Your primary objective is to analyze and interpret an ethics’ case study and apply critical thinking to best interpret main case issues, and their resolution in light of the facts provided. Write a minimum 5 double spaces pages case study critical analysis’ essay. Refer to required readings!
Your primary objective is to analyze and interpret an ethics’ case study and apply critical thinking to best interpret main case issues, and their resolution in light of the facts provided. Please, follow the next instructions:
1. Quickly read the case. Get a feel for the content and the information that needs to be analyzed. Focus on the first few and last few paragraphs which often provide strong insights into the problem(s) and issue(s).
2. Read the case very carefully. Try to put yourself in the shoes of the person(s) involved and develop a sense of involvement in the issue(s).
3. Note the key problem areas.
4. Note all relevant facts for each problem area.
5. Logically derive a set of conclusions/responses to the questions that focus on the key issue(s).
6. Write a minimum 5 pages double spaces case study critical analysis’ essay.
Important:
In your essay you should refer to the readings provided in the Learning Modules, use footnotes.
Issues in Ethics
1
st
EDITION
Sam Vaknin, Ph.D.
Editing and Design:
Lidija Rangelovska
Lidija Rangelovska
A Narcissus Publications Imprint, Skopje 2002-5
Not for Sale! Non-commercial edition.
http://www.gutenberg.org/wiki/Main_Page
http://www.gutenberg.org/wiki/Main_Page
© 2002, 2005 Copyright Lidija Rangelovska.
All rights reserved. This book, or any part thereof, may not be used or reproduced in
any manner without written permission from:
Lidija Rangelovska – write to:
palma@unet.com.mk or to
vaknin@link.com.mk
Visit the Author Archive of Dr. Sam Vaknin in “Central Europe Review”:
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
Visit Sam Vaknin’s United Press International (UPI) Article Archive –
Click HERE!
Philosophical Musings and Essays
http://samvak.tripod.com/culture.html
Malignant Self Love – Narcissism Revisited
http://samvak.tripod.com/
Created by: LIDIJA RANGELOVSKA
REPUBLIC OF MACEDONIA
mailto:palma@unet.com.mk
mailto:vaknin@link.com.mk
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/guide.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/
C O N T E N T S
I. Morality as a Mental State
II. Affiliation and Morality
III.
Nature, Aesthetics, Pleasure, and Ethics
IV.
On Being Human
V.
The Encroachment of the Public
VI.
And Then There Were Too Many
VII.
Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species
VIII.
The Myth of the Right to Life
IX.
The Argument for Torture
X.
The Aborted Contract
XI. In Our Own Image –
The Debate about Cloning
XII.
Ethical Relativism and Absolute Taboos
XIII.
The Merits of Stereotypes
XIV. The Happiness of Others
XV. The Egotistic Friend
XVI. The Distributive Justice of the Market
XVII. The Agent-Principal Conundrum
XVIII.
Legalizing Crime
XIX. The Insanity of the Defense
XX. The Impeachment of the President
XXI. The Rights of Animals
XXII.
Just War or a Just War?
XXIII.
Cannibalism and Human Sacrifice
XXIV.
Euthanasia and the Right to Die
XXV. The Auth
or
XXVI. About “After the Rain”
Morality as a Mental State
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
INTRODUCTION
Moral values, rules, principles, and judgements are often
thought of as beliefs or as true beliefs. Those who hold
them to be true beliefs also annex to them a warrant or a
justification (from the “real world”). Yet, it is far more
reasonable to conceive of morality (ethics) as a state of
mind, a mental state. It entails belief, but not necessarily
true belief, or justification. As a mental state, morality
cannot admit the “world” (right and wrong, evidence,
goals, or results) into its logical formal definition. The
world is never part of the definition of a mental state.
Another way of looking at it, though, is that morality
cannot be defined in terms of goals and results – because
these goals and results ARE morality itself. Such a
definition would be tautological.
There is no guarantee that we know when we are in a
certain mental state. Morality is no exception.
An analysis based on the schemata and arguments
proposed by Timothy Williamson follows.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
Moral Mental State – A Synopsis
Morality is the mental state that comprises a series of
attitudes to propositions. There are four classes of moral
propositions: “It is wrong to…”, “It is right to…”, (You
should) do this…”, “(You should) not do this…”. The most
common moral state of mind is: one adheres to p.
Adhering to p has a non-trivial analysis in the more basic
terms of (a component of) believing and (a component of)
knowing, to be conceptually and metaphysically analysed
later. Its conceptual status is questionable because we
need to decompose it to obtain the necessary and
sufficient conditions for its possession (Peacocke, 1992).
It may be a complex (secondary) concept.
Adhering to proposition p is not merely believing that p
and knowing that p but also that something should be so,
if and only if p (moral law).
Morality is not a factive attitude. One believes p to be true
– but knows p to be contingently true (dependent on
epoch, place, and culture). Since knowing is a factive
attitude, the truth it relates to is the contingently true
nature of moral propositions.
Morality relates objects to moral propositions and it is a
mental state (for every p, having a moral mental relation
to p is a mental state).
Adhering to p entails believing p (involves the mental
state of belief). In other words, one cannot adhere without
believing. Being in a moral mental state is both necessary
and sufficient for adhering to p. Since no “truth” is
involved – there is no non-mental component of adhering
to p.
Adhering to p is a conjunction with each of the conjuncts
(believing p and knowing p) a necessary condition – and
the conjunction is necessary and sufficient for adhering to
p.
One doesn’t always know if one adheres to p. Many moral
rules are generated “on the fly”, as a reaction to
circumstances and moral dilemmas. It is possible to
adhere to p falsely (and behave differently when faced
with the harsh test of reality). A sceptic would say that for
any moral proposition p – one is in the position to know
that one doesn’t believe p. Admittedly, it is possible for a
moral agent to adhere to p without being in the position to
know that one adheres to p, as we illustrated above. One
can also fail to adhere to p without knowing that one fails
to adhere to p. As Williamson says “transparency (to be in
the position to know one’s mental state) is false”.
Naturally, one knows one’s mental state better than one
knows other people’s. There is an observational
asymmetry involved. We have non-observational
(privileged) access to our mental state and observational
access to other people’s mental states. Thus, we can say
that we know our morality non-observationally (directly) –
while we are only able to observe other people’s morality.
One believes moral propositions and knows moral
propositions. Whether the belief itself is rational or not, is
debatable. But the moral mental state strongly imitates
rational belief (which relies on reasoning). In other words,
the moral mental state masquerades as a factive attitude,
though it is not. The confusion arises from the normative
nature of knowing and being rational.
Normative elements exist in belief attributions, too, but,
for some reason, are considered “outside the realm of
belief”. Belief, for instance, entails the grasping of mental
content, its rational processing and manipulation,
defeasible reaction to new information.
We will not go here into the distinction offered by
Williamson between “believing truly” (not a mental state,
according to him) and “believing”. Suffice it to say that
adhering to p is a mental state, metaphysically speaking –
and that “adheres to p” is a (complex or secondary) mental
concept. The structure of adheres to p is such that the non-
mental concepts are the content clause of the attitude
ascription and, thus do not render the concept thus
expressed non-mental: adheres to (right and wrong,
evidence, goals, or results).
Williamson’s Mental State Operator calculus is applied.
Origin is essential when we strive to fully understand the
relations between adhering that p and other moral
concepts (right, wrong, justified, etc.). To be in the moral
state requires the adoption of specific paths, causes, and
behaviour modes. Moral justification and moral
judgement are such paths.
Knowing, Believing and their Conjunction
We said above that:
“Adhering to p is a conjunction with each of the conjuncts
(believing p and knowing p) a necessary condition – and
the conjunction is necessary and sufficient for adhering to
p.”
Williamson suggests that one believes p if and only if one
has an attitude to proposition p indiscriminable from
knowing p. Another idea is that to believe p is to treat p as
if one knew p. Thus, knowing is central to believing
though by no means does it account for the entire
spectrum of belief (example: someone who chooses to
believe in God even though he doesn’t know if God
exists). Knowledge does determine what is and is
not
appropriate to believe, though (“standard of
appropriateness”). Evidence helps justify belief.
But knowing as a mental state is possible without having a
concept of knowing. One can treat propositions in the
same way one treats propositions that one knows – even if
one lacks concept of knowing. It is possible (and
practical) to rely on a proposition as a premise if one has a
factive propositional attitude to it. In other words, to treat
the proposition as though it is known and then to believe
in it.
As Williamson says, “believing is a kind of a botched
knowing”. Knowledge is the aim of belief, its goal.
Affiliation and Morality
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also Read:
Morality as a Mental State
Nature, Aesthetics, Pleasure, and Ethics
What should prevail: the imperative to spare the lives of
innocent civilians – or the need to safeguard the lives of
fighter pilots? Precision bombing puts such pilots at great
risk. Avoiding this risk usually results in civilian
casualties (“collateral damage”).
This moral dilemma is often “solved” by applying –
explicitly or implicitly – the principle of “over-riding
affiliation”. We find the two facets of this principle in
Jewish sacred texts: “One is close to oneself” and “Your
city’s poor denizens come first (with regards to charity)”.
One’s affiliation (to a community, or a fraternity) is
determined by one’s position and, more so, perhaps, by
one’s oppositions.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/moral.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/ethics.html
One’s sole organic position is the positive statement “I am
a human being”. All other positions are actually synthetic.
They are subsets of the single organic positive statement
“I am a human being”. They are made of couples of
positive and negative statements. The negative members
of each couple can be fully derived from (and are entirely
dependent on) – and thus fully implied by – the positive
members. Not so the positive members.
Consider the couple “I am an Israeli” and “I am not an
Indian”.
The positive statement “I am an Israeli” implies about 220
CERTAIN (true) negative statements of the type “I am not
… (a citizen of country X, which is not Israel)”, including
the statement “I am not an Indian”. But it cannot be fully
derived from any single true negative statement, or be
entirely dependent upon it.
The relationship, though, is asymmetrical.
The negative statement “I am not an Indian” implies about
220 POSSIBLE positive statements of the type “I am … (a
citizen of country X, which is not India)”, including the
statement “I am an Israeli”. And it can be fully derived
from any single (true) positive statement or be entirely
dependent upon it (the positive statement “I am an Indian”
being, of course, false).
Thus, a positive statement about one’s affiliation (“I am an
Israeli”) immediately generates 220 true and certain
negative statements (one of which is “I am not an
Indian”).
One’s positive self-definition automatically yields
multiple definitions (by negation) of multiple others.
Their positive self-definitions, in turn, negate one’s
positive self-definition.
It is possible for more than one person to have the same
positive self-definition. A positive self-definition shared
by more than one person is what we know as community,
fraternity, nation, state, religion – or, in short, affiliation.
One’s moral obligations towards others who share with
him his positive self-definition (i.e., with whom one is
affiliated) overrides and supersedes one’s moral
obligations towards others who don’t. As an Israeli, my
moral obligation to safeguard the lives of Israeli fighter
pilots overrides and supersedes (subordinates) my moral
obligation to save the lives of innocent civilians, however
numerous, if they are not Israelis.
The more numerous the positive self-definitions I share
with someone (i.e., the more affiliations) , the larger and
more overriding is my moral obligation to him. My moral
obligation towards other humans is superseded by my
moral obligation towards other Israelis, which, in turn, is
superseded by my moral obligation towards the members
of my family.
But this raises some difficulties.
It would appear that the strength of one’s moral
obligations towards other people is determined by the
number of positive self-definitions he shares with them
(i.e., by the number of his affiliations). Moral obligations
are, therefore, not transcendent – but contingent and
relative. They are the outcomes of interactions with others
– but not in the immediate sense, as the personalist
philosopher Emmanuel Levinas postulated.
Rather, they are the solutions yielded by a moral calculus
of shared affiliations. The solutions are best presented as
matrices with specific moral values and obligations
attached to the numerical strengths of one’s affiliations.
Some moral obligations are universal and are related to
one’s organic position as a human being (the “basic
affiliation”). These are the “transcendent
moral values”.
Other moral values and obligations arise as the number of
shared affiliations increases. These are the “derivative
moral values”.
Yet, moral values and obligations do not accumulate.
There is a hierarchy of moral values and obligations. The
universal ones – the ones related to one’s organic position
as a human being – are the WEAKEST. They are
overruled by derivative moral values and obligations
related to one’s affiliations – and are subordinated to them.
The imperative “thou shall not kill (another human
being)” is easily over-ruled by the moral obligation to kill
for one’s country. The imperative “though shall not steal”
is superseded by one’s moral obligation to spy for one’s
nation.
This leads to another startling conclusion:
There is no such thing as a self-consistent moral system.
The derivative moral values and obligations often
contradict each other and almost always conflict with the
universal moral values
and obligations.
In the examples above, killing (for one’s country) and
stealing (for one’s nation) are moral obligations, the
outcomes of the application of derivative moral
values.
Yet, they contradict the universal moral value of the
sanctity of life and the universal moral obligation not to
kill.
Nature, Aesthetics, Pleasure, and Ethics
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
The distinction often made between emotions and
judgements gives rise to a host of conflicting accounts of
morality. Yet, in the same way that the distinction
“observer-observed” is false, so is the distinction between
emotions and judgements. Emotions contain judgements
and judgements are formed by both emotions and the
ratio. Emotions are responses to sensa (see “The Manifold
of Sense”) and inevitably incorporate judgements (and
beliefs) about those sensa. Some of these judgements are
inherent (the outcome of biological evolution), others
cultural, some unconscious, others conscious, and the
result of personal experience. Judgements, on the other
hand, are not compartmentalized. They vigorously interact
with our emotions as they form.
The source of this artificial distinction is the confusion
between moral and natural laws.
