kinds of moral choices should be made. We may not actually know of such a person, and
indeed such a person may not actually exist. However, the conception of such a virtuous person
helps us examine our own choices and behavior to see where we are doing the right thing and
where we may need improvement.

As is often the case with ethical theories, virtue ethics initially sounds clear, obvious, and easy to
apply. But just as challenges exist to both utilitarianism and deontology, certain problems arise
for proponents of virtue ethics.

Problems With Virtue Ethics

Virtue ethics differs from utilitarianism and deontology in that it examines not what a person
does, but what kind of character he or she has. In addition to the virtues, this theory provides us
with a spectrum on which to moderate our own behavior, as well as an ideal for which to strive.
Applying these notions in real-world examples is more difficult than it would initially appear,
however.

For example, consider one of Aristotle’s specific virtues, courage. While it is easy to imagine
plenty of scenarios in which someone has an excess of courage or a lack of sufficient courage,
it is difficult to determine what the appropriate amount of courage would be for more nuanced
situations. Imagine Steve is a prisoner of war, kept in very brutal conditions with a number of his
fellow soldiers. He knows he has a fairly good chance of escaping, but if he is caught, the guards
will torture and execute him. He also knows that if a prisoner successfully escapes, the guards
will choose another prisoner at random, torture him, and then execute him. To escape under
these conditions requires a certain degree of courage; but choosing not to escape also requires
some courage. Under these circumstances, how should Steve be appropriately courageous? It
is not clear that there is a golden mean to which Steve can appeal, and it is therefore not clear
which, if either, of the possible actions is virtuous. In this specific case then, it seems that virtue
ethics lacks sufficient guidance for how to act. Similar problems confront the other virtues. Is
there an “appropriate amount” of lying one should do in order to be virtuous? Should one be
willing to break some promises but keep others? Even if we think there may be solutions to vari-
ous individual ethical dilemmas, virtue ethics seems to fail to offer the kind of general solution
offered by utilitarianism and deontology.

Another problem with virtue ethics is that Aristotle and many virtue ethicists seem to think that
certain terms are well understood and that everyone shares the same general conception of the
virtues. But do we? We may think that friendship, for example, is universally understood. Yet
imagine Carl, who thinks of himself as a very good friend to Charles and Kate, the couple that
lives next door. Carl discovers that Charles has been having an affair with Kate’s best friend. Pre-
sumably, friends tell each other the truth, but friends also do not want to see their friends hurt,

mos81165_06_c06.indd 185 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.1 How Should One Act?

Read
Alasdair

MacIntyre’s
work After
Virtue in

the Chapter
Readings
section of the
Appendix.

their marriages broken, and so on. It is not at all clear what Carl should do in this case.
More importantly, people would likely disagree over what Carl should do if he is actually
to be a good friend. Thus, we all may not share the same general conception of “friend-
ship.” Such problems multiply because each virtue will confront this kind of problem and
will encounter further problems upon trying to determine the appropriate amount of each
virtue and how they should be balanced with each other. It is for this reason that some
philosophers have rejected virtue ethics entirely. For example, in his text After Virtue, Alas-
dair MacIntyre (2007) dismisses the concept and possibly even the existence of virtues.

One other traditional problem for virtue ethics is that of relativity, or when one culture
views an act as a virtue but another regards that very same act as a vice. Consider two
communities, A and Z. A is a culture of warriors that insists its members be fierce and
respond violently to threats. Z is a culture of pacifists that insists its members always “turn
the other cheek” and respond to threats with nonviolence and negotiation. A group of
outsiders, X, sets up camp outside of both A’s and Z’s land. X appears to have a great num-
ber of weapons and may well pose a threat. Accordingly, A reacts to X’s presence violently,
while Z reacts to X’s presence nonviolently. Virtue ethics does not seem to offer a wholly
adequate way of determining whether A’s violent response or Z’s nonviolent response
is appropriate. A will regard Z’s pacifism as immoral, just as Z will regard A’s violence as
immoral. The point is not so much to determine whether A or Z (or neither) is doing the
virtuous thing. Rather, it is that virtue ethics does not seem to offer enough guidance to
make this determination. Or it ends up saying that both responses, for the respective cul-
ture, are virtuous. But if all our moral evaluations must be made relative to a given culture,
then virtue ethics cannot address actions that have different value in different cultures. In
other words, if evaluations are relativized, then virtue ethics does nothing more than say
some things are right and some are wrong, but no one can really object when someone
from another culture does something wrong so long as they act within their culture’s
moral parameters. There are those who do indeed support this view, which is known as
ethical relativism. (See Table 6.1 for a review of ethical theories and theorists.)

Table 6.1: Concept review: Theories and theorists

Ethical theory Key figure Basic idea

Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill An act (or rule) is good or right if it produces the
greatest net good for the greatest number.

Deontology Immanuel Kant An act is good or right if it is done because it
is the right thing to do, in accordance with a
justified moral rule or rules.

Virtue ethics Aristotle Morality is determined on the basis of specific
virtues, exemplified by a person of noble or
virtuous character.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 186 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section

6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

Each of the three classic ethical theories—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics—has advantages and disadvantages, and none offers an obvious or easily applied solution to the question, “What should I do?” In this section, we will look at alternatives that have been
developed in contrast to these three classic theories. Technically, these are regarded as “meta-
ethical” views, in contrast to normative ethics. Normative ethics provides a way of evaluating
acts as moral or determining whether a given act is right or wrong. Metaethics, as employed
here, is the attempt to understand what ethics is and how we can and should understand moral
questions and evaluations.

Ethical Egoism

Ego comes from the Greek word for “I.” Most readers probably know at least a few people
who could be described as having a big ego; that is, people with an exaggerated sense of their
abilities, talents, accomplishments, or qualities. Egoism, then, means to have a focus on one’s
self, and ethical egoism is the idea that one’s conception of right and wrong, good and evil,
and other moral terms are determined by one’s own sense of value. To return to the notion of
utility, we could describe this position as advocating that one should do what maximizes one’s
own utility. In short, I should do what is in my own self-interest. Thus, in the most literal sense,
this theory is selfish. Yet unlike more traditional moral theories, selfishness, or self-interest, is not
seen as wrong or immoral, but the preferred way for one to act.

Let us return to the example of the group of children playing in a sandbox with access to only
one toy. Sally, the ethical egoist—who we will just call the egoist from now on—determines
that what makes her happiest, or maximizes her utility, is to have the toy to herself. Thus, it is in
Sally’s self-interest to get the toy, keep the toy, and play with they toy all by herself. This is not,
however, the only result possible. It may be that she decides that she would get more out of it
if everyone shared, or for that matter, if only one other person got to play with the toy. If she
concludes that some other option is in her self-interest, then she should adopt that choice. So
we can see that the crucial factor in this case is not that Sally gets the toy to herself; it is that
what she perceives as most beneficial to herself will be what she should do.

Great Ideas: Different Cultures, Different Ethics?

In ancient China emperors were known to have several wives. They also had dozens, even thousands,
of concubines, women who functioned as “secondary wives” in many ways, including sexually. For
example, Emperor Taizong (599–649) of the Tang Dynasty was reputed to have 3,000 concubines.

With this in mind, consider the following questions:

1. How might a utilitarian argue that Emperor Taizong was acting immorally?
2. How might a deontologist argue that Emperor Taizong was acting immorally?
3. How might a virtue ethicist argue that Emperor Taizong was acting immorally?
4. Is there an argument that justifies Emperor Taizong’s behavior? What would such an argu-

ment look like?
5. Do you think ethical values change over time? Would this affect how we might judge this

situation today, and how we might have judged this situation in the 7th century?

mos81165_06_c06.indd 187 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

Read Joel
Feinberg’s
“Psycho-
logical

Egoism” in
the Chapter

Readings
section of the
Appendix.

Now let us revisit the example of Mary, who is trying to decide whether to go dancing
or stay home with her three children. Factoring in the happiness of Mary and the three
children, the utilitarian argued that everyone would be best off if Mary stayed home—that
this scenario would produce the greatest net good for the greatest number. The egoist
might conclude otherwise: If Mary sees her greatest happiness achieved by going out
dancing, then she should go out dancing. Again, Mary may conclude that it would make
her happiest to stay home. The egoist’s position is that what Mary should do is whatever
Mary sees as in her self-interest.

We saw that the classic theories of ethics—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics—
all had problems when we tried to apply them to real life. Egoism, however, seems not
to have that problem. People determine what is in their self-interest. They do what they
think will make them best off, and according to this theory, that is what they should do.

Suppose Joe is a retired billionaire investment banker. He has several houses, cars, and
servants and can take vacations whenever and wherever he wants. One day Joe sees Mike,
an old friend from high school who has become homeless. Mike asks Joe for $10. For Joe,
this amount is almost nothing; but Joe considers whether he would be better off giving
the money to Mike or keeping it himself. Joe decides he would be happier keeping his
money; egoism tells us that is what he should do. Traditional ethical theories and religious
views may regard Joe as being selfish, greedy, and more generally, acting immorally. Ego-
ism, however, does not; traditional conceptions of selfishness are not regarded by egoism
as immoral. It may turn out, of course, that Joe decides that it is in his self-interest to give
Mike the $10; it might make him feel better to help out an old friend, and after all, it is
not much of a sacrifice for Joe. But egoism leaves that decision up to Joe, and what Joe
perceives to be in his own self-interest is what Joe should do.

Many economists have argued that this is in fact how economic exchanges work in free
markets. Buyers want to get as much as they can as cheaply as they can; sellers want to
sell as much as they can for the highest price. Individuals, then, want to maximize their
utility by getting as much as they can out of the exchange. In the traditional views, this
sounds not just selfish, but greedy. Yet we assume everyone has, more or less, the same
amount of information about the product involved, and we also assume that everyone
knows that everyone else is trying to maximize his or her self-interest. In this way the mar-
ket will in theory be most efficient and create more goods and more wealth for everyone
if everyone acts in ways that maximize his or her self-interest.

Recognizing that greed was traditionally regarded as sin, political economist Bernard
Mandeville (1670–1733) claimed that great benefits would be produced if everyone were
greedy. He described this arrangement as “private vices, public benefits”: That is, the pri-
vate vice of selfishness would actually end up making society wealthier than it would have
been otherwise, which is a public benefit. Joel Feinberg (1926–2004) is another philoso-
pher who considered the role of selfishness in human actions. Feinberg, however, argues
against psychological egoism, the idea that humans are internally driven to do all acts by
selfish motives. He demonstrates logical inconsistencies in this position and ultimately
claims that it is an unsound judgment about human motives in ethical judgment.

Problems With Ethical Egoism

Ethicists, religious leaders, and many others protest against ethical egoism because it
seems to promote selfishness. The objection is fairly obvious: Being selfish is wrong, either

mos81165_06_c06.indd 188 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

because it is immoral, a sin, or both; so too must be an ethical theory that promotes it. How-
ever, another more subtle question might trouble the ethical egoist: How do we determine our
self-interest?