We differentiate among four kinds of “right” and “good”.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/sense.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/sense.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/sense.html
THE NATURAL GOOD
There is “right” in the mathematical, physical, or
pragmatic sense. It is “right” to do something in a certain
way. In other words, it is viable, practical, functional, it
coheres with the world. Similarly, we say that it is “good”
to do the “right” thing and that we “ought to” do it. It is
the kind of “right” and “good” that compel us to act
because we “ought to”. If we adopt a different course, if
we neglect, omit, or refuse to act in the “right” and “good”
way, as we “ought to” – we are punished. Nature herself
penalizes such violations. The immutable laws of nature
are the source of the “rightness” and “goodness” of these
courses of action. We are compelled to adopt them –
because we have no other CHOICE. If we construct a
bridge in the “right” and “good” way, as we “ought to” – it
will survive. Otherwise, the laws of nature will make it
collapse and, thus, punish us. We have no choice in the
matter. The laws of nature constrain our moral principles
as well.
THE MORAL GOOD
This lack of choice stands in stark contrast to the “good”
and “right” of morality. The laws of morality cannot be
compared to the laws of nature – nor are they variants or
derivatives thereof. The laws of nature leave us no choice.
The laws of morality rely on our choice.
Yet, the identical vocabulary and syntax we successfully
employ in both cases (the pragmatic and the moral) –
“right action”, “good”, and “ought to” – surely signify a
deep and hidden connection between our dictated
reactions to the laws of nature and our chosen reactions to
the laws of morality (i.e., our reactions to the laws of Man
or God)? Perhaps the principles and rules of morality
ARE laws of nature – but with choice added? Modern
physics incorporates deterministic theories (Newton’s,
Einstein’s) – and theories involving probability and choice
(Quantum Mechanics and its interpretations, especially
the Copenhagen interpretation). Why can’t we conceive of
moral laws as private cases (involving choice,
judgements, beliefs, and emotions) of natural laws?
THE HEDONISTIC GOOD
If so, how can we account for the third, hedonistic, variant
of “good”, “right”, and “ought to”? To live the “good” life
may mean to maximize one’s utility (i.e., happiness, or
pleasure) – but not necessarily to maximize overall utility.
In other words, living the good life is not always a moral
pursuit (if we apply to it Utilitarian or Consequentialist
yardsticks). Yet, here, too, we use the same syntax and
vocabulary. We say that we want to live the “good” life
and to do so, there is a “right action”, which we “ought to”
pursue. Is hedonism a private case of the Laws of Nature
as well? This would be going too far. Is it a private case of
the rules or principles of Morality? It could be – but need
not be. Still, the principle of utility has place in every
cogent description of morality.
THE AESTHETIC GOOD
A fourth kind of “good” is of the aesthetic brand. The
language of aesthetic judgement is identical to the
languages of physics, morality, and hedonism. Aesthetic
values sound strikingly like moral ones and both
resemble, structurally, the laws of nature. We say that
beauty is “right” (symmetric, etc.), that we “ought to”
maximize beauty – and this leads to the right
action.
Replace “beauty” with “good” in any aesthetic statement –
and one gets a moral statement. Moral, natural, aesthetic,
and hedonistic statements are all mutually convertible.
Moreover, an aesthetic experience often leads to moral
action.
AN INTERACTIVE FRAMEWORK
It is safe to say that, when we wish to discuss the nature of
“good” and “right”, the Laws of Nature serve as the
privileged frame of reference. They delimit and constrain
the set of possible states – pragmatic and moral. No moral,
aesthetic, or hedonistic principle or rule can defy, negate,
suspend, or ignore the Laws of Nature. They are the
source of everything that is “good” and “right”. Thus, the
language we use to describe all instances of “good” and
“right” is “natural”. Human choice, of course, does not
exist as far as the Laws of Nature go.
Nature is beautiful – symmetric, elegant, and
parsimonious. Aesthetic values and aesthetic judgements
of “good” (i.e., beautiful) and “right” rely heavily on the
attributes of Nature. Inevitably, they employ the same
vocabulary and syntax. Aesthetics is the bridge between
the functional or correct “good” and “right” – and the
hedonistic “good” and “right”.
Aesthetics is the first order of the interaction between the
WORLD and the MIND. Here, choice is very limited. It is
not possible to “choose” something to be beautiful. It is
either beautiful or it is not (regardless of the objective or
subjective source of the aesthetic judgement).
The hedonist is primarily concerned with the
maximization of his happiness and pleasure. But such
outcomes can be secured only by adhering to aesthetic
values, by rendering aesthetic judgements, and by
maintaining aesthetic standards. The hedonist craves
beauty, pursues perfection, avoids the ugly – in short, the
hedonist is an aesthete. Hedonism is the application of
aesthetic rules, principles, values, and judgements in a
social and cultural setting. Hedonism is aesthetics in
context – the context of being human in a society of
humans. The hedonist has a limited, binary, choice –
between being a hedonist and not being one.
From here it is one step to morality. The principle of
individual utility which underlies hedonism can be easily
generalized to encompass Humanity as a whole. The
social and cultural context is indispensable – there cannot
be meaningful morality outside society. A Robinson
Crusoe – at least until he spotted Friday – is an a-moral
creature. Thus, morality is generalized hedonism with the
added (and crucial) feature of free will and (for all
practical purposes) unrestricted choice. It is what makes
us really human.
On Being Human
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also Read:
The Aborted Contract
In Our Own Image – Cloning
Turing Machines and Universes
Death and the Question of Identity
The Shattered Identity
Are we human because of unique traits and attributes not
shared with either animal or machine? The definition of
“human” is circular: we are human by virtue of the
properties that make us human (i.e., distinct from animal
and machine). It is a definition by negation: that which
separates us from animal and machine is our “human-
ness”.
We are human because we are not animal, nor machine.
But such thinking has been rendered progressively less
tenable by the advent of evolutionary and neo-
evolutionary theories which postulate a continuum in
nature between animals and Man.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/abort.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/cloning.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/turing.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/death.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/identity.html
Our uniqueness is partly quantitative and partly
qualitative. Many animals are capable of cognitively
manipulating symbols and using tools. Few are as adept at
it as we are. These are easily quantifiable differences –
two of many.
Qualitative differences are a lot more difficult to
substantiate. In the absence of privileged access to the
animal mind, we cannot and don’t know if animals feel
guilt, for instance. Do animals love? Do they have a
concept of sin? What about object permanence, meaning,
reasoning, self-awareness, critical thinking? Individuality?
Emotions? Empathy? Is artificial intelligence (AI) an
oxymoron? A machine that passes the Turing Test may
well be described as “human”. But is it really? And if it is
not – why isn’t
it?
Literature is full of stories of monsters – Frankenstein, the
Golem – and androids or anthropoids. Their behavior is
more “humane” than the humans around them. This,
perhaps, is what really sets humans apart: their behavioral
unpredictability. It is yielded by the interaction between
Mankind’s underlying immutable genetically-determined
nature – and Man’s kaleidoscopically changing
environments.
The Constructivists even claim that Human Nature is a
mere cultural artefact. Sociobiologists, on the other hand,
are determinists. They believe that human nature – being
the inevitable and inexorable outcome of our bestial
ancestry – cannot be the subject of moral judgment.
http://samvak.tripod.com/empathy.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/turing.html
An improved Turing Test would look for baffling and
erratic patterns of misbehavior to identify humans. Pico
della Mirandola wrote in “Oration on the Dignity of Man”
that Man was born without a form and can mould and
transform – actually, create – himself at will. Existence
precedes essence, said the Existentialists centuries later.
The one defining human characteristic may be our
awareness of our mortality. The automatically triggered,
“fight or flight”, battle for survival is common to all living
things (and to appropriately programmed machines). Not
so the catalytic effects of imminent death. These are
uniquely human. The appreciation of the fleeting
translates into aesthetics, the uniqueness of our ephemeral
life breeds morality, and the scarcity of time gives rise to
ambition and creativity.
In an infinite life, everything materializes at one time or
another, so the concept of choice is spurious. The
realization of our finiteness forces us to choose among
alternatives. This act of selection is predicated upon the
existence of “free will”. Animals and machines are
thought to be devoid of choice, slaves to their genetic or
human programming.
Yet, all these answers to the question: “What does it mean
to be human” – are lacking.
The set of attributes we designate as human is subject to
profound alteration. Drugs, neuroscience, introspection,
and experience all cause irreversible changes in these
traits and characteristics. The accumulation of these
changes can lead, in principle, to the emergence of new
properties, or to the abolition of old ones.
http://samvak.tripod.com/death.html
Animals and machines are not supposed to possess free
will or exercise it. What, then, about fusions of machines
and humans (bionics)? At which point does a human turn
into a machine? And why should we assume that free will
ceases to exist at that – rather arbitrary – point?
Introspection – the ability to construct self-referential and
recursive models of the world – is supposed to be a
uniquely human quality. What about introspective
machines? Surely, say the critics, such machines are
PROGRAMMED to introspect, as opposed to humans. To
qualify as introspection, it must be WILLED, they
continue. Yet, if introspection is willed – WHO wills it?
Self-willed introspection leads to infinite regression and
formal logical paradoxes.
Moreover, the notion – if not the formal concept – of
“human” rests on many hidden assumptions and
conventions.
Political correctness notwithstanding – why presume that
men and women (or different races) are identically
human? Aristotle thought they were not. A lot separates
males from females – genetically (both genotype and
phenotype) and environmentally (culturally). What is
common to these two sub-species that makes them both
“human”?
Can we conceive of a human without body (i.e., a
Platonian Form, or soul)? Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas
think not. A soul has no existence separate from the body.
A machine-supported energy field with mental states
similar to ours today – would it be considered human?
What about someone in a state of coma – is he or she (or
it) fully human?
Is a new born baby human – or, at least, fully human – and,
if so, in which sense? What about a future human race –
whose features would be unrecognizable to us? Machine-
based intelligence – would it be thought of as human? If
yes, when would it be considered human?
In all these deliberations, we may be confusing “human”
with “person”. The former is a private case of the latter.
Locke’s person is a moral agent, a being responsible for its
actions. It is constituted by the continuity of its mental
states accessible to introspection.
Locke’s is a functional definition. It readily accommodates
non-human persons (machines, energy matrices) if the
functional conditions are satisfied. Thus, an android which
meets the prescribed requirements is more human than a
brain dead person.
Descartes’ objection that one cannot specify conditions of
singularity and identity over time for disembodied souls is
right only if we assume that such “souls” possess no
energy. A bodiless intelligent energy matrix which
maintains its form and identity over time is conceivable.
Certain AI and genetic software programs already do it.
Strawson is Cartesian and Kantian in his definition of a
“person” as a “primitive”. Both the corporeal predicates
and those pertaining to mental states apply equally,
simultaneously, and inseparably to all the individuals of
that type of entity. Human beings are one such entity.
Some, like Wiggins, limit the list of possible persons to
animals – but this is far from rigorously necessary and is
unduly restrictive.
The truth is probably in a synthesis:
A person is any type of fundamental and irreducible entity
whose typical physical individuals (i.e., members) are
capable of continuously experiencing a range of states of
consciousness and permanently having a list of
psychological attributes.
This definition allows for non-animal persons and
recognizes the personhood of a brain damaged human
(“capable of experiencing”). It also incorporates Locke’s
view of humans as possessing an ontological status
similar to “clubs” or “nations” – their personal identity
consists of a variety of interconnected psychological
continuities.
The Encroachment of the Public
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also Read
The Law of Technology and the Technology of Law –
An Epistolary Dialogue
The Ghost in the Net – An Epistolary Dialogue
As Aristotle and John Stuart Mill observed, the private
sphere sets limits, both normative and empirical, to the
rights, powers, and obligations of others. The myriad
forms of undue invasion of the private sphere – such as
rape, burglary, or eavesdropping – are all crimes. Even the
state – this monopolist of legal violence – respects these
boundaries. When it fails to honor the distinction between
public and private – when it is authoritarian or totalitarian
– it loses its legitimacy.
Alas, this vital separation of realms is eroding fast.
In theory, private life is insulated and shielded from social
pressures, the ambit of norms and laws, and even the
strictures of public morality. Reality, though, is different.
The encroachment of the public is inexorable and,
probably, irreversible. The individual is forced to share,
consent to, or merely obey a panoply of laws, norms, and
regulations not only in his or her relationships with others
– but also when solitary.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/lawtech.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/lawtech.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/ghost.html
Failure to comply – and to be seen to be conforming –
leads to dire consequences. In a morbid twist, public
morality is now synonymous with social orthodoxy,
political authority, and the exercise of police powers. The
quiddity, remit, and attendant rights of the private sphere
are now determined publicly, by the state.
In the modern world , privacy – the freedom to withhold
or divulge information – and autonomy – the liberty to act
in certain ways when not in public – are illusory in that
their scope and essence are ever-shifting, reversible, and
culture-dependent. They both are perceived as public
concessions – not as the inalienable (though, perhaps, as
Judith Jarvis Thomson observes, derivative) rights that
they are.
The trend from non-intrusiveness to wholesale
invasiveness is clear:
Only two hundred years ago, the legal regulation of
economic relations between consenting adults – a
quintessentially private matter – would have been
unthinkable and bitterly resisted. Only a century ago, no
bureaucrat would have dared intervene in domestic
affairs. A Man’s home was, indeed, his castle.
Nowadays, the right – let alone dwindling technological
ability – to maintain a private sphere is multiply contested
and challenged. Feminists, such as Catharine MacKinnon,
regard it as a patriarchal stratagem to perpetuate abusive
male domination. Conservatives blame it for mounting
crime and terrorism. Sociologists – and the Church – worry
about social atomization and alienation.
Consequently, today, both one’s business and one’s family
are open books to the authorities, the media, community
groups, non-governmental organizations, and assorted
busybodies.