Ethical egoism assumes that any individual can identify what is in his or her self-interest, but
that may not always be the case. When considering what action to take, do I evaluate my self-
interest in the short term, the long term, or something in between? Perhaps I think it is in my
short-term self-interest to eat an entire blueberry pie because it is delicious; this will be against
my self-interest, however, if I have a long-term goal of losing weight. Perhaps we could adopt
the principle that my long-term interest should always override my short-term interest. Yet can
I really be sure what my long-term interest is and that it will not change? Even if the question
of what I know about my self-interest can be answered, a bigger problem may then arise: Can I
ever be wrong about my self-interest? If whatever I do is defined as having been done in my self-
interest, then how could I ever do something against my self-interest? The egoist maxim “One
should do whatever one does” does not seem to offer much in the way of guidance.

An example further illustrates this. Suppose Emma decides it is in her self-interest to become,
over time, very wealthy. Despite her love of shopping, taking nice vacations, and going out to
expensive dinners with her friends, she resists doing so and becomes very frugal. She only buys
the cheapest things and has to actively resist her friends’ invitations to do all her favorite activi-
ties. She puts all the money she saves into the stock market and other investments and slowly
starts to generate a substantial amount of money. She sees her friends less and less often and
becomes somewhat of a hermit. After several years she realizes that she is very lonely, does not
have much fun, and is generally unpleasant to be around. Even though she has met her goal of
becoming wealthy, she realizes that she sacrificed too much to reach that goal. She decides to
give all of her money away to charity and focuses on doing volunteer work to help others.

The ethical egoist would have offered Emma little guidance. By choosing her long-term goals
over her short-term goals, Emma presumably maximized her utility. However, had she decided
otherwise—to continue shopping, vacationing, and eating at expensive restaurants—she would
have maximized her utility as well. This is because she would have made either choice in her own
self-interest. Worse yet, her long-term goals changed, so she gave up not just her short-term
pleasures but also her original long-term goal when she adopted a new one. Whatever Emma
determines is in her self-interest is what she should do, but she clearly was not able to determine
what that long-term self-interest really was.

Great Ideas: Short-Term and Long-Term Interests

Mark graduated from college six months ago. He has $5,000 in student loans and $1,000 in savings.
He has been looking for a job for several weeks, with no luck.

Reflection Questions:
With this in mind, consider the following questions:

1. Which of the following should Mark pursue if he wants to maximize his short-term
interests?

2. Which of the following should Mark pursue if he wants to maximize his long-term
interests?

(continued)

mos81165_06_c06.indd 189 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

Like utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics, ethical egoism also falls short on the ethical
issue of lying. The classical theories all had guidance for when or if one should lie, but their
results were unsatisfactory and occasionally led to strange or even wrong outcomes. An egoist
would be even less helpful on this subject. If Carolyn asks Bob to go to the movies but Bob does
not want to go, should he lie and say he is busy? Should he tell the truth and say he does not
want to go? The advice ethical egoism seems to offer is that it is all right for him to lie if he does
so out of self-interest; the same is true if he tells the truth out of self-interest. It is unclear how
this reasoning can help Bob make an ethical decision, however.

Relativism

We have now examined a number of theories and also acknowledged that each has its problems.
One might be tempted to abandon the search for an ethical theory at this point, at least one
that tells people what they should do and how they should live. Rather than taking this course
of action, however, we should recognize that there are no universal or general ethical standards;
that a person’s ethical view is relative to his or her culture, society, tradition, religion, worldview,
and even individual values. Because moral claims are said to be relative to something else, this is
a metaethical view known as relativism. Even though philosophers distinguish between different
kinds of relativism, we will generally use the term to mean that any ethical claim is relative to a
set of beliefs and that any such ethical claim is true, or consistent with, that set of beliefs. To take
a simple example: Suppose you like comedies and your best friend likes action films. It is not too
problematic here to reject the suggestion that comedies are better than action films or to reject
the suggestion that action films are better than comedies; each claim is relative to one’s beliefs,
desires, and preferences. Although it may make things more difficult when you and your friend
go see a movie together, neither of you is determined to convince the other that there is some
true, objective, or factual claim being ignored about the merits of comedies and action films.

Moral Relativism
Moral relativism extends this idea to the area of ethics. Ethical evaluations—saying some act is
right or wrong—are made in terms of the context of that act and therefore are relative to the
actor’s culture and values. For example, some cultures bury their dead; some cremate their dead;
some allow them to be exposed to the elements and scavengers; some mummify their dead (at
least their important dead, such as Egyptian pharaohs); some cultures have even been reported
to eat their dead. Which is right? Are any of these wrong? Some religions require the cremation
of the dead, whereas other religions prohibit it. What is the relativist response to these issues?

Great Ideas: Short-Term and Long-Term Interests
(continued)

3. How confident should Mark be about these decisions? In other words, can he distinguish
with a very high degree of certainty between his short-term and long-term interests?

A. Mark borrows more money to buy an expensive guitar he has wanted for several years,
in order to become a professional musician.

B. Mark invests $500 and pays $500 on his student loans.
C. Mark pays $1,000 on his student loans.
D. Mark invests $1,000 in a speculative stock offering, having been told by a friend that

the stock will go up 100% in the next year.
E. Mark buys $1,000 in lottery tickets.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 190 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

The relativist simply says that the practice a given culture adopts as correct determines what
should be done. Let culture A be a society that cremates, or ritually burns, its dead, while culture
B is a society that prohibits cremation. The relativist says A’s tradition is correct for A and not
for B; in the same way, B’s tradition is correct for B and not for A. Just as important for the view
we are calling moral relativism is that those who live in culture A cannot say that cremating is
right and not cremating is wrong; they can only say it is right for them. In the same way, those
in culture B cannot say that cremating is wrong and not cremating is right; they can only say it
is wrong for them. The opinion of cremation, then, is relative to the given culture, and there is
no objective ethical standard to appeal to for determining whether cremating one’s dead is right
or wrong.

Many people find this position very attractive. It seems to eliminate the need, or desire, to
provide objective evaluations for all people and all societies. It allow us to simply “agree to dis-
agree,” in that if some culture or society or religion does something that our society would deem
as immoral, we are free to say it is wrong for our society but not for others.

Moral relativism is often characterized in terms of cultures, and cultural anthropologists have
identified many practices that contrast, and even conflict, with some of the standard Western
traditions. There are numerous rituals and ceremonies relating to birth, achieving adult status,
marrying, and dying, to name a few, that reflect a wide range of beliefs and values.

We saw that Aristotle recommended generosity, within its appropriate limits, as one of the chief
qualities a virtuous person would possess. Imagine a society in which people who are deemed
good or virtuous are those who have the greatest wealth; in this society people would gain vir-
tuous status by accumulating as much as they can and keeping it all to themselves. In contrast,
consider a society in which people are deemed good or virtuous if they give all of their wealth
away. Aristotle regarded a moderate amount of generosity as universally virtuous. Here we see
that the moral relativist might regard a deficiency of generosity (keeping everything for oneself)
as a virtue, relative to a society’s values; an excess of generosity (giving everything away) can
also be seen as virtue, relative to a society’s values. The moral relativist concludes that the claim
“generosity is a virtue” can only be evaluated in terms of a specific society’s values.

Great Ideas: Cultural Relativism

Consider some of the following activities that involve cultural practices and traditions. Can you imag-
ine a version of one or more of these practices that you would find objectionable? What does cultural
relativism tell us about your objection? If you cannot imagine any practice that is objectionable, does
that mean absolutely everything is morally permissible? If so, what are the implications of this idea?

• Dating
• Marriage
• Health care
• How the elderly are treated
• What foods one can eat
• Raising children
• Education
• Encountering strangers
• Death
• Adultery

mos81165_06_c06.indd 191 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

Just as we considered the perspective of the other moral theories on this subject, what would
the moral relativist have to say on the topic of lying? Is it wrong to lie? Is it okay to lie? Is it some-
times wrong to lie and sometimes right to lie? The moral relativist would likely say, “It depends.”
If your society rewards lying, or at least does not punish it, then lying might well be okay. If your
society, on the other hand, has strict penalties against lying (whether legal, official, or informally
enforced by community members), then lying will be wrong. “Lying is right” or “lying is wrong”
are the kinds of claims avoided by the moral relativist, who would advocate statements more
along the lines of, “Lying is right relative to a society that permits or encourages lying” and
“Lying is wrong relative to a society that prohibits lying.”

Extreme Relativism
So far we have discussed relativism in terms of societies and cultures. However, it is worth point-
ing out there is an extreme, or radical, kind of relativism, often associated with the ancient Greek
philosopher Protagoras (ca. 490–420 bce). This kind of relativism is said to hold true for individu-
als: If a person says something is true or false, right or wrong, then it is true or false and right
or wrong for that person. We saw an example of this when you and your friend discussed your
preferences for movies: For you it was true that comedies were best; for your friend, it was true
that action films were best. Protagorean, or extreme, relativism extends this idea to all claims,
including ethical ones. Presumably, this means if you think shoplifting is wrong but another per-
son says shoplifting is not wrong, there is no “fact” we can point to in order to determine who
is correct. Shoplifting is wrong for you, but not wrong (or even right) for the other person. That
is about all there is to say about such disagreements.

This kind of relativism is often attractive in ethics because it allows us to avoid judging or criticiz-
ing other people and cultures. This is especially true when we are considering cultures and tradi-
tions with which we are not very familiar. However, similar to the other moral theories, issues
have been raised with relativism as well.

Problems With Relativism

One problem with relativism is that some acts or traditions seem wrong not just in relation to
a culture, but simply wrong on their own. For example, an ancient Hindu practice called suttee
requires a woman whose husband has recently died to commit suicide by throwing herself on
his funeral pyre. This can be done voluntarily, or she might be forced to do so. (The practice has
been outlawed but occasionally still occurs.) Some societies continue to practice slavery. Others
make child pornography widely available. Some societies practice infanticide, or the killing (or
allowing to die) of an infant after birth if it lacks desired characteristics (frequently if it is a girl).
Some societies have executed prisoners—often on flimsy or inadequate charges and with little
legal protection—in order to take their organs and sell them on the black market. Of course, the
20th century offered many examples of leaders—Joseph Stalin, Mao Tse-tung, and Adolf Hitler,
to name a few—who caused the deaths of millions under their reign.

The relativist would seem to say that such examples are wrong only relative to a specific culture
or worldview. Perhaps we are from a culture that views infanticide or slavery as wrong; we would
then say that, for us, these things are wrong. Yet from the perspective of a culture that does not
share our views, perhaps infanticide or slavery—or both—are not wrong or are even right. The
extreme cases tend to make people uncomfortable, which is the point. Do we want to say that
a government policy that results in family members eating each other is only wrong relative to

mos81165_06_c06.indd 192 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

a given value system, or that such a policy is simply, fundamentally, universally, and obviously
wrong? To be consistent, the relativist has to say that no matter how wrong something seems
to be, the idea of “wrong” is still relative. This suggestion may make you as uncomfortable as it
makes some ethical theorists.