Which leads us back to privacy, the topic of this essay. It
is often confused with autonomy. The private sphere
comprises both. Yet, the former has little to do with the
latter . Even the acute minds of the Supreme Court of the
United States keep getting it wrong.
In 1890, Justice Louise Brandeis (writing with Samuel
Warren) correctly summed up privacy rights as “the right
to be left alone” – that is, the right to control information
about oneself.
But, nearly a century later, in 1973, in the celebrated case
of Roe vs. Wade, the U.S. Supreme Court, mixing up
privacy and autonomy, found some state regulation of
abortion to be in violation of a woman’s constitutional
right of privacy, implicit in the liberty guarantee of the
Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.
But if unrelated to autonomy – what is privacy all about?
As Julie Inness and many others note, privacy – the
exclusive access to information – is tightly linked to
intimacy. The more intimate the act – excretion, ill-health,
and sex come to mind – the more closely we safeguard its
secrets. By keeping back such data, we show
consideration for the sensitivities of other people and we
enhance our own uniqueness and the special nature of our
close relationships.
Privacy is also inextricably linked to personal safety.
Withholding information makes us less vulnerable to
abuse and exploitation. Our privileged access to some data
guarantees our wellbeing, longevity, status, future, and the
welfare of our family and community. Just consider the
consequences of giving potentially unscrupulous others
access to our bank accounts, credit card numbers, PIN
codes, medical records, industrial and military secrets, or
investment portfolios.
Last, but by no way least, the successful defense of one’s
privacy sustains one’s self-esteem – or what Brandeis and
Warren called “inviolate personality”. The invasion of
privacy provokes an upwelling of shame and indignation
and feelings of indignity, violation, helplessness, a
diminished sense of self-worth, and the triggering of a
host of primitive defense mechanisms. Intrusion upon
one’s private sphere is, as Edward J. Bloustein observes,
traumatic.
Incredibly, modern technology has conspired to do just
that. Reality TV shows, caller ID, electronic monitoring,
computer viruses (especially worms and Trojans),
elaborate databases, marketing profiles, Global
Positioning System (GPS)-enabled cell phones, wireless
networks, smart cards – are all intrusive and counter-
privacy.
Add social policies and trends to the mixture – police
profiling, mandatory drug-testing, workplace keylogging,
the nanny (welfare) state, traffic surveillance, biometric
screening, electronic bracelets – and the long-heralded
demise of privacy is no longer mere scaremongering.
As privacy fades – so do intimacy, personal safety, and
self-esteem (mental health) and with them social
cohesion. The ills of anomic modernity – alienation,
violence, and crime, to mention but three – are, therefore,
directly attributable to diminishing privacy. This is the
irony: that privacy is increasingly breached in the name of
added security (counter-terrorism or crime busting). We
seem to be undermining our societies in order to make
them safer.
And Then There Were Too Many
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
The latest census in Ukraine revealed an apocalyptic drop
of 10% in its population – from 52.5 million a decade ago
to a mere 47.5 million last year. Demographers predict a
precipitous decline of one third in Russia’s impoverished,
inebriated, disillusioned, and ageing citizenry. Births in
many countries in the rich, industrialized, West are below
the replacement rate. These bastions of conspicuous
affluence are shriveling.
Scholars and decision-makers – once terrified by the
Malthusian dystopia of a “population bomb” – are more
sanguine now. Advances in agricultural technology
eradicated hunger even in teeming places like India and
China. And then there is the old idea of progress: birth
rates tend to decline with higher education levels and
growing incomes. Family planning has had resounding
successes in places as diverse as Thailand, China, and
western Africa.
In the near past, fecundity used to compensate for infant
mortality. As the latter declined – so did the former.
Children are means of production in many destitute
countries.
Hence the inordinately large families of the past
– a form of insurance against the economic outcomes of
the inevitable demise of some of one’s off-spring.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
Yet, despite these trends, the world’s populace is
augmented by 80 million people annually. All of them are
born to the younger inhabitants of the more penurious
corners of the Earth. There were only 1 billion people
alive in 1804. The number doubled a century later.
But our last billion – the sixth – required only 12 fertile
years. The entire population of Germany is added every
half a decade to both India and China. Clearly, Mankind’s
growth is out of control, as affirmed in the 1994 Cairo
International Conference on Population and Development.
Dozens of millions of people regularly starve – many of
them to death. In only one corner of the Earth – southern
Africa – food aid is the sole subsistence of entire
countries. More than 18 million people in Zambia,
Malawi, and Angola survived on charitable donations in
1992. More than 10 million expect the same this year,
among them the emaciated denizens of erstwhile food
exporter, Zimbabwe.
According to Medecins Sans Frontiere, AIDS kills 3
million people a year, Tuberculosis another 2 million.
Malaria decimates 2 people every minute. More than 14
million people fall prey to parasitic and infectious
diseases every year – 90% of them in the developing
countries.
Millions emigrate every year in search of a better life.
These massive shifts are facilitated by modern modes of
transportation. But, despite these tectonic relocations – and
despite famine, disease, and war, the classic Malthusian
regulatory mechanisms – the depletion of natural resources
– from arable land to water – is undeniable and gargantuan.
Our pressing environmental issues – global warming,
water stress, salinization, desertification, deforestation,
pollution, loss of biological diversity – and our ominous
social ills – crime at the forefront – are traceable to one,
politically incorrect, truth:
There are too many of us. We are way too numerous. The
population load is unsustainable. We, the survivors, would
be better off if others were to perish. Should population
growth continue unabated – we are all doomed.
Doomed to what?
Numerous Cassandras and countless Jeremiads have been
falsified by history. With proper governance, scientific
research, education, affordable medicines, effective
family planning, and economic growth – this planet can
support even 10-12 billion people. We are not at risk of
physical extinction and never have been.
What is hazarded is not our life – but our quality of life.
As any insurance actuary will attest, we are governed by
statistical datasets.
Consider this single fact:
About 1% of the population suffer from the perniciously
debilitating and all-pervasive mental health disorder,
schizophrenia. At the beginning of the 20th century, there
were 16.5 million schizophrenics – nowadays there are 64
million. Their impact on friends, family, and colleagues is
exponential – and incalculable. This is not a merely
quantitative leap. It is a qualitative phase transition.
Or this:
Large populations lead to the emergence of high density
urban centers. It is inefficient to cultivate ever smaller
plots of land. Surplus manpower moves to centers of
industrial production. A second wave of internal migrants
caters to their needs, thus spawning a service sector.
Network effects generate excess capital and a virtuous
cycle of investment, employment, and consumption
ensues.
But over-crowding breeds violence (as has been
demonstrated in experiments with mice). The sheer
numbers involved serve to magnify and amplify social
anomies, deviate behaviour, and antisocial traits. In the
city, there are more criminals, more perverts, more
victims, more immigrants, and more racists per square
mile.
Moreover, only a planned and orderly urbanization is
desirable. The blights that pass for cities in most third
world countries are the outgrowth of neither premeditation
nor method. These mega-cities are infested with non-
disposed of waste and prone to natural catastrophes and
epidemics.
No one can vouchsafe for a “critical mass” of humans, a
threshold beyond which the species will implode and
vanish.
Luckily, the ebb and flow of human numbers is subject to
three regulatory demographic mechanisms, the combined
action of which gives hope.
The Malthusian Mechanism
Limited resources lead to wars, famine, and diseases and,
thus, to a decrease in human numbers. Mankind has done
well to check famine, fend off disease, and staunch war.
But to have done so without a commensurate policy of
population control was irresponsible.
The Assimilative Mechanism
Mankind is not divorced from nature. Humanity is
destined to be impacted by its choices and by the
reverberations of its actions. Damage caused to the
environment haunts – in a complex feedback loop – the
perpetrators.
Examples:
Immoderate use of antibiotics leads to the eruption of
drug-resistant strains of pathogens. A myriad types of
cancer are caused by human pollution. Man is the victim
of its own destructive excesses.
The Cognitive Mechanism
Humans intentionally limit the propagation of their race
through family planning, abortion, and contraceptives.
Genetic engineering will likely intermesh with these to
produce “enhanced” or “designed” progeny to
specifications.
We must stop procreating. Or, else, pray for a reduction
in our numbers.
This could be achieved benignly, for instance by
colonizing space, or the ocean depths – both remote and
technologically unfeasible possibilities.
Yet, the alternative is cataclysmic. Unintended wars,
rampant disease, and lethal famines will ultimately trim
our numbers – no matter how noble our intentions and
how diligent our efforts to curb them.
Is this a bad thing?
Not necessarily. To my mind, even a Malthusian
resolution is preferable to the alternative of slow decay,
uniform impecuniosity, and perdition in instalments – an
alternative made inexorable by our collective
irresponsibility and denial.
Racing Down
Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
“It is clear that modern medicine has created a serious
dilemma … In the past, there were many children who
never survived – they succumbed to various diseases …
But in a sense modern medicine has put natural selection
out of commission. Something that has helped one
individual over a serious illness can in the long run
contribute to weakening the resistance of the whole
human race to certain diseases. If we pay absolutely no
attention to what is called hereditary hygiene, we could
find ourselves facing a degeneration of the human race.
Mankind’s hereditary potential for resisting serious
disease will be weakened.”
(Jostein Gaarder in “Sophie’s World”, a bestselling
philosophy textbook for adolescents published in Oslo,
Norway, in 1991 and, afterwards, throughout the world,
having been translated to dozens of languages)
The Nazis regarded the murder of the feeble-minded and
the mentally insane – intended to purify the race and
maintain hereditary hygiene – as a form of euthanasia.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
German doctors were enthusiastic proponents of an
eugenics movements rooted in 19th century social
Darwinism. Luke Gormally writes, in his essay “Walton,
Davies, and Boyd” (published in “Euthanasia Examined –
Ethical, Clinical, and Legal Perspectives”, ed. John
Keown, Cambridge University Press, 1995):
“When the jurist Karl Binding and the psychiatrist Alfred
Hoche published their tract The Permission to Destroy
Life that is Not Worth Living in 1920 … their motive was
to rid society of the ‘human ballast and enormous
economic burden’ of care for the mentally ill, the
handicapped, retarded and deformed children, and the
incurably ill. But the reason they invoked to justify the
killing of human beings who fell into these categories was
that the lives of such human beings were ‘not worth
living’, were ‘devoid of value'”
It is this association with the hideous Nazi regime that
gave eugenics – a term coined by a relative of Charles
Darwin, Sir Francis Galton, in 1883 – its bad name.
Richard Lynn, of the University of Ulster of North
Ireland, thinks that this recoil resulted in “Dysgenics – the
genetic deterioration of modern (human) population”, as
the title of his controversial tome puts it.
The crux of the argument for eugenics is that a host of
technological, cultural, and social developments conspired
to give rise to negative selection of the weakest, least
intelligent, sickest, the habitually criminal, the sexually
deviant, the mentally-ill, and the least adapted.
Contraception is more widely used by the affluent and the
well-educated than by the destitute and dull. Birth control
as practiced in places like China distorted both the sex
distribution in the cities – and increased the weight of the
rural population (rural couples in China are allowed to
have two children rather than the urban one).
Modern medicine and the welfare state collaborate in
sustaining alive individuals – mainly the mentally
retarded, the mentally ill, the sick, and the genetically
defective – who would otherwise have been culled by
natural selection to the betterment of the entire species.
Eugenics may be based on a literal understanding of
Darwin’s metaphor.
The 2002 edition of the Encyclopedia Britannica has this
to say:
“Darwin’s description of the process of natural selection as
the survival of the fittest in the struggle for life is a
metaphor. “Struggle” does not necessarily mean
contention, strife, or combat; “survival” does not mean
that ravages of death are needed to make the selection
effective; and “fittest” is virtually never a single optimal
genotype but rather an array of genotypes that collectively
enhance population survival rather than extinction. All
these considerations are most apposite to consideration of
natural selection in humans. Decreasing infant and
childhood mortality rates do not necessarily mean that
natural selection in the human species no longer operates.
Theoretically, natural selection could be very effective if
all the children born reached maturity.
http://www.britannica.com/
Two conditions are needed to make this theoretical
possibility realized: first, variation in the number of
children per family and, second, variation correlated with
the genetic properties of the parents. Neither of these
conditions is farfetched.”
The eugenics debate is only the visible extremity of the
Man vs. Nature conundrum. Have we truly conquered
nature and extracted ourselves from its determinism?
Have we graduated from natural to cultural evolution,
from natural to artificial selection, and from genes to
memes?
Does the evolutionary process culminate in a being that
transcends its genetic baggage, that programs and charts
its future, and that allows its weakest and sickest to
survive? Supplanting the imperative of the survival of the
fittest with a culturally-sensitive principle may be the
hallmark of a successful evolution, rather than the
beginning of an inexorable decline.
The eugenics movement turns this argument on its head.
They accept the premise that the contribution of natural
selection to the makeup of future human generations is
glacial and negligible. But they reject the conclusion that,
having ridden ourselves of its tyranny, we can now let the
weak and sick among us survive and multiply. Rather,
they propose to replace natural selection with eugenics.
But who, by which authority, and according to what
guidelines will administer this man-made culling and
decide who is to live and who is to die, who is to breed
and who may not? Why select by intelligence and not by
courtesy or altruism or church-going – or al of them
together? It is here that eugenics fails miserably.
Should the criterion be physical, like in ancient Sparta?
Should it be mental? Should IQ determine one’s fate – or
social status or wealth? Different answers yield disparate
eugenic programs and target dissimilar groups in the
population.
Aren’t eugenic criteria liable to be unduly influenced by
fashion and cultural bias? Can we agree on a universal
eugenic agenda in a world as ethnically and culturally
diverse as ours? If we do get it wrong – and the chances
are overwhelming – will we not damage our gene pool
irreparably and, with it, the future of our species?