Reformer’s Dilemma
A second, more sophisticated objection to relativism, known as the “Reformer’s Dilemma” (Feld-
man, 1978, p. 166), has been provided by the philosopher Fred Feldman (b. 1941). Imagine
Sarah lives in a society that values boys but not girls. To keep the society going, some number
of girls is needed, but parents are allowed to kill a third, female child if they already have a girl.
Furthermore, if a couple already has three children, girls or boys, they are required to kill all
subsequent female children. Sarah thinks this is wrong; perhaps she just feels it is wrong, or
perhaps she has substantial arguments for her position. Yet moral relativism says that her soci-
ety determines what is wrong or right, and it has determined that killing girls is right. So Sarah
must be wrong to object to this policy. More generally, anyone who objects to any of a society’s
policies must be wrong. Thus, by this logic, Martin Luther King Jr. would have been wrong to
object to oppressive and racist American practices in the 1960s; Nelson Mandela would have
been wrong to object to the oppressive and racist South African system of apartheid. In fact,
anyone who wished to change society could never be correct. This seems problematic, given
that many of history’s most admired people were critical of their societies. Worse, this seems to
suggest that if criticizing social values always puts a person in the wrong, then society cannot
ever be improved, and thus must be perfect. Yet as Feldman observes, this poses a challenge to
the absolute relativist.

Remembering What We Agree On
Perhaps the most sophisticated response to relativism can be found in the work of American
philosopher Donald Davidson, who expanded upon the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Davidson
(1974) argues that radical relativism is incoherent, for several reasons. First, assume that the
relativist is right and that a person’s beliefs are relative to his or her society. However, we must
recall that within any society, a person can “belong” to many different kinds of groups, based
on ethnicity, class, income level, language, gender, race, religion, sexual orientation, and so on.
Consider Jafari, who has lived for most of his life in France but was born in Egypt. His native
language is Arabic and he is Muslim. From which group does he derive his values? What if one
group to which Jafari belongs approves of, say, restricting women from working outside the
home, whereas another group to which he belongs disapproves of such a prohibition? How
does Jafari figure out whether it is right or wrong? To take the idea to its extreme, does a poor
White 50-year-old Lutheran heterosexual woman from Texas have moral values in common with
an 18-year-old wealthy Chinese lesbian or with a homosexual middle-class 50-year-old White
Unitarian male from Pennsylvania? It seems that the many factors that constitute culture pose a
problem for the relativist who argues that culture determines our values.

Second, Davidson points out that when discussing ethical viewpoints, politics, religion, and other
controversial topics, we almost always focus on the areas over which we disagree. Yet in order
to reach a point of disagreement, there are actually numerous issues and ideas upon which we
actually agree. Consider a debate over gun control between Jim and John. Jim thinks no one
should be able to own a handgun; John thinks everyone should be required to own a handgun.
Their disagreement seems substantial, yet imagine if they started their disagreement by listing

mos81165_06_c06.indd 193 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

the points on which they agree, the points that make their disagreement possible—such as that
guns do not speak Japanese, guns do not make good hats, guns are not an appropriate filling for
sandwiches, guns cannot fly, and so on. This exercise hardly makes our disagreements disappear,
yet it highlights how people’s agreements typically outnumber their disagreements. As Davidson
puts it, disagreements—even between two people from dramatically different cultures—can
only occur within the context of massive agreement, or on the assumption of an enormous back-
ground of shared ideas. Relativists would likely purport that two people from different cultures
would agree on very little. However, in order to disagree, Davidson argues that they must agree
on an awful lot even to reach the point of disagreement.

Nietzsche’s Challenge

Relativism seems to place ethical problems on a scale of “difficult to solve” to “unsolvable.”
As Davidson indicates, this may be the consequence of focusing exclusively on what divides us
rather than what unites us. Others have challenged even more fundamentally the values of soci-
ety as a whole, including traditional political and religious structures. Perhaps the most powerful
such challenge came from the German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche.

Nietzsche’s father, uncle, and grandfathers were all Lutheran pastors, but Nietzsche’s father
died when he was 4 years old, and his brother died a few months later. Nietzsche was raised by
his mother and sister, was sent to a highly prestigious boarding school in Germany, and at the
age of just 24 accepted a position to teach classical philology (the study of classical Greek and
Latin texts) at the University of Basel in Switzerland. Nietzsche taught there for 10 years, but his
job was interrupted by military service, during which he received a serious injury. His health in
general was not good, and he had to resign from his teaching post. He spent much of the rest
of his life wandering around Italy, France, Switzerland, and Germany. In 1889 Nietzsche had a
mental breakdown and collapsed in Turin, Italy. He spent the remaining years of his life unable
to communicate, not realizing that the many books he had produced had begun to make him a
world-famous philosopher.

Übermensch
Nietzsche’s influence on 20th-century philosophy is difficult to overstate. He presented, and still
represents, a radical challenge to traditional ethical viewpoints. His position called for a reevalua-
tion of all values; that is, a criticism and scrutiny of all the various things that traditional morality
and religion had said were good or wrong. In doing so Nietzsche determined that much of tradi-
tional morality was fundamentally wrong. He declared that “God is dead” (and had been killed
by human beings) and defended atheism. Nietzsche thought that Judaism and Christianity had
adopted the ancient ideas of the Greeks and Romans and perverted them. Before Christianity,
the “good” was identified as the strong, the powerful, the courageous, the noble, and the cre-
ative; the “bad” was that which was weak, timid, small-minded, and cowardly. Nietzsche argued
that Christianity turned this upside down. He suggested that people had been convinced by “the
priests”—those who control a society’s moral, cultural, political, and religious values—that what
had been good was now evil and what had been bad was now good. Hence, he saw the prevail-
ing morality as preventing those who were noble, creative, and bold from being recognized as
superior to the masses. He also argued that the masses—who were timid and weak—could be
easily controlled by those in power, like sheep by a shepherd. He thought both Christianity and

mos81165_06_c06.indd 194 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

Read
Friedrich

Nietzsche’s
Beyond Good

and Evil in
the Chapter

Readings
section of the
Appendix.

democracy (a democracy being of a mass of people who were kept ignorant and did what
they were told) held back society’s very few exceptional individuals who were capable of
achieving greatness. Such an individual was called by Nietzsche an Übermensch, which is
usually translated as “superman” or “overman” (Nietzsche, 1973). This overman creates
his (or her; Nietzsche’s issues with women are notorious, but very complex) own values,
and his own morality, as an expression of his power to overcome the values people around
him have tried to force upon him. In this way the overman becomes a free and indepen-
dent spirit, risking everything in his unwillingness to accept social conventions. Ultimately,
Nietzsche (1974) suggests a view he calls “eternal recurrence” as the goal of the truly
noble soul: People should seek a life that they would be happy living if they were to have
to live exactly that way for eternity.

Critiques of

Nietzsche

Those who have resisted Nietzsche’s ideas (and there are many) do so for a number of rea-
sons. Unlike Nietzsche, they think moral and religious traditions express important truths
and values, and certainly disagree that “God is dead.” Most Nietzsche scholars reject the
idea that he was the type of extreme relativist discussed previously in this chapter; how-
ever, it is easy to see why some might regard him that way. After all, if one creates one’s
own values, then those values would seem relative to that person. Some critics regard
Nietzsche as elitist because of his suggestion that just a few “great souls” were allowed
full access to freedom and independence, but the great masses who did not so qualify
were relegated to mediocrity, following rules they did not understand and more or less
doing what they were told.

However, there is no denying that in the history
of ethics, Nietzsche presents a serious challenge
to a number of different moral and religious
traditions. He requires us to examine our moral
values and see how we use them to justify our
actions. Has Christianity been used to promise
people a true reward that will come after death
to make it easier to control them while alive?
Have Western societies often punished people
who are unwilling to go along with their over-
riding values? Interestingly enough, at times
Nietzsche identified Jesus as a person whom
society punished for being brave and indepen-
dent enough to raise profound objections to
the values imposed upon him, but Nietzsche
(1968) also remarked that the “last true Chris-
tian died on the cross” (sec. 39). Have societ-
ies that officially or unofficially regarded them-
selves as Christian acted in ways that violate
the very Christian principles they are said to
embrace? These and many of Nietzsche’s other
questions are important reminders that people
often say one thing but do another. Nietzsche’s

Oronoz/SuperStock

Friedrich Nietzsche called for intense
scrutiny and criticism of all of what
traditional morality and religion had
deemed as good and bad.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 195 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

willingness to expose this hypocrisy has continued to confront Western philosophy, specifi-
cally its development of moral theories. He has, therefore, demanded that philosophers and all
those interested in moral questions carefully consider whether what we do actually conforms to
what we believe. Demanding we make this critical and uncomfortable self-examination is the
very thing that makes those demanding it unpopular; many think this was precisely the reason
Socrates was executed. At the same time, most of us recognize that it is to our benefit to see
if there are any contradictions between what we believe, why we believe it, and how we treat
others.

Tolerance and Diversity

We may well reject Nietzsche’s scathing critique of society and its hypocrisy. We may also resist
what seem to be Nietzsche’s elitism and his lack of tolerance. At the same time, given the
increasing global interdependence and the diversity of societies, philosophers have also worried
about whether we can determine what an appropriate amount of tolerance is. The United States
is a diverse country, with people from a vast number of backgrounds who represent numer-
ous ethnic groups, religious traditions, and countries of origin. Some 80% of Americans speak
English, but according to the 2010 U.S. Census, more than 350 other languages are spoken (or
signed) in the United States (although some of these are spoken by a very small groups). Some
estimate there are more than 200 different religious denominations in the United States. There is
even more diversity globally, of course: The planet’s 7 billion people speak thousands of different
languages, practice thousands of different religious traditions and denominations, and are com-
posed of thousands of different ethnic groups. In India alone, for example, some 350 different
languages are spoken by a substantial number of people, even though its official state language
is Hindi (and its secondary “official” language is English).

Assuming that differences in culture, religion, ethnicity, and other value systems generate dis-
agreement, this degree of diversity would indicate a good deal of disagreement. It would be nice
to think that ethicists—or anyone else, for that matter—could come up with a recipe for pre-
venting, or at least minimizing, these disagreements and thereby minimize the military invasions,
terrorism, and various other violence caused by these disagreements. That may seem a bit opti-
mistic, but it is worth thinking about how the study of ethics could move us closer to this goal.

Extreme Tolerance and Intolerance
We can start by identifying two positions on opposite ends of the spectrum: extreme toler-
ance and extreme intolerance. The extremely tolerant person will accept all cultures, perspec-
tives, views, and ethical values expressed by any society, anywhere, and at any time. In short an
extremely tolerant person tolerates everything. Extreme intolerance, on the other hand, involves
tolerating nothing but one’s own view. Thus, the extremely intolerant culture Z rejects all other
cultures from A through Y. One and only one position is acceptable to Z, and Z regards all
other cultures as wrong. The extremely tolerant society, on the other hand, never considers
another view to be wrong and never challenges or criticizes it. Thus, it would never need to
engage another culture or society militarily. The extremely intolerant society may always be at
war, however, for it always sees any culture with distinct views as being incorrect.