And even if many will avoid a slippery slope leading from
eugenics to active extermination of “inferior” groups in
the general population – can we guarantee that everyone
will? How to prevent eugenics from being appropriated by
an intrusive, authoritarian, or even murderous state?
Modern eugenicists distance themselves from the crude
methods adopted at the beginning of the last century by 29
countries, including Germany, The United States, Canada,
Switzerland, Austria, Venezuela, Estonia, Argentina,
Norway, Denmark, Sweden (until 1976), Brazil, Italy,
Greece, and Spain.
They talk about free contraceptives for low-IQ women,
vasectomies or tubal ligations for criminals, sperm banks
with contributions from high achievers, and incentives for
college students to procreate. Modern genetic engineering
and biotechnology are readily applicable to eugenic
projects. Cloning can serve to preserve the genes of the
fittest. Embryo selection and prenatal diagnosis of
genetically diseased embryos can reduce the number of
the unfit.
But even these innocuous variants of eugenics fly in the
face of liberalism. Inequality, claim the proponents of
hereditary amelioration, is genetic, not environmental. All
men are created unequal and as much subject to the
natural laws of heredity as are cows and bees. Inferior
people give birth to inferior offspring and, thus, propagate
their inferiority.
Even if this were true – which is at best debatable – the
question is whether the inferior specimen of our species
possess the inalienable right to reproduce? If society is to
bear the costs of over-population – social welfare, medical
care, daycare centers – then society has the right to
regulate procreation. But does it have the right to act
discriminately in doing so?
Another dilemma is whether we have the moral right – let
alone the necessary knowledge – to interfere with natural
as well as social and demographic trends. Eugenicists
counter that contraception and indiscriminate medicine
already do just that. Yet, studies show that the more
affluent and educated a population becomes – the less
fecund it is. Birth rates throughout the world have
dropped dramatically already.
Instead of culling the great unwashed and the unworthy –
wouldn’t it be a better idea to educate them (or their off-
spring) and provide them with economic opportunities
(euthenics rather than eugenics)? Human populations
seem to self-regulate. A gentle and persistent nudge in the
right direction – of increased affluence and better
schooling – might achieve more than a hundred eugenic
programs, voluntary or compulsory.
That eugenics presents itself not merely as a biological-
social agenda, but as a panacea, ought to arouse suspicion.
The typical eugenics text reads more like a catechism than
a reasoned argument. Previous all-encompassing and
omnicompetent plans tended to end traumatically –
especially when they contrasted a human elite with a
dispensable underclass of persons.
Above all, eugenics is about human hubris. To presume to
know better than the lottery of life is haughty. Modern
medicine largely obviates the need for eugenics in that it
allows even genetically defective people to lead pretty
normal lives. Of course, Man himself – being part of
Nature – may be regarded as nothing more than an agent
of natural selection. Still, many of the arguments
advanced in favor of eugenics can be turned against it
with embarrassing ease.
Consider sick children. True, they are a burden to society
and a probable menace to the gene pool of the species.
But they also inhibit further reproduction in their family
by consuming the financial and mental resources of the
parents. Their genes – however flawed – contribute to
genetic diversity. Even a badly mutated phenotype
sometimes yields precious scientific knowledge and an
interesting genotype.
The implicit Weltbild of eugenics is static – but the real
world is dynamic. There is no such thing as a “correct”
genetic makeup towards which we must all strive. A
combination of genes may be perfectly adaptable to one
environment – but woefully inadequate in another. It is
therefore prudent to encourage genetic diversity or
polymorphism.
The more rapidly the world changes, the greater the value
of mutations of all sorts. One never knows whether
today’s maladaptation will not prove to be tomorrow’s
winner. Ecosystems are invariably comprised of niches
and different genes – even mutated ones – may fit different
niches.
In the 18th century most peppered moths in Britain were
silvery gray, indistinguishable from lichen-covered trunks
of silver birches – their habitat. Darker moths were
gobbled up by rapacious birds. Their mutated genes
proved to be lethal. As soot from sprouting factories
blackened these trunks – the very same genes, hitherto
fatal, became an unmitigated blessing. The blacker
specimen survived while their hitherto perfectly adapted
fairer brethren perished (“industrial melanism”). This
mode of natural selection is called directional.
Moreover, “bad” genes are often connected to “desirable
genes” (pleitropy). Sickle cell anemia protects certain
African tribes against malaria. This is called “diversifying
or disruptive natural selection”. Artificial selection can
thus fast deteriorate into adverse selection due to
ignorance.
Modern eugenics relies on statistics. It is no longer
concerned with causes – but with phenomena and the
likely effects of intervention. If the adverse traits of off-
spring and parents are strongly correlated – then
preventing parents with certain undesirable qualities from
multiplying will surely reduce the incidence of said
dispositions in the general population. Yet, correlation
does not necessarily imply causation. The manipulation of
one parameter of the correlation does not inevitably alter
it – or the incidence of the outcome.
Eugenicists often hark back to wisdom garnered by
generations of breeders and farmers. But the unequivocal
lesson of thousands of years of artificial selection is that
cross-breeding (hybridization) – even of two lines of
inferior genetic stock – yields valuable genotypes. Inter-
marriage between races, groups in the population, ethnic
groups, and clans is thus bound to improve the species’
chances of survival more than any eugenic scheme.
The Myth of the Right to Life
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
I. The Right to Life
Generations of malleable Israeli children are brought up
on the story of the misnamed Jewish settlement Tel-Hai
(“Mount of Life”), Israel’s Alamo. There, among the
picturesque valleys of the Galilee, a one-armed hero
named Joseph Trumpeldor is said to have died, eight
decades ago, from an Arab stray bullet, mumbling: “It is
good to die for our country.” Judaism is dubbed “A
Teaching of Life” – but it would seem that the sanctity of
life can and does take a back seat to some overriding
values.
The right to life – at least of human beings – is a rarely
questioned fundamental moral principle. In Western
cultures, it is assumed to be inalienable and indivisible
(i.e., monolithic). Yet, it is neither. Even if we accept the
axiomatic – and therefore arbitrary – source of this right,
we are still faced with intractable dilemmas. All said, the
right to life may be nothing more than a cultural construct,
dependent on social mores, historical contexts, and
exegetic systems.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
Rights – whether moral or legal – impose obligations or
duties on third parties towards the right-holder. One has a
right AGAINST other people and thus can prescribe to
them certain obligatory behaviors and proscribe certain
acts or omissions. Rights and duties are two sides of the
same Janus-like ethical coin.
This duality confuses people. They often erroneously
identify rights with their attendant duties or obligations,
with the morally decent, or even with the morally
permissible. One’s rights inform other people how they
MUST behave towards one – not how they SHOULD or
OUGHT to act morally. Moral behavior is not dependent
on the existence of a right. Obligations are.
To complicate matters further, many apparently simple
and straightforward rights are amalgams of more basic
moral or legal principles. To treat such rights as unities is
to mistreat them.
Take the right to life. It is a compendium of no less than
eight distinct rights: the right to be brought to life, the
right to be born, the right to have one’s life maintained,
the right not to be killed, the right to have one’s life
saved, the right to save one’s life (wrongly reduced to the
right to self-defense), the right to terminate one’s life, and
the right to have one’s life terminated.
None of these rights is self-evident, or unambiguous, or
universal, or immutable, or automatically applicable. It is
safe to say, therefore, that these rights are not primary as
hitherto believed – but derivative.
The Right to be Brought to Life
In most moral systems – including all major religions and
Western legal methodologies – it is life that gives rise to
rights. The dead have rights only because of the existence
of the living. Where there is no life – there are no rights.
Stones have no rights (though many animists would find
this statement abhorrent).
Hence the vitriolic debate about cloning which involves
denuding an unfertilized egg of its nucleus. Is there life in
an egg or a sperm cell?
That something exists, does not necessarily imply that it
harbors life. Sand exists and it is inanimate. But what
about things that exist and have the potential to develop
life?
No one disputes the existence of eggs and sperms –
or their capacity to grow alive.
Is the potential to be alive a legitimate source of rights?
Does the egg have any rights, or, at the very least, the
right to be brought to life (the right to become or to be)
and thus to acquire rights? The much trumpeted right to
acquire life pertains to an entity which exists but is not
alive – an egg. It is, therefore, an unprecedented kind of
right. Had such a right existed, it would have implied an
obligation or duty to give life to the unborn and the not
yet conceived.
Clearly, life manifests, at the earliest, when an egg and a
sperm unite at the moment of fertilization. Life is not a
potential – it is a process triggered by an event. An
unfertilized egg is neither a process – nor an event. It does
not even possess the potential to become alive unless and
until it is fertilized.
The potential to become alive is not the ontological
equivalent of actually being alive. A potential life cannot
give rise to rights and obligations. The transition from
potential to being is not trivial, nor is it automatic, or
inevitable, or independent of context. Atoms of various
elements have the potential to become an egg (or, for that
matter, a human being) – yet no one would claim that they
ARE an egg (or a human being), or that they should be
treated as such (i.e., with the same rights
and obligations).
The Right to be Born
While the right to be brought to life deals with potentials –
the right to be born deals with actualities. When one or
two adults voluntarily cause an egg to be fertilized by a
sperm cell with the explicit intent and purpose of creating
another life – the right to be born crystallizes. The
voluntary and premeditated action of said adults amounts
to a contract with the embryo – or rather, with society
which stands in for the embryo.
Henceforth, the embryo acquires the entire panoply of
human rights: the right to be born, to be fed, sheltered, to
be emotionally nurtured, to get an education, and so on.
But what if the fertilization was either involuntary (rape)
or unintentional (“accidental” pregnancy)?
Is the embryo’s successful acquisition of rights dependent
upon the nature of the conception? We deny criminals
their loot as “fruits of the poisoned tree”. Why not deny an
embryo his life if it is the outcome of a crime?
The conventional response – that the embryo did not
commit the crime or conspire in it – is inadequate. We
would deny the poisoned fruits of crime to innocent
bystanders as well. Would we allow a passerby to freely
spend cash thrown out of an escape vehicle following a
robbery?
Even if we agree that the embryo has a right to be kept
alive – this right cannot be held against his violated
mother. It cannot oblige her to harbor this patently
unwanted embryo. If it could survive outside the womb,
this would have solved the moral dilemma. But it is
dubious – to say the least – that it has a right to go on
using the mother’s body, or resources, or to burden her in
any way in order to sustain its own life.
The Right to Have One’s Life Maintained
This leads to a more general quandary. To what extent can
one use other people’s bodies, their property, their time,
their resources and to deprive them of pleasure, comfort,
material possessions, income, or any other thing – in order
to maintain one’s life?
Even if it were possible in reality, it is indefensible to
maintain that I have a right to sustain, improve, or prolong
my life at another’s expense. I cannot demand – though I
can morally expect – even a trivial and minimal sacrifice
from another in order to prolong my life. I have no right to
do so.
Of course, the existence of an implicit, let alone explicit,
contract between myself and another party would change
the picture. The right to demand sacrifices commensurate
with the provisions of the contract would then crystallize
and create corresponding duties and obligations.
No embryo has a right to sustain its life, maintain, or
prolong it at its mother’s expense. This is true regardless
of how insignificant the sacrifice required of her is.
Yet, by knowingly and intentionally conceiving the
embryo, the mother can be said to have signed a contract
with it. The contract causes the right of the embryo to
demand such sacrifices from his mother to crystallize. It
also creates corresponding duties and obligations of the
mother towards her embryo.
We often find ourselves in a situation where we do not
have a given right against other individuals – but we do
possess this very same right against society. Society owes
us what no constituent-individual does.
Thus, we all have a right to sustain our lives, maintain,
prolong, or even improve them at society’s expense – no
matter how major and significant the resources required.
Public hospitals, state pension schemes, and police forces
may be needed in order to fulfill society’s obligations to
prolong, maintain, and improve our lives – but fulfill them
it must.
Still, each one of us can sign a contract with society –
implicitly or explicitly – and abrogate this right. One can
volunteer to join the army. Such an act constitutes a
contract in which the individual assumes the duty or
obligation to give up his or her life.
The Right not to be Killed
It is commonly agreed that every person has the right not
to be killed unjustly. Admittedly, what is just and what is
unjust is determined by an ethical calculus or a social
contract – both constantly in flux.
Still, even if we assume an Archimedean immutable point
of moral reference – does A’s right not to be killed mean
that third parties are to refrain from enforcing the rights of
other people against A? What if the only way to right
wrongs committed by A against others – was to kill A?
The moral obligation to right wrongs is about restoring the
rights of the wronged.
If the continued existence of A is predicated on the
repeated and continuous violation of the rights of others –
and these other people object to it – then A must be killed
if that is the only way to right the wrong and re-assert the
rights of A’s victims.
The Right to have One’s Life Saved
There is no such right because there is no moral obligation
or duty to save a life. That people believe otherwise
demonstrates the muddle between the morally
commendable, desirable, and decent (“ought”, “should”)
and the morally obligatory, the result of other people’s
rights (“must”). In some countries, the obligation to save a
life is codified in the law of the land. But legal rights and
obligations do not always correspond to moral rights and
obligations, or give rise to them.
The Right to Save One’s Own Life
One has a right to save one’s life by exercising self-
defense or otherwise, by taking certain actions or by
avoiding them. Judaism – as well as other religious, moral,
and legal systems – accept that one has the right to kill a
pursuer who knowingly and intentionally is bent on taking
one’s life. Hunting down Osama bin-Laden in the wilds of
Afghanistan is, therefore, morally acceptable (though not
morally mandatory).
But does one have the right to kill an innocent person who
unknowingly and unintentionally threatens to take one’s
life? An embryo sometimes threatens the life of the
mother. Does she have a right to take its life? What about
an unwitting carrier of the Ebola virus – do we have a
right to terminate her life? For that matter, do we have a
right to terminate her life even if there is nothing she
could have done about it had she known about her
condition?