It is likely that few, if any, cultures qualify as either extremely tolerant or extremely intolerant.
Most fall between these two extremes. Considering the polar opposites is useful, however,

mos81165_06_c06.indd 196 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics

because it gives us a sense of the limits involved in describing the various ways one might
endorse, or advocate, tolerance. For even though many agree that “tolerance” is generally a
good thing, we can see that too much tolerance could be as bad as too much intolerance. Imag-
ine you are sitting quietly at home, watching a baseball game with a friend. Someone comes in,
shoots your friend, and takes everything you own. An extremely tolerant person would have no
objections to this scenario. More generally, extreme tolerance may lead to what one might call
the paradox of tolerance, for the extremely tolerant person cannot object to the extremely intol-
erant person, and ends up tolerating the most vicious, dogmatic, and violent kind of intolerant
behavior. Even if tolerance is a virtue, Aristotle would tell us that too much tolerance can be bad.

However, a look around indicates that threats are more likely to stem from intolerance. A gov-
ernment may ban free speech or a particular religion. Two countries may go to war over a piece
of land not because they each want it, but rather they each want to prevent the other from
acquiring it. Terrorists may kill people who practice a different religion or those who simply hold
different values. A town may practice informal discrimination against people regarded by the
majority as “different,” whether because they are a different race, religion, sexual orientation,
or have another minority identity. A person may decide that abortion is so immoral that it is
acceptable to murder a doctor who performs abortions. Do philosophers, specifically ethicists,
have tools to question these and other intolerant acts?

Reflective Equilibrium
In his extremely influential 1971 book A Theory of Justice, the philosopher John Rawls
(1921–2002) puts forth a strategy he calls reflective equilibrium. While the full theory is quite
complex, Rawls’s fundamental ideas help make clear our sense of fairness. Rawls believes any
plausible conception of justice must be one that is regarded by all who participate in a society’s
decisions as fair, and thus he is famous for characterizing justice as fairness (Rawls, 1971).

Rawls describes a thought experiment where people come together to design a society in which
they will at some point live. He puts a crucial condition on those designing this society: They
are behind what he calls a “veil of ignorance” (1971). That is, they do not know what kind of
person they will be in this future society: They do not know their gender, race, religion (if any),
class, ethnicity, sexual orientation, physical handicaps, and so on. Thus, what the participants
determine to be fair must express what each thinks would be fair for all. For instance, a man
would not describe a society that discriminates against women, for he might discover that in this
future society, he is one.

Part of Rawls’s discussion requires the notion of reflective equilibrium, where individuals with
various moral and political views discuss the moral and political views of others, in order to see
what agreement can be reached. As Rawls describes the idea, “adopting the role of observing
moral theorist, we investigate what principles people would acknowledge and accept the conse-
quences of when they have an opportunity to consider other plausible conceptions and to assess
their supporting grounds” (Rawls, 1971).

To illustrate the idea further, consider the following example. John and Mary, who come from
very different backgrounds, compare their notions of a just and fair society. They both are willing
to consider the other’s viewpoint and recognize that some adjustment to their own notion may
have to be made. Perhaps John is suspicious of religions other than his own, whereas Mary is
an agnostic and thus has no religion. Through reflective equilibrium, John adjusts his beliefs to
accept others who may not share his religious views, and Mary adjusts her beliefs to allow more
tolerance for those who cherish their religious commitments. After much give and take, they

mos81165_06_c06.indd 197 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section

6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

come to a position they both accept. In a certain sense Rawls offers a sophisticated account of
precisely what many people do all the time: compromise. In doing so he suggests a nonviolent
way of solving our disputes, and thus provides us with another way to think about making our
diverse and often contentious planet more harmonious.

6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

We have seen some of the best known ethical theories and some of the challenges they confront. We have also seen some of the alternatives to these traditional theories and some of their weaknesses. We will now look at more specific ethical issues, describe
the problems they present, and examine how ethical theories might be used to resolve them. We
will begin with personal or individual ethical issues before turning to more general social ethi-
cal issues, although there is often overlap between these. We will see that many ethical issues
require us to think about the relationship between the individual and his or her society and how
one influences the other. (See Table 6.2 for a list of topics to be explored in ethics.)

Table 6.2: Concept review: Topics to be explored

Individual issues in ethics

Promises

Free speech

Greed

Vegetarianism

Euthanasia

Social issues in ethics

Animal rights

Plato’s critique of democracy

Rawls’s conception of fairness

The environment

The personal and the political

Libertarianism

Victimless crimes

Promises

We all make promises, and for the most part we expect promises to be kept. Since I expect oth-
ers to keep their promises, deontological ethics insists that this means I should keep the promises
I make. The utilitarian takes a different approach; perhaps there are situations in which the great-
est number achieves the greatest net good by breaking a promise. We probably also think that
promises have a certain context, or set of conditions. For example, we should not make promises
we know we cannot keep. Yet it may not be unethical to make a promise, try our best to fulfill
it, yet end up breaking it. Various kinds of examples bear out these ideas further.

Imagine you promise to pay Smith $5 next week if he loans it to you today (you are friends, so he
does not charge you interest). Smith may think that in addition to being paid back, if he loans you
money, you might return the favor some day if he is in need. Similarly, you do not want Smith to

mos81165_06_c06.indd 198 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

regard you as someone who does not meet his obligations; or perhaps you might need to borrow
money again in the future, so you want to be sure to pay it back this time. One might look at this
from the point of view of ethical egoism: You and Smith are both looking out for your self-interest,
now and in the future. So Smith loans you the money, and you promise to pay it back (and do).

On the one hand, your self-interest is best met by getting the money and ensuring the poten-
tial to borrow more. Smith’s self-interest is best met by loaning the money and ensuring his
potential to borrow from you. The deontologist, on the other hand, says that you have made a
promise to Smith—to pay him back—and that one should keep one’s promises; not out of self-
interest, but because it is the right thing to do. (We can determine that it is the right thing to do
by looking at it from the perspective of the Golden Rule or from the perspective of Kant, who
would suggest that morality requires that promises be kept.) Meanwhile, the utilitarian might
say there are various outcomes, but paying back the loan will certainly create a utility calcula-
tion that would not be lower than any of the other outcomes. Presumably, being honest and
keeping one’s promises are virtues—at least if done appropriately and in moderation—so the
virtue ethicist will also insist that the money be paid back. As we see, then, the ethical egoist,
the deontologist, the utilitarian, and the virtue ethicist all agree that the promise should be kept,
but they arrive at that conclusion from very different directions.

However, these theories may not always agree so nicely. Consider marriage vows, in which
partners promise to love, cherish, honor, and obey, among other things, “till death do us part.”
Despite the fact this promise is binding and often made before God, it is not always kept. Pre-
sumably, people make this promise fully intending to keep it, but circumstances change. Assum-
ing one or both members of a marriage are sufficiently miserable to end it, the utilitarian would
probably conclude that doing so would lead to the greatest good for the greatest number. The
deontologist might say that although promises should never be made lightly, the Kantian “uni-
versality requirement”—that we act in such a way that it would always be the right thing to
do in those circumstances—could be taken to mean that ending the marriage is the right thing
to do. The virtue ethicist would probably argue that keeping a promise to remain married, if it
makes one or both of those people miserable, is immoderate and fails to recognize that it is
sometimes appropriate to break promises. In this case, however, one can also see that others
might argue that a utility calculation, an application of the categorical imperative, or the virtue
of honesty might require the marriage to continue.

Thus, ethical theories might not only conflict with each other, but may even conflict with com-
mon sense. For instance, if one interprets Kant as saying that promises must never be broken,
then it would violate his ethical principle to dissolve the marriage, even if it condemns both
people to abject misery for the rest of their lives. This also shows that ethical theories are not
really “recipes” that guarantee a certain and reliable ethical outcome. Instead, they can offer
guidance for ascertaining right and wrong, so long as we understand that their application may
change depending on a situation’s specifics.

Free Speech

In the United States specifically, a number of political and ethical questions arise from how one
interprets the Constitution. It will be helpful to see a specific example of this from the Bill of
Rights. The First Amendment to the Constitution of the United States reads:

Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohib-
iting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the
press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the
Government for a redress of grievances.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 199 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

The questions this raises about religion—whether what is known is the “establishment” clause
or the “free exercise” clause—are pretty well known. However, the questions of the freedom of
speech and of the press raise issues that are also worth looking at, in terms of constitutionally pro-
tected rights, and what our ethical theories might say about when those rights might be violated.

As we saw with the issue of promises, we probably start with an assumption that free speech, for
individuals and for the media (or press), cannot be prohibited without a very good reason. In other
words, free speech is always assumed to be protected unless legitimate reasons can be provided.

Yelling “Fire!”
The most famous example of when free speech can be prohibited comes from the Supreme
Court case Schenck v. United States (1919), in which Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes noted that
one should not be allowed to yell “Fire!” in a crowded theatre. The reason is that falsely indicat-
ing there is a fire could cause panic and put people in danger as they all rush toward the exits.
Holmes’s reasoning sounds utilitarian: Even if the person yelling “Fire!” gets some degree of
pleasure from doing so, everyone else is at risk of psychological trauma and physical injury. Thus,
the greatest good for the greatest number demands prohibiting this kind of speech. The deon-
tologist, who rejects lying on principle, would agree with Holmes’s conclusion, pointing out that
falsely yelling “Fire!” is a lie. As we have seen before, two different ethical theories come to the
same conclusion, though for different reasons.

Even those who advocate the greatest amount of free speech recognize that in this specific case,
the harm caused outweighs the right to say whatever one wishes. There are other such restric-
tions recognized in the law: One cannot threaten the life of the president, for example, nor freely
joke about bombs or hijacking while in an airport. Most people recognize these as legitimate
restrictions to the First Amendment’s guarantee of free speech.

Freedom for Speech We Do Not Like
Real life presents many situations in which one person’s right to say something may violate
another person’s right not to hear (or see) it. For instance, there are various laws that regulate
pornography’s production, distribution, and sale. Should adults be able to take whatever kind
of pictures they want and sell them to another adult? Some argue that to prevent them from
doing so is a restriction on free speech; others argue that pornography objectifies women (treat-
ing them solely as a means to an end, not as ends in themselves, in Kantian language) in ways
that can lead to violence, sexual abuse, rape, and other immoral and illegal acts, and thus should
not qualify as protected speech. Even though most people agree that child pornography should
be illegal (as it is in the United States), what about a novel that depicts a pornographic scenario
involving a child? Should consenting adults be allowed to write and read such novels?

Great Ideas: Bradley Manning, Daniel Ellsberg,
and Free Speech

In 2010 soldier Bradley (now Chelsea) Manning was arrested on charges that he had passed classified
material to a website known as Wikileaks. In 2013 Manning pleaded guilty to 10 of the 22 charges
he faced, though many debate whether he should be regarded as a hero or a traitor for exposing
national secrets.

(continued)

mos81165_06_c06.indd 200 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

Many other such cases have arisen in which one per –
son’s right to free speech conflicts with another
person’s desire—possibly legitimate desire—to pre-
vent that speech. Should high school students be
allowed to wear T-shirts that other students—or
teachers—find offensive? Should a person be allowed
to advocate the overthrow of the U.S. government?
Should a person be allowed to design a Web page
calling for the murder of physicians who provide
abortion services? Should a student be allowed to
pray in school? Should such schools allow or prevent
such prayers at official school functions such as foot-
ball games or graduations? We may want to protect
religious speech, but what if one person’s religious
speech offends another person’s religious beliefs? Is
there a danger of a majority trampling the rights of
a minority?

Ethical theories do not provide exact formulas for
solving such debates. How might a utilitarian respond
to these kinds of cases? How might a deontologist
respond? Would they agree? Would they disagree?
How would they support their conclusions? Would it
depend on the circumstances of the case? If so, does
that prevent us from developing a sufficiently general
notion of morality, as expressed in the Golden Rule
or the “greatest net good for the greatest number”
principle of utilitarianism?

Great Ideas: Bradley Manning, Daniel Ellsberg,
and Free Speech (continued)

Manning is not the first American to make government secrets public; in 1971 Daniel Ellsberg leaked
the now famous Pentagon Papers, which revealed numerous problems about the prosecution of the
Vietnam War.

Are such leaks justified? Some suggest that without them, government malfeasance and incompe-
tence would be much harder to discover; others argue that the government must withhold certain
information from the public for reasons of national security.

Reflection Questions:

1. Can revealing government secrets ever be justified?
2. Can revealing government secrets ever lead to more benefits than maintaining those

secrets?
3. Defend your answers to numbers 1 and 2 using a version of utilitarianism.

Steve Senne/

Associated Press

A high school in Rhode Island displayed this
school prayer banner in their auditorium
until one of its students, an atheist,
requested the school take it down. She
argued that the banner was offensive to
non-Christians.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 201 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics
Greed

Earlier we saw that ethical egoism calls into question some of the traditional philosophical and
religious objections against selfishness and its end result, greed. Here we will explore whether
there is any conflict between what traditional views say about greed and certain principles
underlying a capitalist economy.

In director Oliver Stone’s 1987 film Wall Street, a wealthy investor named Gordon Gekko makes
a speech that is now probably better known than the movie itself. He declares:

Greed—for lack of a better word—is good. Greed is right. Greed works. Greed
clarifies, cuts through, and captures the essence of the evolutionary spirit. Greed,
in all of its forms—greed for life, for money, for love, knowledge—has marked
the upward surge of mankind. (Pressman & Stone, 1987)

As we saw briefly, in economic exchanges between two people, each wants the very most he or
she can get. If John wants to buy something from Mary, he wants the most he can get for the
least amount of money, and Mary wants the greatest amount of money she can get while giving
up the least. This desire for getting the most for the least is often considered the way we should
(and do) act. Traditionally, however, wanting as much as possible of something was regarded as
being greedy. In contrast to Gordon Gekko, one might consider this passage from the Gospel
according to Saint Luke: “Watch out! Be on your guard against all kinds of greed; a man’s life
does not consist in the abundance of his possessions” (Luke 12:15). Indeed, many religious tradi-
tions regard greed—sometimes called avarice, covetousness, or cupidity—as a sin. Gekko says
“greed is good”; Saint Luke says “greed is bad.” Presumably, they cannot both be right.

With the exception of ethical egoism, Saint Luke seems to be backed up by traditional ethical
theories. Returning to our sandbox with four children and one toy: The greedy child wants the
toy all to him- or herself. The utilitarian will reject this as failing to generate the greatest good for
the greatest number, whereas the deontologist will point out that this is not the kind of act that
would always be the right thing to do. It is probably safe to assume that Saint Luke approved
of the Golden Rule, and we can simply apply it by asking the greedy child: “Would you like it
if some other greedy child took the toy and did not allow anyone else—including you—to play
with it?” The virtue ethicist would see such greed as an extreme: We may desire to have certain
things, but those desires should be moderate. Perhaps we should not desire too little, which
would be an extreme of self-sacrifice, but the extreme of desiring too much is greed, and thus
virtue ethics would reject it.

Does this mean our ethical theories are in fundamental conflict with our economic theories?
In many ways, Gordon Gekko summarized how capitalism works. A business wants to sell the
most goods or offer the most services at the highest prices it can charge, and it wants to capture
the largest market share. Its competitors want to do the same thing. Its customers, on the other
hand, want to get the most goods or services for the lowest prices they can find and will go
to a company’s competitors to do so. There exists, then, competition between customers and
companies, and the end result is that customers get the best price, companies that make the
best product have the highest profits, and companies that charge too much or produce goods
or services of lower quality go out of business. So it is possible that acting in one’s self-interest
(whether as company or customer) reveals that maybe Gordon Gekko is right. Greed is good!

There are some legal restrictions that prevent certain types of greed. Agencies such as the Food
and Drug Administration ensure that companies do not take shortcuts on products that might

mos81165_06_c06.indd 202 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

Classic Vision/age footstock/SuperStock

An enduring contribution of philosopher
Ludwig Feuerbach is the observation that
“you are what you eat.”

make consumers ill. The U.S. Department of Justice Antitrust Division supports competition
among companies and works to prevent monopolies. The U.S. government has sued both IBM
and Microsoft for operating as monopolies. Thus, there are some rules that prevent absolute,
unrestricted greed. However, that does not mean that companies (or customers) should not act
in their own financial best interest.

It unclear how ethical theories treat this apparent conflict between business practice and moral
values. Perhaps one might say that in certain contexts greed is good, whereas in other contexts
it is wrong. Perhaps the term greedy is not adequate for describing entities or individuals who
seek the biggest profits or the lowest prices. Or we might say that businesses should not follow
the same moral code as individuals. We should also consider that many outrageously profitable
companies have also made substantial charitable contributions and supported worthy causes.
Cynics might suggest that companies do this to improve their public image or for a tax deduc-
tion, which would then beg the question of whether a company’s reasons for giving to charity
mattered.

In any case we see the difficulty in applying ethical theory. While not many parents would teach
their child the merits of being greedy, how would we explain to the child how the business
world works? The difficulty is illustrated by imagining the child to ask, “So, should I be greedy
or should I not be greedy?”

Vegetarianism

Ethical questions can arise from even the most ordinary activities, such as eating. A once famous,
now somewhat forgotten German philosopher Ludwig Feuerbach (1804–1872) once observed,
“You are what you eat” (1864). We are all familiar with the notion that a healthful diet is impor-
tant and that those who eat foods high in saturated fat, cholesterol and trans fats are at greater

risk for stroke, heart disease, cancer, diabetes, and
other health problems. But aside from health issues,
can there be ethical issues involved with diet? From
one perspective, what people eat may reflect their
relationship to the rest of nature and the extent to
which they seek to be in some kind of harmony with
nature. Another perspective considers how our food
is produced and whether it forces sentient beings to
experience cruelty and pain. Should we care if our
food is borne from the pain and suffering of other
animals? Should we want to know more about the
process, or is it acceptable to be ignorant of how our
food is produced? The German politician Otto von
Bismarck once pointed out that one cannot enjoy
politics or sausage if one closely observes how either
is made. Would someone continue to enjoy eating
meat if he or she knew how the animal from which it
came was raised?

We might begin addressing this issue by identifying
the extreme positions relative to food. At one end
of the spectrum, there is the extreme omnivore: a
person who eats anything and everything he or she

mos81165_06_c06.indd 203 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

wants and does not care about how that food is produced. At the other end of the spectrum
is the extreme vegan, a person who refuses to eat any animal products or by-products such as
butter, eggs, cheese, honey, or food containing these, such as pastas and breads. Few people
adopt either such extreme: Even an extreme omnivore might (we hope) draw the line at eating
human flesh, and an extreme vegan may be willing to eat some things, such as yeast or apples,
even though it may be difficult to determine whether yeast is in the relevant sense of “alive,”
and often apples are glazed with a shellac made from insects.

Great Ideas: Are You What You Eat?

Which of the following would you definitely eat? Which would you possibly eat? Are there any items
in this list you would never eat? What kind of reasons did you use to distinguish among the three
categories?

• Cat
• Dog
• Chimpanzee
• Chicken
• Rat
• Pig
• Squirrel

• Horse
• Soybean
• Lobster
• Cockroach
• Bonobo
• Rabbit
• Spider

• Human
• Cow
• Dolphin
• Octopus
• Snail
• Grapes

Take one of the foods you would possibly eat and justify your choice using one of the ethical theories
discussed in this chapter.

Within these extremes is a wide range of positions. Some carnivores do not eat red meat (beef,
pork, and sometimes duck) but only chicken and fish. Some vegetarians eat eggs, cheese, and
butter, and others make an exception for fish. Some people say they will not eat anything with
a personality or anything with a face! What people are willing to consume may depend on their
culture or religion: In some cultures, eating pork is thought to be not just revolting but a violation
of strict religious dietary laws. In the United States many are repulsed by the idea of eating dogs
or chimpanzees, but other cultures may eat both without giving it any more thought than some
Americans would to eating a pork chop.

Speciesism
Can ethicists offer any guidance on determining the right thing to do (or eat)? Ethicist Peter
Singer (b. 1946) has famously argued from the perspective of utilitarianism that animals—includ-
ing humans—deserve some degree of respect because they have “interests.” Singer rejects the
idea that human interests are somehow superior to those of other sentient beings. Minimally,
all animals seek pleasure and avoid pain. We assume, with some good evidence, that rocks
do not feel pain but that cats do. Singer believes that we should take this pain into consider-
ation. To do otherwise is what he calls speciesism, which ignores the interests (and suffering)
of other species. Singer thinks speciesism is no more defensible than racism or sexism. Singer

mos81165_06_c06.indd 204 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics

Read Peter
Singer’s “All
Animals Are
Equal” in

the Chapter
Readings
section of the
Appendix.

(1975) concludes that respecting the greatest good for the greatest number—the greatest
number of sentient beings, that is—offers an argument in favor of vegetarianism or even
veganism.

Singer’s position may be extreme, and his views are controversial. However, supporters
of his view argue that food production methods inflict needless pain and cruelty. For
example, veal is often produced by taking a calf from its mother at birth and raising it in
a small crate in which it cannot turn around or lie down comfortably. The calf is never
allowed any exercise and is fed a milk substitute so that it will produce a prized pink flesh
when it is slaughtered between 12 and 23 weeks of age. Factory-farmed chickens are kept
in small cages, often along with tens of thousands of other chickens; they frequently have
their beaks removed and are injected with growth-producing drugs that make them so fat
they cannot stand up. The crowded conditions also generate a great deal of disease that
quickly spreads from chicken to chicken. These and other methods for raising animals for
food have been criticized for inflicting an unacceptable level of pain.