The Right to Terminate One’s Life
There are many ways to terminate one’s life: self sacrifice,
avoidable martyrdom, engaging in life risking activities,
refusal to prolong one’s life through medical treatment,
euthanasia, overdosing and self inflicted death that is the
result of coercion. Like suicide, in all these – bar the last –
a foreknowledge of the risk of death is present coupled
with its acceptance. Does one have a right to take one’s
life?
The answer is: it depends. Certain cultures and societies
encourage suicide. Both Japanese kamikaze and Jewish
martyrs were extolled for their suicidal actions. Certain
professions are knowingly life-threatening – soldiers,
firemen, policemen. Certain industries – like the
manufacture of armaments, cigarettes, and alcohol – boost
overall mortality rates.
In general, suicide is commended when it serves social
ends, enhances the cohesion of the group, upholds its
values, multiplies its wealth, or defends it from external
and internal threats. Social structures and human
collectives – empires, countries, firms, bands, institutions –
often commit suicide. This is considered to be a healthy
process.
Thus, suicide came to be perceived as a social act. The
flip-side of this perception is that life is communal
property. Society has appropriated the right to foster
suicide or to prevent it. It condemns individual suicidal
entrepreneurship. Suicide, according to Thomas Aquinas,
is unnatural. It harms the community and violates God’s
property rights.
In Judeo-Christian tradition, God is the owner of all souls.
The soul is on deposit with us. The very right to use it, for
however short a period, is a divine gift. Suicide, therefore,
amounts to an abuse of God’s possession. Blackstone, the
venerable codifier of British Law, concurred. The state,
according to him, has a right to prevent and to punish
suicide and attempted suicide. Suicide is self-murder, he
wrote, and, therefore, a grave felony. In certain
paternalistic countries, this still is the case.
The Right to Have One’s Life Terminated
The right to have one’s life terminated at will (euthanasia),
is subject to social, ethical, and legal strictures. In some
countries – such as the Netherlands – it is legal (and
socially acceptable) to have one’s life terminated with the
help of third parties given a sufficient deterioration in the
quality of life and given the imminence of death. One has
to be of sound mind and will one’s death knowingly,
intentionally, repeatedly, and forcefully.
II. Issues in the Calculus of
Rights
The Hierarchy of Rights
The right to life supersedes – in Western moral and legal
systems – all other rights. It overrules the right to one’s
body, to comfort, to the avoidance of pain, or to
ownership of property. Given such lack of equivocation,
the amount of dilemmas and controversies surrounding
the right to life is, therefore, surprising.
When there is a clash between equally potent rights – for
instance, the conflicting rights to life of two people – we
can decide among them randomly (by flipping a coin, or
casting dice). Alternatively, we can add and subtract
rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic.
Thus, if the continued life of an embryo or a fetus
threatens the mother’s life – that is, assuming,
controversially, that both of them have an equal right to
life – we can decide to kill the fetus. By adding to the
mother’s right to life her right to her own body we
outweigh the fetus’ right to life.
The Difference between Killing and Letting Die
Counterintuitively, there is a moral gulf between killing
(taking a life) and letting die (not saving a life). The right
not to be killed is undisputed. There is no right to have
one’s own life saved. Where there is a right – and only
where there is one – there is an obligation. Thus, while
there is an obligation not to kill – there is no obligation to
save a life.
Killing the Innocent
The life of a Victim (V) is sometimes threatened by the
continued existence of an innocent person (IP), a person
who cannot be held guilty of V’s ultimate death even
though he caused it. IP is not guilty of dispatching V
because he hasn’t intended to kill V, nor was he aware that
V will die due to his actions or continued existence.
Again, it boils down to ghastly arithmetic. We definitely
should kill IP to prevent V’s death if IP is going to die
anyway – and shortly. The remaining life of V, if saved,
should exceed the remaining life of IP, if not killed. If
these conditions are not met, the rights of IP and V should
be weighted and calculated to yield a decision (See
“Abortion and the Sanctity of Human Life” by Baruch A.
Brody).
Utilitarianism – a form of crass moral calculus – calls for
the maximization of utility (life, happiness, pleasure). The
lives, happiness, or pleasure of the many outweigh the
life, happiness, or pleasure of the few. If by killing IP we
save the lives of two or more people and there is no other
way to save their lives – it is morally permissible.
But surely V has right to self defense, regardless of any
moral calculus of rights? Not so. Taking another’s life to
save one’s own is rarely justified, though such behavior
cannot be condemned. Here we have the flip side of the
confusion we opened with: understandable and perhaps
inevitable behavior (self defense) is mistaken for a moral
right.
If I were V, I would kill IP unhesitatingly. Moreover, I
would have the understanding and sympathy of everyone.
But this does not mean that I had a right to kill IP.
Which brings us to September 11.
Collateral Damage
What should prevail: the imperative to spare the lives of
innocent civilians – or the need to safeguard the lives of
fighter pilots? Precision bombing puts such pilots at great
risk. Avoiding this risk usually results in civilian
casualties (“collateral damage”).
This moral dilemma is often “solved” by applying –
explicitly or implicitly – the principle of “over-riding
affiliation”. We find the two facets of this principle in
Jewish sacred texts: “One is close to oneself” and “Your
city’s poor denizens come first (with regards to charity)”.
Some moral obligations are universal – thou shalt not kill.
They are related to one’s position as a human being. Other
moral values and obligations arise from one’s affiliations.
Yet, there is a hierarchy of moral values and obligations.
The ones related to one’s position as a human being are,
actually, the weakest.
They are overruled by moral values and obligations
related to one’s affiliations. The imperative “thou shalt not
kill (another human being)” is easily over-ruled by the
moral obligation to kill for one’s country. The imperative
“thou shalt not steal” is superseded by one’s moral
obligation to spy for one’s nation.
This leads to another startling conclusion:
There is no such thing as a self-consistent moral system.
Moral values and obligations often contradict each other
and almost always conflict with universal moral values
and obligations.
In the examples above, killing (for one’s country) and
stealing (for one’s nation) are moral obligations. Yet, they
contradict the universal moral value of the sanctity of life
and the universal moral obligation not to kill. Far from
being a fundamental and immutable principle – the right to
life, it would seem, is merely a convenient implement in
the hands of society.
The Argument for Torture
By: Sam Vaknin
Also Read:
The Business of Torture
I. Practical Considerations
The problem of the “ticking bomb” – rediscovered after
September 11 by Alan Dershowitz, a renowned criminal
defense lawyer in the United States – is old hat. Should
physical torture be applied – where psychological strain
has failed – in order to discover the whereabouts of a
ticking bomb and thus prevent a mass slaughter of the
innocent? This apparent ethical dilemma has been
confronted by ethicists and jurists from Great Britain to
Israel.
Nor is Dershowitz’s proposal to have the courts issue
“torture warrants” (Los Angeles Times, November 8,
2001) unprecedented. In a controversial decision in 1996,
the Supreme Court of Israel permitted its internal security
forces to apply “moderate physical pressure” during the
interrogation of suspects.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/brief-torture01.html
It has thus fully embraced the recommendation of the
1987 Landau Commission, presided over by a former
Supreme Court judge. This blanket absolution was
repealed in 1999 when widespread abuses against
Palestinian detainees were unearthed by human rights
organizations.
Indeed, this juridical reversal – in the face of growing
suicidal terrorism – demonstrates how slippery the ethical
slope can be. What started off as permission to apply mild
torture in extreme cases avalanched into an all-pervasive
and pernicious practice. This lesson – that torture is habit-
forming and metastasizes incontrollably throughout the
system – is the most powerful – perhaps the only –
argument against it.
As Harvey Silverglate argued in his rebuttal of
Dershowitz’s aforementioned op-ed piece:
“Institutionalizing torture will give it society‘s
imprimatur, lending it a degree of respectability. It will
then be virtually impossible to curb not only the
increasing frequency with which warrants will be sought
— and granted — but also the inevitable rise in
unauthorized use of torture. Unauthorized torture will
increase not only to extract life-saving information, but
also to obtain confessions (many of which will then prove
false). It will also be used to punish real or imagined
infractions, or for no reason other than human sadism.
This is a genie we should not let out of the bottle.”
Alas, these are weak contentions.
That something has the potential to be widely abused –
and has been and is being widely misused – should not
inevitably lead to its utter, universal, and unconditional
proscription. Guns, cars, knives, and books have always
been put to vile ends. Nowhere did this lead to their
complete interdiction.
Moreover, torture is erroneously perceived by liberals as a
kind of punishment. Suspects – innocent until proven
guilty – indeed should not be subject to penalty. But
torture is merely an interrogation technique. Ethically, it is
no different to any other pre-trial process: shackling,
detention, questioning, or bad press. Inevitably, the very
act of suspecting someone is traumatic and bound to
inflict pain and suffering – psychological, pecuniary, and
physical – on the suspect.
True, torture is bound to yield false confessions and
wrong information, Seneca claimed that it “forces even
the innocent to lie”. St. Augustine expounded on the
moral deplorability of torture
thus:
―If the accused be
innocent, he will undergo for an uncertain crime a certain
punishment, and that not for having committed a crime,
but because it is unknown whether he committed it.”
But the same can be said about other, less corporeal,
methods of interrogation. Moreover, the flip side of ill-
gotten admissions is specious denials of guilt. Criminals
regularly disown their misdeeds and thus evade their
penal consequences. The very threat of torture is bound to
limit this miscarriage of justice. Judges and juries can
always decide what confessions are involuntary and were
extracted under duress.
Thus, if there was a way to ensure that non-lethal torture
is narrowly defined, applied solely to extract time-critical
information in accordance with a strict set of rules and
specifications, determined openly and revised frequently
by an accountable public body; that abusers are severely
punished and instantly removed; that the tortured have
recourse to the judicial system and to medical attention at
any time – then the procedure would have been ethically
justified in rare cases if carried out by the authorities.
This proviso – “if carried out by the authorities” – is
crucial.
The sovereign has rights denied the individual, or any
subset of society. It can judicially kill with impunity. Its
organs – the police, the military – can exercise violence. It
is allowed to conceal information, possess illicit or
dangerous substances, deploy arms, invade one’s bodily
integrity, or confiscate property. To permit the sovereign
to torture while forbidding individuals, or organizations
from doing so would, therefore, not be without precedent,
or inconsistent.
Alan Dershowitz expounds:
“(In the United States) any interrogation technique,
including the use of truth serum or even torture, is not
prohibited. All that is prohibited is the introduction into
evidence of the fruits of such techniques in a criminal trial
against the person on whom the techniques were used. But
the evidence could be used against that suspect in a non-
criminal case – such as a deportation hearing – or against
someone else.”
When the unspeakable horrors of the Nazi concentration
camps were revealed, C.S. Lewis wrote, in quite
desperation:
“What was the sense in saying the enemy were in the
wrong unless Right is a real thing which the Nazis at
bottom knew as well as we did and ought to have
practiced? If they had no notion of what we mean by
Right, then, though we might still have had to fight them,
we could no more have blamed them for that than for the
color of their hair.” (C.S. Lewis, Mere Christianity (New
York: Macmillan, paperback edition, 1952).
But legal torture should never be directed at innocent
civilians based on arbitrary criteria such as their race or
religion. If this principle is observed, torture would not
reflect on the moral standing of the state. Identical acts are
considered morally sound when carried out by the realm –
and condemnable when discharged by individuals.
Consider the denial of freedom. It is lawful incarceration
at the hands of the republic – but kidnapping if effected by
terrorists.
Nor is torture, as “The Economist” misguidedly claims, a
taboo.
According to the 2002 edition of the “Encyclopedia
Britannica”, taboos are “the prohibition of an action or the
use of an object based on ritualistic distinctions of them
either as being sacred and consecrated or as being
dangerous, unclean, and accursed.” Evidently, none of this
applies to torture. On the contrary, torture – as opposed,
for instance, to incest – is a universal, state-sanctioned
behavior.
Amnesty International – who should know better –
professed to have been shocked by the results of their own
surveys:
“In preparing for its third international campaign to stop
torture, Amnesty International conducted a survey of its
research files on 195 countries and territories. The survey
covered the period from the beginning of 1997 to mid-
2000. Information on torture is usually concealed, and
reports of torture are often hard to document, so the
figures almost certainly underestimate its extent. The
statistics are shocking. There were reports of torture or ill-
treatment by state officials in more than 150 countries. In
more than 70, they were widespread or persistent. In more
than 80 countries, people reportedly died as a result.”
Countries and regimes abstain from torture – or, more
often, claim to do so – because such overt abstention is
expedient. It is a form of global political correctness, a
policy choice intended to demonstrate common values and
to extract concessions or benefits from others. Giving up
this efficient weapon in the law enforcement arsenal even
in Damoclean circumstances is often rewarded with
foreign direct investment, military aid, and other forms of
support.
But such ethical magnanimity is a luxury in times of war,
or when faced with a threat to innocent life. Even the
courts of the most liberal societies sanctioned atrocities in
extraordinary circumstances. Here the law conforms both
with common sense and with formal, utilitarian, ethics.
II. Ethical Considerations
Rights – whether moral or legal – impose obligations or
duties on third parties towards the right-holder. One has a
right AGAINST other people and thus can prescribe to
them certain obligatory behaviors and proscribe certain
acts or omissions. Rights and duties are two sides of the
same Janus-like ethical coin.
This duality confuses people. They often erroneously
identify rights with their attendant duties or obligations,
with the morally decent, or even with the morally
permissible. One’s rights inform other people how they
MUST behave towards one – not how they SHOULD, or
OUGHT to act morally. Moral behavior is not dependent
on the existence of a right. Obligations are.
To complicate matters further, many apparently simple
and straightforward rights are amalgams of more basic
moral or legal principles. To treat such rights as unities is
to mistreat them.