This is an interesting ethical issue that many people prefer to ignore. It is, after all, consid-
erably easier to enjoy fried chicken if one does not know what the chicken experienced.
Of course, there are many who argue that eating meat itself is not wrong as long as one’s
meat does not comes from large-scale factory farms.

Virtue ethics might make a compelling case on this issue: that one should prevent any cru-
elty that can be avoided and that a moderate approach might include some meat but not
too much, or perhaps meat of some kinds but not others. Aristotle recommended eating
“clear meats,” by which he seemed to mean poultry and fish. It is interesting to consider
whether this course of action might be in agreement with some versions of utilitarianism
(though not Singer’s) as well as some versions of deontology. To be sure, ethical theory
is not, generally, going to determine what we eat, but it might make us pause and think
about whether we have good reasons for eating what we do.

Euthanasia

Ethics can raise troubling questions not only about seemingly ordinary activities like eating,
but also its most difficult and mysterious ones, such as death. Suppose Richard’s wife of
40 years, Elizabeth, has been diagnosed with pancreatic cancer. Elizabeth, who is in her
70s, has been told by several different physicians that the disease is unquestionably ter-
minal; she can expect to live at most another 18 months, over which time she will experi-
ence increasing levels of pain. Drugs can minimize the pain but not fully relieve it. As the
weeks go by, Elizabeth experiences increasingly agonizing pain. Her doctor has given her
the strongest drugs available, and in massive doses, but they seem not to work. Through
it all, Richard has to helplessly watch his wife suffer.

In this type of case, some ethicists (such as James Rachels; 1941–2003) have argued for
euthanasia (from the Greek for “good death”), or the right to die. The argument is
straightforward: A person who is virtually certain to die within a given amount of time
and is experiencing or will experience a lot of pain before he or she dies should be able
to choose an earlier, less painful death. What purpose is served by keeping a person alive
only to experience constant, agonizing pain? This argument is also used to support phy-
sician-assisted suicide (PAS), which is slightly different from euthanasia. In PAS a doctor

mos81165_06_c06.indd 205 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section

6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

Read James
Rachels’s
“Active

and Passive
Euthanasia”

in the
Chapter
Readings

section of the
Appendix.

Read
Philippa
Foot’s

“Killing
and Letting
Die” in the

Chapter
Readings
section of the
Appendix.

provides a patient with a lethal dose of medication or another way of causing death, but
the patient, not the doctor, ends his or her own life. Some countries, such as Netherlands
and Belgium, have made PAS legal. Oregon legalized PAS in 1997; the Supreme Court
upheld Oregon’s “death with dignity” law as constitutional in 2006, and it has since
become legal in Washington and Vermont.

Some of the opposition to euthanasia and PAS comes from an insistence that there is a
difference between killing people and letting them die, as was suggested by philosopher
Philippa Foot (1984) in her work “Killing and Letting Die.” Other opposition is grounded
in religion. In this view, life is a precious gift from God. To end it prematurely is to reject
that gift; only God should determine when life should end. As Saint Thomas Aquinas put
it, “Whoever takes his own life sins against God.” According to some religious traditions,
suicide indicates a lack of trust in God and a rejection of God’s plan. Other nonreligious
objections to PAS are based on the potential consequences of its legalization: that it could
inspire a catastrophic lack of respect for life; that family members or physicians might pres-
sure patients to end their lives prematurely; or that a person may end his or her life not
because of terminal illness but due to a treatable condition such as depression.

Assuming Elizabeth has PAS available as an option, she and her husband still confront
an extremely difficult decision, one that has to be made under the most challenging cir-
cumstances. Even though ethics may help clarify what is at stake, it may not ultimately
be able to design a satisfactory solution. Also, the effects of such ethical decisions may
not always be limited to the individual. If Elizabeth terminates her life via PAS, her decision
affects many others and is representative of just one view within her larger society. Others
may condemn her decision on the basis of their own ethical or religious views, though it
is questionable whether they have the right to insist their views be the basis of universally
enforced laws. We probably do not think kosher laws—such as the prohibition on eating
pork—should be imposed on those who do not keep kosher. Should a Roman Catholic’s
view be imposed on someone who does not share such beliefs or even actively rejects
them?

Many argue that a compromise is to continue to develop drugs and other forms of pallia-
tive care—treatment that reduces suffering—to alleviate a terminally ill person’s anguish.
The hospice movement emphasizes the reduction of end-of-life suffering and promotes
death with dignity, and it has thus become an increasingly attractive option for those who
resist endorsing PAS.

6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

Ethical theory can do a great deal to clarify what is at stake and help us better evaluate our choices. It can be challenging, however, to distinguish between ethical questions that confront individuals and those that involve large parts or even all of society. This
is the focus of our next discussion. Because these questions affect everyone, we must
consider how everyone’s voices can be integrated into solutions, or why, perhaps, such
solutions should be left to experts. We will conclude by considering whether we can truly
make sense of the distinction between individual and social ethical decisions.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 206 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

Animal Rights

We touched on the question of animal rights when discussing ethical issues related to eating
meat and vegetarianism. Ethics can also help us navigate other issues in the relationship between
humans and animals. As we consider some of these, recall that humans are of course animals.
Too frequently animal rights discussions proceed in terms of the contrast between humans and
animals. We may be different kinds of animals, or possess qualities other animals do not; but we
also have a number of things in common with the rest of the animal kingdom. Here, however,
we will use “animals” to refer to the nonhuman kind.

What We Have in Common
For centuries the distinction between humans and animals was taken for granted, and a sharp
line between them was easily drawn. René Descartes, for instance, regarded animals as simply
physical bodies that lacked minds or souls; thus, animals were similar to organic machines. This
is in line with a long history of Western and Christian thinking. Another aspect of that tradition,
sometimes called the great chain of being, ranks all things from highest to lowest: God, followed
by the angels, then human beings, then other animals, then plants. There are a number of dis-
tinctions within these categories as well; some cultures or societies rank kings higher than other
humans, men higher than women, some classes of angels above others, and some even rank
certain plants above others, so that the oak tree is superior to the yew tree.

In contemporary times, however, research and interaction with some species such as cetaceans
(whales, dolphins) and primates (chimpanzees, bonobos) make drawing the line between human
beings and other animals more difficult. Research has indicated that nonhuman animals may do
many of the things once regarded as uniquely human, such as make tools, develop plans, grieve,
remember, and use language. In addition, biologists have demonstrated that human DNA and
chimpanzee DNA overlap between 95% and 98%. Primatologists have suggested that the DNA
of bonobos overlaps with human DNA to an even greater extent (Navin, Thomas, NISC Com-
parative Sequencing Program, & Yi, 2006). In light of these discoveries, some have proposed the
propensity for religion, the ability to pretend, the sense of time, and even essential differences in
the brain as qualities that makes humans unique.

Great Ideas: Are There Limits to the Way
We Treat Animals?

Given the account of animal sentience, intelligence, and their ability to feel pain, are there any animals
you would hesitate to submit to drug or product testing if those tests involved experiencing severe
levels of pain and then death?

Reflection Questions:

1. Identify one nonhuman animal you would approve of and one you would object to being
used for such testing.

2. Identify the differences that informed your response.
3. If you cannot name one animal in each category—either because you see no differences

or because you think no animals should be treated this way—explain what your position
implies for other ways animals are treated.

4. If all animals could be treated in the way described, does that mean there is no such thing
as “cruelty to animals”?

5. If no animals should be treated in the way described, what does that imply about how
humans test drugs for their safety and efficacy?

mos81165_06_c06.indd 207 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

One could conclude that drawing the line between human beings and other animals is arbitrary
and depends on controversial criteria. For instance, would it seem odd to give crabs or mice the
same respect we might think bonobos and dolphins deserve? If the line all the way from human
beings to, say, bacteria is continuous and without any gaps, then anywhere we draw the line will
be controversial and, to a certain extent, involve guesswork. One solution is to simply distinguish
humans from other animals, but that seems more an assumption rather than a defensible position.

Where Do We Draw the Line?
Drawing this line is essential to the question of animal rights. Cultures vary on their acceptance
of acts done with and to animals, such as making clothes and shoes from their body parts;
testing pharmaceuticals and perfumes on them; and even watching them fight to the death
for entertainment or sport. For example, many Americans objected strongly when professional
football player Michael Vick was involved in dogfighting. Yet other countries regularly stage bull-
fights, which often conclude with a ritualized death of the bull. In the United States some groups
object to raising, killing, and skinning animals for fur, whereas others regard such criticism as too
sensitive. Does the fact that people need safe, effective drugs mean that chimpanzees should be
subjected to medical testing? One such test, called the Draize test, applies a substance (a cos-
metic or other product) to an animal that is restrained and conscious; scientists then record the
substance’s effects (burning, toxicity, and so on). Is this test necessary or useful?

Responses to these issues often depend on our relationship to other animals. As Descartes pro-
posed, if we recognize humans as unique and all other animals as inferior, there is no obvious
problem in treating other animals as we wish. On the other hand, those who propose that we
draw the line at sentience (as does Peter Singer) would have a problem with testing on animals,
using animal products, bullfighting, and even eating honey or using leather products. Some-
where in between may be a response that many find satisfactory—a compromise that says tor-
turing animals for perfume or fur is unnecessary but that subjecting them to tests that improve
human life and health is acceptable. This compromise incorporates the idea that cruelty to other
animals not only inflicts needless pain and suffering but also says a good bit about those who
are willing to inflict that pain and suffering.

The Environment

Many ethical issues are also political ones, meaning that many choices we make as individuals
significantly affect the larger community. At the same time, the community imposes restrictions
and laws that limit our choices as individuals, often for good reason. Few would oppose laws that
require everyone to stop at red lights or drive in the same direction on the same side of the road.

One set of political or social issues is known as environmental ethics. This is the study of obli-
gations and values relating to the environment, including any human obligations and values.
Many philosophers and religious traditions have considered the relationship between human
beings and the environment. Aristotle suggested that all things are made by nature for human
beings; that is, the value of things is what they can produce for humans. Genesis 1:26 states,
“And God said, Let us make man in our image, after our likeness: and let them have dominion
over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth,
and over every creeping thing that creepeth upon the earth.” Some have interpreted the notion
of dominion to mean that humans are masters of the earth and can do with it what they please.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 208 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

In this view, nature is an instrument to achieve other human goals and is therefore said to pos-
sess “instrumental value.” Thus, just as a spoon may have instrumental value in allowing me
to achieve my goal of eating, the group of plants that produces digitalis may have instrumental
value in the medicine they can create for patients with heart conditions. Of course, something
also has value if people get pleasure and enjoyment from it, and so one would be able to say
that a particularly vibrant sunset has instrumental value in providing the pleasure humans get
from experiencing it.