Take the right not to be tortured. It is a compendium of
many distinct rights, among them: the right to bodily and
mental integrity, the right to avoid self-incrimination, the
right not to be pained, or killed, the right to save one’s life
(wrongly reduced merely to the right to self-defense), the
right to prolong one’s life (e.g., by receiving medical
attention), and the right not to be forced to lie under
duress.
None of these rights is self-evident, or unambiguous, or
universal, or immutable, or automatically applicable. It is
safe to say, therefore, that these rights are not primary –
but derivative, nonessential, or mere “wants”.
Moreover, the fact that the torturer also has rights whose
violation may justify torture is often overlooked.
Consider these two, for instance:
The Rights of Third Parties against the Tortured
What is just and what is unjust is determined by an ethical
calculus, or a social contract – both in constant flux. Still,
it is commonly agreed that every person has the right not
to be tortured, or killed unjustly.
Yet, even if we find an Archimedean immutable point of
moral reference – does A’s right not to be tortured, let
alone killed, mean that third parties are to refrain from
enforcing the rights of other people against A?
What if the only way to right wrongs committed, or about
to be committed by A against others – was to torture, or
kill A? There is a moral obligation to right wrongs by
restoring, or safeguarding the rights of those wronged, or
about to be wronged by A.
If the defiant silence – or even the mere existence – of A
are predicated on the repeated and continuous violation of
the rights of others (especially their right to live), and if
these people object to such violation – then A must be
tortured, or killed if that is the only way to right the wrong
and re-assert the rights of A’s victims.
This, ironically, is the argument used by liberals to justify
abortion when the fetus (in the role of A) threatens his
mother’s rights to health and life.
The Right to Save One’s Own Life
One has a right to save one’s life by exercising self-
defense or otherwise, by taking certain actions, or by
avoiding them. Judaism – as well as other religious, moral,
and legal systems – accepts that one has the right to kill a
pursuer who knowingly and intentionally is bent on taking
one’s life. Hunting down Osama bin-Laden in the wilds of
Afghanistan is, therefore, morally acceptable (though not
morally mandatory). So is torturing his minions.
When there is a clash between equally potent rights – for
instance, the conflicting rights to life of two people – we
can decide among them randomly (by flipping a coin, or
casting dice). Alternatively, we can add and subtract
rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic. The right to life
definitely prevails over the right to comfort, bodily
integrity, absence of pain and so on. Where life is at stake,
non-lethal torture is justified by any ethical calculus.
Utilitarianism – a form of crass moral calculus – calls for
the maximization of utility (life, happiness, pleasure). The
lives, happiness, or pleasure of the many outweigh the
life, happiness, or pleasure of the few. If by killing or
torturing the few we (a) save the lives of the many (b) the
combined life expectancy of the many is longer than the
combined life expectancy of the few and (c) there is no
other way to save the lives of the many – it is morally
permissible to kill, or torture the few.
III. The Social Treaty
There is no way to enforce certain rights without
infringing on others. The calculus of ethics relies on
implicit and explicit quantitative and qualitative
hierarchies. The rights of the many outweigh certain rights
of the few. Higher-level rights – such as the right to life –
override rights of a lower order.
The rights of individuals are not absolute but “prima
facie”. They are restricted both by the rights of others and
by the common interest. They are inextricably connected
to duties towards other individuals in particular and the
community in general. In other words, though not
dependent on idiosyncratic cultural and social contexts,
they are an integral part of a social covenant.
It can be argued that a suspect has excluded himself from
the social treaty by refusing to uphold the rights of others
– for instance, by declining to collaborate with law
enforcement agencies in forestalling an imminent disaster.
Such inaction amounts to the abrogation of many of one’s
rights (for instance, the right to be free). Why not apply
this abrogation to his or her right not to be tortured?
The Aborted Contract And the Right to Life
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
The issue of abortion is emotionally loaded and this often
makes for poor, not thoroughly thought out
arguments. The questions: “Is abortion immoral” and “Is
abortion a murder” are often confused. The pregnancy
(and the resulting fetus) are discussed in terms normally
reserved to natural catastrophes (force majeure). At times,
the embryo is compared to cancer, a thief, or an invader:
after all, they are both growths, clusters of cells. The
difference, of course, is that no one contracts cancer
willingly (except, to some extent, smokers -–but, then
they gamble, not contract).
When a woman engages in voluntary sex, does not use
contraceptives and gets pregnant – one can say that she
signed a contract with her fetus. A contract entails the
demonstrated existence of a reasonably (and reasonable)
free will. If the fulfillment of the obligations in a contract
between individuals could be life-threatening – it is fair
and safe to assume that no rational free will was involved.
No reasonable person would sign or enter such a contract
with another person (though most people would sign such
contracts with society).
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
Judith Jarvis Thomson argued convincingly (“A Defence
of Abortion”) that pregnancies that are the result of forced
sex (rape being a special case) or which are life
threatening should or could, morally, be terminated. Using
the transactional language: the contract was not entered to
willingly or reasonably and, therefore, is null and
void. Any actions which are intended to terminate it and
to annul its consequences should be legally and morally
permissible.
The same goes for a contract which was entered into
against the express will of one of the parties and despite
all the reasonable measures that the unwilling party
adopted to prevent it. If a mother uses contraceptives in a
manner intended to prevent pregnancy, it is as good as
saying: ” I do not want to sign this contract, I am doing
my reasonable best not to sign it, if it is signed – it is
contrary to my express will”. There is little legal (or
moral) doubt that such a contract should be voided.
Much more serious problems arise when we study the
other party to these implicit agreements: the embryo. To
start with, it lacks consciousness (in the sense that is
needed for signing an enforceable and valid contract). Can
a contract be valid even if one of the “signatories” lacks
this sine qua non trait? In the absence of consciousness,
there is little point in talking about free will (or rights
which depend on sentience). So, is the contract not a
contract at all? Does it not reflect the intentions of the
parties?
The answer is in the negative. The contract between a
mother and her fetus is derived from the larger Social
Contract. Society – through its apparatuses – stands for
the embryo the same way that it represents minors, the
mentally retarded, and the insane. Society steps in – and
has the recognized right and moral obligation to do so –
whenever the powers of the parties to a contract (implicit
or explicit) are not balanced. It protects small citizens
from big monopolies, the physically weak from the thug,
the tiny opposition from the mighty administration, the
barely surviving radio station from the claws of the
devouring state mechanism. It also has the right and
obligation to intervene, intercede and represent the
unconscious: this is why euthanasia is absolutely
forbidden without the consent of the dying person. There
is not much difference between the embryo and the
comatose.
A typical contract states the rights of the parties. It
assumes the existence of parties which are “moral
personhoods” or “morally significant persons” – in other
words, persons who are holders of rights and can demand
from us to respect these rights. Contracts explicitly
elaborate some of these rights and leaves others
unmentioned because of the presumed existence of the
Social Contract. The typical contract assumes that there is
a social contract which applies to the parties to the
contract and which is universally known and, therefore,
implicitly incorporated in every contract. Thus, an explicit
contract can deal with the property rights of a certain
person, while neglecting to mention that person’s rights to
life, to free speech, to the enjoyment the fruits of his
lawful property and, in general to a happy life.
There is little debate that the Mother is a morally
significant person and that she is a rights-holder. All born
humans are and, more so, all adults above a certain age.
But what about the unborn fetus?
One approach is that the embryo has no rights until certain
conditions are met and only upon their fulfillment is he
transformed into a morally significant person (“moral
agent”). Opinions differ as to what are the conditions.
Rationality, or a morally meaningful and valued life are
some of the oft cited criteria. The fallaciousness of this
argument is easy to demonstrate: children are irrational –
is this a licence to commit infanticide?
A second approach says that a person has the right to life
because it desires it.
But then what about chronic depressives who wish to die
– do we have the right to terminate their miserable lives?
The good part of life (and, therefore, the differential and
meaningful test) is in the experience itself – not in the
desire to experience.
Another variant says that a person has the right to life
because once his life is terminated – his experiences
cease. So, how should we judge the right to life of
someone who constantly endures bad experiences (and, as
a result, harbors a death wish)? Should he better be
“terminated”?
Having reviewed the above arguments and counter-
arguments, Don Marquis goes on (in “Why Abortion is
Immoral”, 1989) to offer a sharper and more
comprehensive criterion: terminating a life is morally
wrong because a person has a future filled with value and
meaning, similar to ours.
But the whole debate is unnecessary. There is no conflict
between the rights of the mother and those of her fetus
because there is never a conflict between parties to an
agreement. By signing an agreement, the mother gave up
some of her rights and limited the others. This is normal
practice in contracts: they represent compromises, the
optimization (and not the maximization) of the parties’
rights and wishes. The rights of the fetus are an
inseparable part of the contract which the mother signed
voluntarily and reasonably. They are derived from the
mother’s behaviour. Getting willingly pregnant (or
assuming the risk of getting pregnant by not using
contraceptives reasonably) – is the behaviour which
validates and ratifies a contract between her and the
fetus. Many contracts are by behaviour, rather than by a
signed piece of paper. Numerous contracts are verbal or
behavioural. These contracts, though implicit, are as
binding as any of their written, more explicit,
brethren. Legally (and morally) the situation is crystal
clear: the mother signed some of her rights away in this
contract. Even if she regrets it – she cannot claim her
rights back by annulling the contract unilaterally. No
contract can be annulled this way – the consent of both
parties is required. Many times we realize that we have
entered a bad contract, but there is nothing much that we
can do about it. These are the rules of the game.
Thus the two remaining questions: (a) can this specific
contract (pregnancy) be annulled and, if so (b) in which
circumstances – can be easily settled using modern
contract law. Yes, a contract can be annulled and voided if
signed under duress, involuntarily, by incompetent
persons (e.g., the insane), or if one of the parties made a
reasonable and full scale attempt to prevent its signature,
thus expressing its clear will not to sign the contract. It is
also terminated or voided if it would be unreasonable to
expect one of the parties to see it through. Rape,
contraception failure, life threatening situations are all
such cases.
This could be argued against by saying that, in the case of
economic hardship, f or instance, the damage to the
mother’s future is certain. True, her value- filled,
meaningful future is granted – but so is the detrimental
effect that the fetus will have on it, once born. This
certainty cannot be balanced by the UNCERTAIN value-
filled future life of the embryo. Always, preferring an
uncertain good to a certain evil is morally wrong. But
surely this is a quantitative matter – not a qualitative one.
Certain, limited aspects of the rest of the mother’s life will
be adversely effected (and can be ameliorated by society’s
helping hand and intervention) if she does have the
baby. The decision not to have it is both qualitatively and
qualitatively different. It is to deprive the unborn of all the
aspects of all his future life – in which he might well have
experienced happiness, values, and meaning.
The questions whether the fetus is a Being or a growth of
cells, conscious in any manner, or utterly unconscious,
able to value his life and to want them – are all but
irrelevant. He has the potential to lead a happy,
meaningful, value-filled life, similar to ours, very much as
a one minute old baby does. The contract between him
and his mother is a service provision contract. She
provides him with goods and services that he requires in
order to materialize his potential. It sounds very much like
many other human contracts. And this contract continue
well after pregnancy has ended and birth given.
Consider education: children do not appreciate its
importance or value its potential – still, it is enforced upon
them because we, who are capable of those feats, want
them to have the tools that they will need in order to
develop their potential. In this and many other respects,
the human pregnancy continues well into the fourth year
of life (physiologically it continues in to the second year
of life – see “Born Alien”). Should the location of the
pregnancy (in uterus, in vivo) determine its future? If a
mother has the right to abort at will, why should the
mother be denied her right to terminate the ” pregnancy”
AFTER the fetus emerges and the pregnancy continues
OUTSIDE her womb? Even after birth, the woman’s body
is the main source of food to the baby and, in any case,
she has to endure physical hardship to raise the
child. Why not extend the woman’s ownership of her body
and right to it further in time and space to the post-natal
period?
http://samvak.tripod.com/alien.html
Contracts to provide goods and services (always at a
personal cost to the provider) are the commonest of
contracts. We open a business. We sell a software
application, we publish a book – we engage in helping
others to materialize their potential. We should always do
so willingly and reasonably – otherwise the contracts that
we sign will be null and void. But to deny anyone his
capacity to materialize his potential and the goods and
services that he needs to do so – after a valid contract was
entered into – is
immoral.
To refuse to provide a service or
to condition it provision (Mother: ” I will provide the
goods and services that I agreed to provide to this fetus
under this contract only if and when I benefit from such
provision”) is a violation of the contract and should be
penalized. Admittedly, at times we have a right to choose
to do the immoral (because it has not been codified as
illegal) – but that does not turn it into moral.
Still, not every immoral act involving the termination of
life can be classified as murder. Phenomenology is
deceiving: the acts look the same (cessation of life
functions, the prevention of a future). But murder is the
intentional termination of the life of a human who
possesses, at the moment of death, a consciousness (and,
in most cases, a free will, especially the will not to
die). Abortion is the intentional termination of a life
which has the potential to develop into a person with
consciousness and free will. Philosophically, no identity
can be established between potential and actuality. The
destruction of paints and cloth is not tantamount (not to
say identical) to the destruction of a painting by Van
Gogh, made up of these very elements. Paints and cloth
are converted to a painting through the intermediacy and
agency of the Painter. A cluster of cells a human makes
only through the agency of Nature.
Surely, the destruction of the painting materials
constitutes an offence against the Painter. In the same
way, the destruction of the fetus constitutes an offence
against Nature. But there is no denying that in both cases,
no finished product was eliminated. Naturally, this
becomes less and less so (the severity of the terminating
act increases) as the process of creation advances.
Classifying an abortion as murder poses numerous and
insurmountable philosophical problems.