More recently, however, many environmental ethicists have argued that things other than human
beings have intrinsic value, meaning that they have value in themselves and not for some other
purpose. This view rejects the assumption that only human beings possess intrinsic value and
argues that other things have a right to exist not solely because of some human purpose they
serve but simply because they are part of nature and the universe. This is a controversial view, and
one that is in fact quite old. Many religious traditions regard the earth as a sacred gift that must
be cared for and protected. This seems to be the idea expressed in Ezekiel 34:18: “Seemeth it a
small thing unto you to have eaten up the good pasture, but ye must tread down with your feet
the residue of your pastures? and to have drunk of the deep waters, but ye must foul the residue
with your feet?” Many Native American traditions have also regarded the relationship between
people and their environment as sacred. As one ancient Native American proverb states:

Treat the earth well.

It was not given to you by your parents,

it was loaned to you by your children.

We do not inherit the Earth from our Ancestors,

we borrow it from our Children.

Thus, we have two distinct ways of interpreting the relationship between human beings and their
environment. One regards the environment as possessing solely instrumental value (although
this does not necessarily endorse the idea of using it however one pleases); the other regards the
environment as possessing intrinsic value, thus preventing it from being treated simply instru-
mentally and requiring respect. Of course, there are many different interpretations of each of
these positions, as well as positions that seek some degree of compromise between them, or
even combine the two views. We can contrast the two perspectives more clearly with a specific
example.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 209 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

Great Ideas: Ethics, Economics, and the Environment

You are the CEO of Smith Petroleum. Large amounts of oil have been discovered in the middle of Yel-
lowstone National Park. The oil industry claims that the reserves in Yellowstone will lower gas prices
in the United States by 10 cents a gallon and create at least 10,000 new jobs. Both private environ-
mental groups and federal agencies, however, have described the environmental damage posed by
the drilling as “catastrophic.”

The decision to drill is entirely yours to make. Before you answer the following questions, you may
wish to visit this link:

http://www.nps.gov/yell/index.htm

Reflection Questions:

1. What is your decision?
2. How do you justify your decision from an economic and environmental standpoint?
3. What ethical issues are involved?
4. If you decided to drill, how do you respond to someone who claims that Yellowstone’s rock

formations are both enormous and irreplaceable?
5. What are the costs and benefits involved in your decision? Are they solely economic costs

and benefits, or are there other factors you must consider?
6. Does your view change on this when you remember that occasionally oil companies have

made predictions that were overly optimistic?

Ethics of Extinction
Consider the dwarf wedge mussel, an aquatic mollusk found exclusively on the Atlantic coast
of North America. This mussel has become extinct in Canada and is severely endangered in the
United States. It has very little obvious use to human beings. It does not seem to provide any
particularly essential medicinal value, is not eaten, and does not offer much in terms of aesthetic
value or beauty to human observers since it spends most of its time buried completely in the
bottom of streams and rivers.

This animal’s survival may well depend on whether it is regarded in terms of possessing instru-
mental or intrinsic value. Those who see little use for it may not particularly care if it goes extinct,
beyond some possible repercussions in the rest of the food chain. However, the instrumentalist
perspective would suggest that if the mussel plays a crucial role in its ecosystem that affects the
fishing industry, this might be reason enough to prevent the mussel’s extinction. (Some instru-
mentalists tend to err on the side of caution in these cases, recognizing that human beings may
not always be wholly aware of what value a given organism might have; it might be something
that has yet to be discovered.)

The intrinsic perspective does not need to specify some value or product the mussel offers
human beings; its existence as part of an environmental subsystem gives it intrinsic value. We
should simply do what is reasonable to protect the mussel and prevent its extinction out of our
respect for the earth in general and this little part of it specifically. Some might think it is silly to
protect such an odd little critter. Others may argue not protecting it is silly. For example, suppose
a major threat to this mussel is chemical runoff from golf courses. Are we genuine stewards of
an environment if we allow species to go extinct in order to preserve the right to hit a small white
ball relatively large distances with the goal of placing it in a hole that is 4.25 inches in diameter?

mos81165_06_c06.indd 210 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

Population growth, the economic and technological development of large countries such as
India and China, and the difficulty in determining the costs and benefits of specific economic and
developmental policies are all other issues that fall under this category. Humans have become
considerably more aware that resources are finite, and many environmental ethicists insist that
we realize we are dependent on the earth and not treat it as a source of riches to exploit and
plunder. Some have likened the earth to a spaceship on which humans are traveling. From that
perspective, the earth looks more like a home to be cared for than a department or grocery store
from which we take things without regard to the consequences.

The Personal and the Political

We began by looking at certain kinds of behavior—keeping promises, end of life issues, even
determining what to eat—that seem to be based on individual choices that more or less only
affect the person who makes them (obviously, if one breaks a promise, it affects the person to
whom the promise was made). We then considered more general ethical questions that affect
whole communities. Here we will conclude our discussion of ethics by looking at the distinction
between the individual and society, a line that is not easily drawn.

Consider “victimless crimes” (sometimes called consensual crimes), activities that are against the
law but do not physically harm a person or property, or were voluntarily (consensually) entered
into. Examples of victimless crimes include smoking marijuana, failing to wear seat belts and
motorcycle helmets, committing suicide, as well as engaging in prostitution, sodomy, or bungee
jumping. The question is whether the state, or society, has the right to prevent a person from
engaging in such activities. Those who stress minimal state involvement and emphasize a libertar-
ian approach to state authority suggest that drug laws, pornography laws, curfews for teenagers,
and even driver’s licenses are beyond the legitimate scope of what government can legislate.

Victimless crimes help clarify government’s legitimate role and also demonstrate that society’s rules
can change over time. For instance, many states had laws against sodomy for decades. Even though
sodomy is a general term used to describe
nonreproductive sex acts—acts that can-
not lead to reproduction—sodomy laws
were generally enforced only against
homosexuals. Such laws were ruled
unconstitutional in the United States in
2003 but are still found in other coun-
tries’ legal codes. Another example are
sumptuary laws, which were designed to
prevent extravagant consumption. The
Massachusetts Bay Colony, for example,
prohibited people who did not have sub-
stantial wealth from wearing lace, hat-
bands, belts, or capes.

Laws that prohibit activities that are
very common and widely accepted may
not effectively curb behavior, and may
even worsen it. Many have argued that
the ban on alcohol during Prohibition
(1919–1933) was both widely ignored

Associated Press

It is sometimes argued that banning a victimless crime
could generate more victims than the banned activity. An
example is the 18th Amendment banning alcohol in the
United States. Prohibition gave rise to organized crime
and gangsters like Lucky Luciano, shown here at right.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 211 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.4 Social Issues in Ethics

Read Virginia
Held’s

“Feminist
Transfor-
mations
of Moral

Theory” in
the Chapter

Readings
section of the
Appendix.

and allowed criminals to develop powerful criminal organizations. If this objection is cor-
rect, then banning the victimless crime of drinking alcohol generated more victims than
drinking itself would have caused.

From a different perspective, however, it has been argued that many so-called victim-
less crimes cannot be removed from their social context. Take as an example Al, whose
occasional yet illegal marijuana use seems to harm no one but himself (and it is debat-
able whether he is even doing that). Those defending this law might argue that Al and
everyone else who violates the laws against marijuana financially support drug cartels
and criminals who have corrupted governments, murdered police officers, politicians, and
judges, supported terrorism, and numerous other serious crimes. From this perspective,
we may want to ask if Al’s marijuana habit is in fact a victimless crime or if the larger con-
text in which he buys marijuana must be considered.

Prostitution is another so-called victimless activity prohibited in some countries (such as
the United States, except in a small part of Nevada). Two distinct issues arise here: whether
engaging in sex as a prostitute or a customer should be illegal and whether the victims—if
there are any—are the result of the activity or a result of the activity being illegal. The lib-
ertarian perspective argues that prostitution involves a voluntary, consensual agreement
between two adults in which the government has no legitimate right to interfere. Those
who oppose legal prostitution argue that prostitutes face a wide variety of dangers from
both customers and pimps, including rape and battery. They also argue that many prosti-
tutes sell sex out of economic necessity, and thus it should not be regarded as voluntary.
Furthermore, many impoverished and desperate young women are sold against their will
into prostitution. How we describe the situation may determine our moral evaluation of it.

The relationship between the personal and the political is an issue that Virginia Held con-
fronts in her article about feminist responses to ethical theory. The personal realm has
often been aligned with the feminine while the political has often been aligned with
the masculine. Women are thought of as participating in the life of the home (the per-
sonal) while men have been thought to lead the life of the state (political). Held examines
assumptions about the role of women in society and the ways that women are working
in the ethical tradition to provide a feminine voice in a world that is dominated by the
masculine.

As we have seen, some activities that were once illegal have become legal, or at least
“decriminalized,” presumably due to society’s changing standards. Perhaps this means, as
the saying goes, that “you cannot legislate morality,” meaning that the state simply is not
good at legislating ethical choices. However, we legislate morality all the time. A society
legislates against murder on the assumption that it is wrong. No one responds to the fact
that people continue to murder each other by recommending that we get rid of laws that
make murder illegal. Ethics provides some guidance but offers no clear-cut set of rules to
determine an answer on which everyone will agree. Ethics can clarify how we determine
the relationship between the individual citizen and their society. Is it a laissez-faire society?
Or is it a society that exerts its power to ensure that all its members are treated fairly and
given equal access to opportunity? How we answer that question plays an important role
in how we look at a society’s laws, rules, and informal policies. That answer will in turn
help us evaluate the morality of the various activities in which people and communities
engage.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 212 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section

6.5 Summary and Resources

6.5 Summary and Resources

Chapter Highlights

• Philosophers have developed substantial and complex approaches to solving ethical
issues, including utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics.

• Other ethical views, known as metaethics, raise significant questions about how the
discipline of ethics should be understood.

• Applying ethical theory to specific problems reveals that a more rigorous understanding
of those theories can help clarify those problems though not necessarily offer solutions.

Philosopher Vignette:

John Stuart Mill

John Stuart Mill was born in a London suburb in 1806. His
father, James Mill, undertook his education, and John began
study of Greek at the age of 3 and Latin at the age of 8. By the
time he was getting ready for what most would call the fresh-
man year of high school, Mill had read most of the ancient clas-
sics and intensely studied history, mathematics, and economics.
At the age of 20, Mill suffered from serious depression that he
attributed to his rigorously analytical education. Mill connected
to his emotions through the poetry of William Wordsworth, and
over time his depression faded.

In 1830 Mill met Harriet Taylor. Taylor was married at the time,
but they began a friendship that ultimately led to marriage 21
years later. It is generally believed that Mill and Taylor’s relation-
ship was platonic until Taylor’s husband died. They were married
two years after Taylor’s husband’s death. Mill found great com-
fort and inspiration in their relationship. He felt such a strong emotional and intellectual connection
to her that, after her tragic death in 1858, he spent half of each year for the rest of his life in Avignon,
France, just to be close to her grave. He was ultimately buried next to her when he died in 1873.

Mill’s relationship with Taylor changed his views about the ends that ought to be pursued in the realm
of human happiness and well-being. Mill believed in gender equality, and he worked with Taylor to
complete his work On the Subjection of Women, an extended argument that attempts to expand the
notion of women’s rights and criticizes some of the restrictions and obstacles women faced.

Mill wrote on a wide array of philosophical topics, including logic, politics, equality, economics, reli-
gion, and ethics. He is best known for Utilitarianism, in which he attempts to refine the definition of
utilitarianism, define its ultimate aims, and refute arguments against it. Mill’s ethical system is based
on the principle (what he calls “the greatest happiness principle”) that the best action is the one that
creates the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people.

Mill—along with American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce—is widely considered to be the most
important English-speaking philosopher of the 19th century. His views on gender equality and social
welfare were ahead of his time. His writings reflect a keen intellect that was able to incisively and
clearly break down problems and brilliantly present his own arguments and positions. Mill sought to
bring about a better world, one in which all humans enjoyed equality and pursued the pleasures of
the mind. His works paved the way for much of our current thinking about justice, equality, and social
harmony.

Photos.com/© Getty Images/Thinkstock

John Stuart Mill

mos81165_06_c06.indd 213 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.5 Summary and Resources

Case Study: Lifeboat Ethics

In the 1974 article “Lifeboat Ethics: The Case Against Helping the Poor,” Garrett Hardin presents an
ethical thought experiment regarding the issue of the environment and resource distribution around
the world. Hardin’s primary question is whether all humans have an equal right to an equal share of
the earth’s resources. He suggests that we imagine the rich countries of the world as lifeboats. Each
lifeboat represents a country’s resources (land, clean water, resources used for profit, oil, etc.). The
more resources a country has, the bigger its boat. In the water surrounding each lifeboat are people
swimming. These swimmers represent the world’s poor people. Suppose our lifeboat is called the
United States and has 60 seats total, 50 of which are taken. Around the boat are 100 swimmers. How
do we determine to whom to give the 10 remaining seats?

Hardin claims that the first option is to try applying Christian or Marxist philosophy. In these cases we
would have to take everyone into our boat, as each person is no more important than any other, and
all deserve to be saved. However, having 150 people in a boat designed for 60 means that the boat
will fall apart or capsize, and everyone will drown.

The second option is to choose 10 people from the 100 swimmers to allow onto the boat. But how to
choose? Will we choose those who are first? The neediest? Those with the best rowing or boat-repair
skills? We must also consider that once we fill all the seats, we lose our “safety factor.” With 10 seats
still open, we have room to move people around or seat new passengers that are born on the boat.
Or, should we lose a part of our ship, the 50 passengers would still be safe because of the 10 empty
seats. Hardin claims that it is important to seat people, but it is equally important to leave some seats
open. Therefore, in order to ensure the safety and survival of all the boat’s passengers, we need to
prevent swimmers from boarding our vessel.

Hardin says that people who feel guilty for preventing swimmers from boarding the boat can give
up their spot. The swimmer who climbs into your seat will not feel badly about this turn of events.
Hardin claims that as people jump out and climb on, the boat will “purge itself” of feelings of guilt.
At some point none of the passengers will feel badly about the swimmers in the water, at least not
badly enough to give up their own seat.

Hardin uses this thought experiment to critique socialist ideals as well as the idea of a world food bank.
He believes that opening up resources to allow everyone equal access creates a “ruin of the com-
mons.” If the world established a food bank out of which poorer countries could take food when they
did not have the resources to feed their populations, the world would be taxed beyond its capacity,
which would result in even greater catastrophe. For example, suppose country X can sustain 50 mil-
lion people. However, their population has risen to 70 million over the past 10 years, and their leaders
have taken food out of the food bank to feed everyone. Suddenly, the country experiences a severe
drought, and its resources cannot be distributed quickly enough. Rather than a few hundred thousand
people dying if the population were still at 50 million, 20 million people are now in danger of dying.

At first glance, Hardin’s analysis seems callous and arbitrary. However, when further analyzed, it is
possible to see that Hardin’s underlying motivation is not only to prevent large crises like famine, but
also to create responsible citizens who understand the importance of not overly taxing the world’s
resources. Consider that 7 billion humans now live on earth, compared with 1 billion in 1818. Hardin
believed that the best world would be one in which nations kept some open seats on their lifeboats,
even when that meant letting others drown in the sea.

Reflection Questions:

1. Do you find Hardin’s analysis logistically convincing? Ethically convincing? Why or why not?
2. Does the perspective from which one confronts this issue matter in these cases? If you

were a swimmer as opposed to a passenger, would that make a difference in the way you
viewed things?

(continued)

mos81165_06_c06.indd 214 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.5 Summary and Resources

Critical Thinking Questions

1. Identify one of the Aristotelian virtues you think is important for a moral person to
have. Describe what it would be like to have too much of this feature and what it
would be like to have too little of this feature.

2. Relativism is a very popular view. Describe a situation in which you think relativism
might not provide the best response, and explain why. If you cannot do that, explain
why that means that ultimately nothing can be called wrong, no matter how evil it
may appear.

3. Explain what kind of responsibilities the current generation has, if any, to future gen-
erations in terms of treating the environment well. If you think the current generation
has no such obligations, discuss whether the generation before you should have had
such an obligation and what the implications are if they did not.

4. When you think about the ways that you try to live an ethically good life, which ethical
theory do you think most directly aligns with the motives and/or ethical considerations
that you take into account when you make moral decisions?

5. One common critique of virtue ethics is that there is not a universal standard by which
one can judge whether or not one has achieved the virtuous characteristic. How do
you think that one can tell whether or not one has maximized a virtue in her or his
life? Which three virtues do you think are most important in your own life? Why?

6. Is it necessary to have a grounding for one’s ethical actions and beliefs, or is ethics
something that naturally emerges and that people recognize intuitively? Is there another
option?

7. Is it possible to create positive ethical beliefs in people who seem to be immoral? How
can one go about creating those dispositions and actions? Are some people just natu-
rally more ethical than others?

8. Do you think that it is acceptable to sacrifice a single person for the good of the many?
Why or why not? What if the person is a serial rapist? Does that change your view? If
so, why? What if the person is your mother? Does that change your view? If so, why?

9. Feminist philosophers have critiqued the history of ethical philosophy due to many fac-
tors. It is obvious that this history has been dominated by masculine perspectives and
philosophies. In addition, others have claimed that men tend to focus on duty, respect,
and autonomy, whereas women’s ethical thinking aligns more with responsiveness, care,
and community. Do you think that men and women think differently when it comes to
ethics? If so, what does that mean about religious and philosophical conceptions of eth-
ics that rely on a male perspective? Are they in some sense inadequate? Why?

Case Study: Lifeboat Ethics (continued)

3. What is humanity’s responsibility regarding reproduction? Is the ethical human the one who
refuses to procreate so as not to add to the world’s population? Why or why not?

4. Is there a way to create more seats in the lifeboat using no additional resources?
5. Do humans deserve the right to life, even if they have been irresponsibly brought into the

world? Why or why not?

mos81165_06_c06.indd 215 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.5 Summary and Resources

Additional Resources

Ethical Theory

Some detailed descriptions of various ethical theories can be found here:

http://ethics.sandiego.edu/theories/Intro/index.asp

Kantian Ethics

Nigel Warburton provides an introduction to Kantian ethics at:

http://virtualphilosopher.com

Nietzsche

A discussion of Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morality under the heading “Christopher Janaway on
Nietzsche on Morality” is available at:

http://www.philosophybites.com

A discussion of many of the views that have been attributed, wrongly, to Nietzsche, under the
heading “Brian Leiter on Nietzsche Myths” is available at:

http://www.philosophybites.com

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

A development of issues surrounding various versions of egoism can be found here:

http://instruct.westvalley.edu/lafave/Egoism.html

Utilitarianism

A number of discussions of ethics, including a discussion of rule utilitarianism by British
American philosopher Brad Hooker, under the title “Consequentialism” is available at:

http://www.philosophybites.com
Virtue Ethics

A 2-minute introduction to Aristotle’s virtue ethics, presented under the predictable title
“Virtue Ethics” is available here:

http://philinstall.uoregon.edu

mos81165_06_c06.indd 216 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.5 Summary and Resources

Chapter Reading List

Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill

Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals, Immanuel Kant

Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle

After Virtue, Alasdair MacIntyre

“Psychological Egoism,” Joel Feinberg

Beyond Good and Evil, Friedrich Nietzsche

“All Animals Are Equal,” Peter Singer

“Active and Passive Euthanasia,” James Rachels

“Killing and Letting Die,” Philippa Foot

“Feminist Transformations of Moral Theory,” Virginia Held

Key Terms

act utilitarianism An interpretation of
utilitarianism that focuses on a given act and
evaluates it in terms of that act generating
the greatest net good for the greatest num-
ber of people.

categorical imperative An obligation or
demand that holds for an agent without
qualification, or unconditionally.

consequentialist A type of ethical theory
that includes utilitarianism and evaluates the
morality of an act in terms of the results it
produces.

environmental ethics The study of obliga-
tions and values relating to the environment,
including any human obligations and values.

ethical egoism The ethical view that a
person should do what is in that person’s
self-interest.

eudaimonia The state of being justifiably
happy and content, particularly emphasized
in Aristotelian ethics.

euthanasia The intentional causing of death
in order relieve pain or suffering.

golden mean The appropriate place
between two extremes; in Aristotelian ethics,
virtues are those characteristics that achieve
this balance.

instrumentalist A view that ideas, con-
cepts, and other claims are valuable to the
extent that they can be used to bring about
some result.

magnanimity The virtue of having a great
soul, or the character of being nobly gener-
ous; regarded as a particularly important
virtue by Aristotle.

metaethics The study of concepts, claims,
and assumptions that ethics uses to evaluate
moral actions.

phronesis The ability to judge appropriately,
to determine what appropriate ends are
and how to achieve them; often translated
as “practical wisdom” and often associated
with Aristotle.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 217 1/6/14 2:33 PM

CHAPTER 6Section 6.5 Summary and Resources

physician-assisted suicide (PAS) A pro-
cedure whereby a physician aids a patient
in ending his or her life, although the act (in
contrast to euthanasia) is carried out by the
patient.

reflective equilibrium A procedure, ide-
ally leading to the most reasonable result,
whereby reflection on various factors leads to
the fullest possible consideration of the fac-
tors underlying a decision.

rule utilitarianism An interpretation of
utilitarianism that emphasizes identifying
those rules that, when generally adopted,
will lead to the greatest net good for the
greatest number.

speciesism The discrimination against a
species; often a critical term used to charac-
terize human behavior relative to nonhuman
animals.

temperance A virtue that emphasizes mod-
eration and control of one’s natural appetites
and keeps them in check.

utilitarianism The ethical theory that evalu-
ates the morality of an act or a rule in terms
of its consequences, and whereby an act is
seen as moral if it produces the greatest net
good for the greatest number.

utility A term used to measure and evaluate
satisfaction and benefits; used to compare
various activities in terms of their success in
maximizing utility.

virtue ethics An approach to moral and
ethical questions that focuses on a person’s
character.

mos81165_06_c06.indd 218 1/6/14 2:33 PM

Still stressed from student homework?
Get quality assistance from academic writers!

Order your essay today and save 25% with the discount code LAVENDER