No one disputes the now common view that the main
crime committed in aborting a pregnancy – is a crime
against potentialities. If so, what is the philosophical
difference between aborting a fetus and destroying a
sperm and an egg? These two contain all the information
(=all the potential) and their destruction is philosophically
no less grave than the destruction of a fetus. The
destruction of an egg and a sperm is even more serious
philosophically: the creation of a fetus limits the set of all
potentials embedded in the genetic material to the one
fetus created. The egg and sperm can be compared to the
famous wave function (state vector) in quantum
mechanics – the represent millions of potential final states
(=millions of potential embryos and lives). The fetus is
the collapse of the wave function: it represents a much
more limited set of potentials. If killing an embryo is
murder because of the elimination of potentials – how
should we consider the intentional elimination of many
more potentials through masturbation and contraception?
The argument that it is difficult to say which sperm cell
will impregnate the egg is not serious. Biologically, it
does not matter – they all carry the same genetic
content. Moreover, would this counter-argument still hold
if, in future, we were be able to identify the chosen one
and eliminate only it? In many religions (Catholicism)
contraception is murder. In Judaism, masturbation is “the
corruption of the seed” and such a serious offence that it is
punishable by the strongest religious penalty: eternal ex-
communication (“Karet”).
If abortion is indeed murder how should we resolve the
following moral dilemmas and questions (some of them
patently absurd):
Is a natural abortion the equivalent of manslaughter
(through negligence)?
Do habits like smoking, drug addiction, vegetarianism –
infringe upon the right to life of the embryo? Do they
constitute a violation of the contract?
Reductio ad absurdum: if, in the far future, research will
unequivocally prove that listening to a certain kind of
music or entertaining certain thoughts seriously hampers
the embryonic development – should we apply censorship
to the Mother?
Should force majeure clauses be introduced to the
Mother-Embryo pregnancy contract? Will they give the
mother the right to cancel the contract? Will the embryo
have a right to terminate the contract? Should the
asymmetry persist: the Mother will have no right to
terminate – but the embryo will, or vice versa?
Being a rights holder, can the embryo (=the State) litigate
against his Mother or Third Parties (the doctor that
aborted him, someone who hit his mother and brought
about a natural abortion) even after he died?
Should anyone who knows about an abortion be
considered an accomplice to murder?
If abortion is murder – why punish it so mildly? Why is
there a debate regarding this question? “Thou shalt not
kill” is a natural law, it appears in virtually every legal
system. It is easily and immediately identifiable. The fact
that abortion does not “enjoy” the same legal and moral
treatment says a lot.
In Our Own Image
The Debate about Cloning
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
There are two types of cloning. One involves harvesting
stem cells from embryos (“therapeutic cloning”). These
are the biological equivalent of a template. They can
develop into any kind of mature functional cell and thus
help cure many degenerative and auto-immune diseases.
The other kind of cloning is much derided in popular
culture – and elsewhere – as the harbinger of a Brave, New
World. A nucleus from any cell of a donor is embedded in
an egg whose own nucleus has been removed. The egg is
then implanted in a woman’s womb and a cloned baby is
born nine months later. Biologically, the cloned infant is a
replica of the donor.
Cloning is often confused with other advances in bio-
medicine and bio-engineering – such as genetic selection.
It cannot – in itself – be used to produce “perfect humans”
or select sex or other traits. Hence, some of the arguments
against cloning are either specious or fuelled by
ignorance.
It is true, though, that cloning, used in conjunction with
other bio-technologies, raises serious bio-ethical
questions.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
Scare scenarios of humans cultivated in sinister labs as
sources of spare body parts, “designer babies”, “master
races”, or “genetic sex slaves” – formerly the preserve of B
sci-fi movies – have invaded mainstream discourse.
Still, cloning touches upon Mankind’s most basic fears
and hopes. It invokes the most intractable ethical and
moral dilemmas. As an inevitable result, the debate is
often more passionate than informed.
Right to Life Arguments
According to cloning’s detractors, the nucleus removed
from the egg could otherwise have developed into a
human being. Thus, removing the nucleus amounts to
murder.
It is a fundamental principle of most moral theories that
all human beings have a right to life. The existence of a
right implies obligations or duties of third parties towards
the right-holder. One has a right AGAINST other people.
The fact that one possesses a certain right – prescribes to
others certain obligatory behaviours and proscribes certain
acts or omissions. This Janus-like nature of rights and
duties as two sides of the same ethical coin – creates great
confusion. People often and easily confuse rights and their
attendant duties or obligations with the morally decent, or
even with the morally permissible. What one MUST do as
a result of another’s right – should never be confused with
one SHOULD or OUGHT to do morally (in the absence
of a right).
But is the egg – alive?
This question is NOT equivalent to the ancient quandary
of “when does life begin”. Life crystallizes, at the earliest,
when an egg and a sperm unite (i.e., at the moment of
fertilization). Life is not a potential – it is a process
triggered by an event. An unfertilized egg is neither a
process – nor an event. It does not even possess the
potential to become alive unless and until it merges with a
sperm. Should such merger not occur – it will never
develop life.
The potential to become X is not the ontological
equivalent of actually being X, nor does it spawn moral
and ethical rights and obligations pertaining to X. The
transition from potential to being is not trivial, nor is it
automatic, or inevitable, or independent of context. Atoms
of various elements have the potential to become an egg
(or, for that matter, a human being) – yet no one would
claim that they ARE an egg (or a human being), or that
they should be treated as one (i.e., with the same rights
and obligations).
Moreover, it is the donor nucleus embedded in the egg
that endows it with life – the life of the cloned baby. Yet,
the nucleus is usually extracted from a muscle or the skin.
Should we treat a muscle or a skin cell with the same
reverence the critics of cloning wish to accord an
unfertilized egg?
Is this the main concern?
The main concern is that cloning – even the therapeutic
kind – will produce piles of embryos. Many of them –
close to 95% with current biotechnology – will die. Others
can be surreptitiously and illegally implanted in the
wombs of “surrogate mothers”.
It is patently immoral, goes the precautionary argument,
to kill so many embryos. Cloning is such a novel
technique that its success rate is still unacceptably low.
There are alternative ways to harvest stem cells – less
costly in terms of human life. If we accept that life begins
at the moment of fertilization, this argument is valid. But
it also implies that – once cloning becomes safer and
scientists more adept – cloning itself should be permitted.
This is anathema to those who fear a slippery slope. They
abhor the very notion of “unnatural” conception. To them,
cloning is a narcissistic act and an ignorant and dangerous
interference in nature’s sagacious ways. They would ban
procreative cloning, regardless of how safe it is.
Therapeutic cloning – with its mounds of discarded fetuses
– will allow rogue scientists to cross the boundary between
permissible (curative cloning) and illegal (baby cloning).
Why should Baby Cloning be Illegal?
Cloning’s opponents object to procreative cloning because
it can be abused to design babies, skew natural selection,
unbalance nature, produce masters and slaves and so on.
The “argument from abuse” has been raised with every
scientific advance – from in vitro fertilization to space
travel.
http://samvak.tripod.com/npdglance.html
Every technology can be potentially abused. Television
can be either a wonderful educational tool – or an
addictive and mind numbing pastime. Nuclear fission is a
process that yields both nuclear weapons and atomic
energy. To claim, as many do, that cloning touches upon
the “heart” of our existence, the “kernel” of our being, the
very “essence” of our nature – and thus threatens life itself
– would be incorrect.
There is no “privileged” form of technological abuse and
no hierarchy of potentially abusive technologies. Nuclear
fission tackles natural processes as fundamental as life.
Nuclear weapons threaten life no less than cloning. The
potential for abuse is not a sufficient reason to arrest
scientific research and progress – though it is a necessary
condition.
Some fear that cloning will further the government’s
enmeshment in the healthcare system and in scientific
research. Power corrupts and it is not inconceivable that
governments will ultimately abuse and misuse cloning and
other biotechnologies. Nazi Germany had a state-
sponsored and state-mandated eugenics program in the
1930’s.
Yet, this is another variant of the argument from abuse.
That a technology can be abused by governments does not
imply that it should be avoided or remain undeveloped.
This is because all technologies – without a single
exception – can and are abused routinely – by governments
and others. This is human nature.
Fukuyama raised the possibility of a multi-tiered
humanity in which “natural” and “genetically modified”
people enjoy different rights and privileges. But why is
this inevitable? Surely this can easily by tackled by
proper, prophylactic, legislation?
All humans, regardless of their pre-natal history, should
be treated equally. Are children currently conceived in
vitro treated any differently to children conceived in
utero? They
are not.
There is no reason that cloned or
genetically-modified children should belong to distinct
legal classes.
Unbalancing Nature
It is very anthropocentric to argue that the proliferation of
genetically enhanced or genetically selected children will
somehow unbalance nature and destabilize the precarious
equilibrium it maintains. After all, humans have been
modifying, enhancing, and eliminating hundreds of
thousands of species for well over 10,000 years now.
Genetic modification and bio-engineering are as natural as
agriculture. Human beings are a part of nature and its
manifestation. By definition, everything they do is natural.
Why would the genetic alteration or enhancement of one
more species – homo sapiens – be of any consequence? In
what way are humans “more important” to nature, or
“more crucial” to its proper functioning? In our short
history on this planet, we have genetically modified and
enhanced wheat and rice, dogs and cows, tulips and
orchids, oranges and potatoes. Why would interfering
with the genetic legacy of the human species be any
different?
Effects on Society
Cloning – like the Internet, the television, the car,
electricity, the telegraph, and the wheel before it – is
bound to have great social consequences. It may foster
“embryo industries”. It may lead to the exploitation of
women – either willingly (“egg prostitution”) or
unwillingly (“womb slavery”). Charles Krauthammer, a
columnist and psychiatrist, quoted in “The Economist”,
says:
“(Cloning) means the routinisation, the
commercialisation, the commodification of the human
embryo”.
Exploiting anyone unwillingly is a crime, whether it
involves cloning or white slavery. But why would egg
donations and surrogate motherhood be considered
problems? If we accept that life begins at the moment of
fertilization and that a woman owns her body and
everything within it – why should she not be allowed to
sell her eggs or to host another’s baby and how would
these voluntary acts be morally repugnant? In any case,
human eggs are already being bought and sold and the
supply far exceeds the demand.
Moreover, full-fledged humans are routinely “routinised,
commercialized, and commodified” by governments,
corporations, religions, and other social institutions.
Consider war, for instance – or commercial advertising.
How is the “routinisation, commercialization, and
commodification” of embryos more reprehensible that the
“routinisation, commercialization, and commodification”
of fully formed human beings?
Curing and Saving Life
Cell therapy based on stem cells often leads to tissue
rejection and necessitates costly and potentially dangerous
immunosuppressive therapy. But when the stem cells are
harvested from the patient himself and cloned, these
problems are averted. Therapeutic cloning has vast
untapped – though at this stage still remote – potential to
improve the lives of hundreds of millions.
As far as “designer babies” go, pre-natal cloning and
genetic engineering can be used to prevent disease or cure
it, to suppress unwanted traits, and to enhance desired
ones. It is the moral right of a parent to make sure that his
progeny suffers less, enjoys life more, and attains the
maximal level of welfare throughout his or her life.
That such technologies can be abused by over-zealous, or
mentally unhealthy parents in collaboration with
avaricious or unscrupulous doctors – should not prevent
the vast majority of stable, caring, and sane parents from
gaining access to them.
Ethical Relativism and Absolute Taboos
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
I. Taboos
II. Incest
III. Suicide
IV. Race
V. Moral Relativism
I. Taboos
Taboos regulate our sexual conduct, race relations,
political institutions, and economic mechanisms – virtually
every realm of our life. According to the 2002 edition of
the “Encyclopedia Britannica”, they are “the prohibition
of an action or the use of an object based on ritualistic
distinctions of them either as being sacred and
consecrated or as being dangerous, unclean, and
accursed.”
Jews are instructed to ritually cleanse themselves after
having been in contact with a Torah scroll – or a corpse.
This association of the sacred with the accursed and the
holy with the depraved is the key to the guilt and sense of
danger which accompany the violation of a taboo.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#taboo
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#incest
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#suicide
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#race
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#relativism
In Polynesia, where the term originated, “taboos could
include prohibitions on fishing or picking fruit at certain
seasons; food taboos that restrict the diet of pregnant
women; prohibitions on talking to or touching chiefs or
members of other high social classes; taboos on walking
or traveling in certain areas, such as forests; and various
taboos that function during important life events such as
birth, marriage, and death.”
Political correctness is a particularly pernicious kind of
taboo enforcement. It entails an all-pervasive self-
censorship coupled with social sanctions. Consider the
treatment of the right to life, incest, suicide, and race.
II. Incest
In contemporary thought, incest is invariably associated
with child abuse and its horrific, long-lasting, and often
irreversible consequences. But incest is far from being the
clear-cut or monolithic issue that millennia of taboo
imply. Incest with minors is a private – and particularly
egregious – case of pedophilia or statutory rape. It should
be dealt with forcefully. But incest covers much more
besides these criminal
acts.
Incest is the ethical and legal prohibition to have sex with
a related person or to marry him or her – even if the people
involved are consenting and fully informed adults.
Contrary to popular mythology, banning incest has little to
do with the fear of genetic diseases. Even genetically
unrelated parties (a stepfather and a stepdaughter) can
commit incest.
http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#incest
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#suicide
../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#race
Incest is also forbidden between fictive kin or
classificatory kin (that belong to the same matriline or
patriline). In certain societies (certain Native American
tribes, or the Chinese) it is sufficient to carry the same
family name (i.e., to belong to the same clan) to render a
relationship incestuous. Clearly, eugenic considerations
have little to do with incest.
Moreover, the use of contraceptives means that incest
does not need to result in pregnancy and the transmission
of genetic material. Inbreeding (endogamous) or
straightforward incest is the norm in many life forms,
even among primates (e.g., chimpanzees). It was also
quite common until recently in certain human societies –
the Hindus, for instance, or many Native American tribes,
and royal families everywhere.
Nor is the taboo universal. In some societies, incest is
mandatory or prohibited, according to one’s social class
(Bali). In others, the Royal House started a tradition of
incestuous marriages, later emulated by the lower classes
(Ancient Egypt). The list is long and it serves to
demonstrate the diversity of attitudes towards this most
universal practice.
The more primitive and aggressive the society, the more
strict and elaborate the set of incest prohibitions and the
fiercer the penalties for their violation. The reason may be
economic. Incest interferes with rigid algorithms of
inheritance in conditions of extreme scarcity (for instance,
of land and water) and consequently leads to survival-
threatening internecine disputes.
Freud said that incest provokes horror because it touches
upon our forbidden, ambivalent sexual cravings and
aggression towards members of our close family.
Westermark held that “familiarity breeds repulsion” and
that the incest taboo – rather than counter inbred instincts –
simply reflects emotional reality. Both ignored the fact
that the incest taboo is learned – not inherent.
We can easily imagine a society where incest is extolled,
taught, and practiced – and out-breeding is regarded with
horror and revulsion. The incestuous marriages among
members of the royal households of Europe were intended
to preserve the familial property and expand the clan’s
territory. They were normative, not aberrant. Marrying an
outsider was considered abhorrent.
III. Suicide
Self-sacrifice, avoidable martyrdom, engaging in life
risking activities, refusal to prolong one’s life through
medical treatment, euthanasia, overdosing, and self-
destruction that is the result of coercion – are all closely
related to suicide. They all involve a deliberately self-
inflicted death.
But while suicide is chiefly intended to terminate a life –
the other acts are aimed at perpetuating, strengthening,
and defending values or other people. Many are appalled
by the choice implied in suicide – of death over life. They
feel that it demeans life – i.e., abnegates its meaning.
Life’s meaning – the outcome of active selection by the
individual – is either external (i.e., God’s plan) or internal
(i.e., the outcome of an arbitrary frame of reference).
Our life is rendered meaningful only by integrating into an
eternal thing, process, design, or being. Suicide makes life
trivial because the act is not natural – not part of the
eternal framework, the undying process, the timeless cycle
of birth and death. Suicide is a break with eternity.
Sidgwick said that only conscious (i.e., intelligent) beings
can appreciate values and meanings. So, life is significant
to conscious, intelligent, though finite, beings – because it
is a part of some eternal goal, plan, process, thing, design,
or being. Suicide flies in the face of Sidgwick’s dictum. It
is a statement by an intelligent and conscious being about
the meaninglessness of life.
If suicide is a statement, than society, in this case, is
against the freedom of expression. In the case of suicide,
free speech dissonantly clashes with the sanctity of a
meaningful life. To rid itself of the anxiety brought on by
this conflict, society cast suicide as a depraved or even
criminal act and its perpetrators are much castigated.
The suicide violates not only the social contract – but,
many will add, covenants with God or nature. Thomas
Aquinas said that – since organisms strive to survive –
suicide is an unnatural act. Moreover, it adversely affects
the community and violates the property rights of God,
the imputed owner of one’s spirit. Christianity regards the
immortal soul as a gift and, in Jewish writings, it is a
deposit. Suicide amounts to the abuse or misuse of God’s
possessions, temporarily lodged in a corporeal mansion.
This paternalism was propagated, centuries later, by
Blackstone, the codifier of British Law. Suicide – being
self-murder – is a grave felony, which the state has a right
to prevent and to punish for.
In certain countries this still is the case. In Israel, for
instance, a soldier is considered to be “military property”
and an attempted suicide is severely punished as “a
corruption of a army chattel”.
Paternalism, a malignant mutation of benevolence, is
about objectifying people and treating them as
possessions. Even fully-informed and consenting adults
are not granted full, unmitigated autonomy, freedom, and
privacy. This tends to breed “victimless crimes”. The
“culprits” – gamblers, homosexuals, communists, suicides,
drug addicts, alcoholics, prostitutes – are “protected from
themselves” by an intrusive nanny state.
The possession of a right creates a corresponding
obligation not to act to frustrate its exercise. Suicide is
often the choice of a mentally and legally competent
adult. Life is such a basic and deep set phenomenon that
even the incompetents – the mentally retarded or mentally
insane or minors – can fully gauge its significance and
make “informed” decisions, in my view.
The paternalists claim counterfactually that no competent
adult “in his right mind” will ever decide to commit
suicide. They cite the cases of suicides who survived and
felt very happy that they have – as a compelling reason to
intervene. But we all make irreversible decisions for
which, sometimes, we are sorry. It gives no one the right
to interfere.
Paternalism is a slippery slope. Should the state be
allowed to prevent the birth of a genetically defective
child or forbid his parents to marry in the first place?
Should unhealthy adults be forced to abstain from
smoking, or steer clear from alcohol? Should they be
coerced to exercise?
Suicide is subject to a double moral standard. People are
permitted – nay, encouraged – to sacrifice their life only in
certain, socially sanctioned, ways. To die on the
battlefield or in defense of one’s religion is commendable.
This hypocrisy reveals how power structures – the state,
institutional religion, political parties, national movements
– aim to monopolize the lives of citizens and adherents to
do with as they see fit. Suicide threatens this monopoly.
Hence the taboo.
IV. Race
Social Darwinism, sociobiology, and, nowadays,
evolutionary psychology are all derided and disparaged
because they try to prove that nature – more specifically,
our genes – determine our traits, our accomplishments, our
behavior patterns, our social status, and, in many ways,
our destiny. Our upbringing and our environment change
little. They simply select from ingrained libraries
embedded in our brain.
Moreover, the discussion of race and race relations is
tainted by a history of recurrent ethnocide and genocide
and thwarted by the dogma of egalitarianism. The
(legitimate) question “are all races equal” thus becomes a
private case of the (no less legitimate) “are all men equal”.
To ask “can races co-exist peacefully” is thus to embark
on the slippery slope to slavery and Auschwitz. These
historical echoes and the overweening imposition of
political correctness prevent any meaningful – let alone
scientific – discourse.
The irony is that “race” – or at least race as determined by
skin color – is a distinctly unscientific concept, concerned
more with appearances (i.e., the color of one’s skin, the
shape of one’s head or hair), common history, and social
politics – than with heredity. Most human classificatory
traits are not concordant. Different taxonomic criteria
conjure up different “races”. IQ is a similarly contentious
construct, although it is stable and does predict academic
achievement effectively.
Thus, racist-sounding claims are as unfounded as claims
about racial equality. Still, while the former are treated as
an abomination – the latter are accorded academic
respectability and scientific scrutiny.
Consider these two hypotheses:
I. That the IQ (or any other measurable trait) of a given
race or ethnic group is hereditarily determined (i.e., that
skin color and IQ – or another measurable trait – are
concordant) and is strongly correlated with certain types
of behavior, life accomplishments, and social status.
II. That the IQ (or any other quantifiable trait) of a given
race or “ethnic group” is the outcome of social and
economic circumstances and even if strongly correlated
with behavior patterns, academic or other achievements,
and social status – which is disputable – is amenable to
“social engineering”.
Both theories are falsifiable and both deserve serious,
unbiased, study. That we choose to ignore the first and
substantiate the second demonstrates the pernicious and
corrupting effect of political correctness.
Claims of the type “trait A and trait B are concordant”
should be investigated by scientists, regardless of how
politically incorrect they are. Not so claims of the type
“people with trait A are …” or “people with trait A do …”.
These should be decried as racist tripe.
Thus the statement “The traits of being an Ashkenazi Jew
(A) and suffering from Tay-Sachs induced idiocy (B) are
concordant” is true 1 of every 2500 times.
The statements “people who are Jews (i.e., with trait A)
are (narcissists)”, or “people who are Jews (i.e., with trait
A) do this: they drink the blood of innocent Christian
children during the Passover rites” – are vile racist and
paranoid statements.
People are not created equal. Human diversity – a taboo
topic – is a cause for celebration. It is important to study
and ascertain what are the respective contributions of
nature and nurture to the way people – individuals and
groups – grow, develop, and mature. In the pursuit of this
invaluable and essential knowledge, taboos are
dangerously counter-productive.
V. Moral Relativism
Protagoras, the Greek Sophist, was the first to notice that
ethical codes are culture-dependent and vary in different
societies, economies, and geographies. The pragmatist
believe that what is right is merely what society thinks is
right at any given moment. Good and evil are not
immutable. No moral principle – and taboos are moral
principles – is universally and eternally true and valid.
Morality applies within cultures but not across them.
But ethical or cultural relativism and the various schools
of pragmatism ignore the fact that certain ethical percepts
– probably grounded in human nature – do appear to be
universal and ancient, if not eternal. Fairness, veracity,
keeping promises, moral hierarchy – permeate all the
cultures we have come to know. Nor can certain moral
tenets be explained away as mere expressions of emotions
or behavioral prescriptions – devoid of cognitive content,
logic, and a relatedness to certain facts.
Still, it is easy to prove that most taboos are, indeed,
relative. Incest, suicide, feticide, infanticide, parricide,
ethnocide, genocide, genital mutilation, social castes, and
adultery are normative in certain cultures – and strictly
proscribed in others. Taboos are pragmatic moral
principles. They derive their validity from their efficacy.
They are observed because they work, because they yield
solutions and provide results. They disappear or are
transformed when no longer useful.
Incest is likely to be tolerated in a world with limited
possibilities for procreation. Suicide is bound to be
encouraged in a society suffering from extreme scarcity of
resources and over-population. Ethnocentrism, racism and
xenophobia will inevitably rear their ugly heads again in
anomic circumstances. None of these taboos is
unassailable.
None of them reflects some objective truth, independent
of culture and circumstances. They are convenient
conventions, workable principles, and regulatory
mechanisms – nothing more. That scholars are frantically
trying to convince us otherwise – or to exclude such a
discussion altogether – is a sign of the growing
disintegration of our weakening society.
The Merits of Stereotypes
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also Read:
The Science of Superstitions
The trouble with people is not that they don’t know but
that they know so much that ain’t so.
— Henry Wheeler Shaw
Do stereotypes usefully represent real knowledge or
merely reflect counter-productive prejudice?
Stereotypes invariably refer in a generalized manner to –
often arbitrary – groups of people, usually minorities.
Stereotypes need not necessarily be derogatory or
cautionary, though most of them are. The “noble savage”
and the “wild savage” are both stereotypes. Indians in
movies, note Ralph and Natasha Friar in their work titled
“The Only Good Indian – The Hollywood Gospel” (1972)
are overwhelmingly drunken, treacherous, unreliable, and
childlike. Still, some of them are as portrayed as
unrealistically “good”.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/supers.html
But alcoholism among Native Americans – especially
those crammed into reservations – is, indeed, more
prevalent than among the general population. The
stereotype conveys true and useful information about
inebriation among Indians. Could its other descriptors be
equally accurate?
It is hard to unambiguously define, let alone quantify,
traits. At which point does self-centerdness become
egotism or the pursuit of self-interest – treachery? What
precisely constitutes childlike behavior? Some types of
research cannot even be attempted due to the stifling
censorship of political correctness. Endeavoring to answer
a simple question like: “Do blacks in America really
possess lower IQ’s and, if so, is this deficiency
hereditary?” has landed many an American academic
beyond the pale.
The two most castigated aspects of stereotypes are their
generality and their prejudice. Implied in both criticisms is
a lack of veracity and rigor of stereotypes. Yet, there is
nothing wrong with generalizations per se. Science is
constructed on such abstractions from private case to
general rule. In historiography we discuss “the Romans”
or “ancient Greeks” and characterize them as a group.
“Nazi Germany”, “Communist Russia”, and
“Revolutionary France” are all forms of groupspeak.
In an essay titled “Helping Students Understand
Stereotyping” and published in the April 2001 issue of
“Education Digest”, Carlos Cortes suggest three
differences between “group generalizations” and
“stereotypes”:
“Group generalizations are flexible and permeable to new,
countervailing, knowledge – ideas, interpretations, and
information that challenge or undermine current beliefs.
Stereotypes are rigid and resistant to change even in the
face of compelling new evidence.
Second, group generalizations incorporate intragroup
heterogeneity while stereotypes foster intragroup
homogeneity. Group generalizations embrace diversity –
“there are many kinds of Jews, tall and short, mean and
generous, clever and stupid, black and white, rich and
poor”. Stereotypes cast certain individuals as exceptions
or deviants – “though you are Jewish, you don’t behave as
a Jew would, you are different”.
Finally, while generalizations provide mere clues about
group culture and behavior – stereotypes purport to proffer
immutable rules applicable to all the members of the
group. “Stereotypes develop easily, rigidify
surreptitiously, and operate reflexively, providing simple,
comfortable, convenient bases for making personal sense
of the world. Because generalizations require greater
attention, content flexibility, and nuance in application,
they do not provide a stereotype’s security blanket of
permanent, inviolate, all-encompassing, perfectly reliable
group knowledge.”
It is commonly believed that stereotypes form the core of
racism, sexism, homophobia, and other forms of
xenophobia. Stereotypes, goes the refrain, determine the
content and thrust of prejudices and propel their advocates
to take action against minorities. There is a direct lineage,
it is commonly held, between typecasting and lynching.
It is also claimed that pigeonholing reduces the quality of
life, lowers the expectations, and curbs the
accomplishments of its victims. The glass ceiling and the
brass ceiling are pernicious phenomena engendered by
stereotypes. The fate of many social policy issues – such
as affirmative action, immigration quotas, police profiling,
and gay service in the military – is determined by
stereotypes rather than through informed opinion.
USA Today Magazine reported the findings of a survey of
1000 girls in grades three to twelve conducted by Harris
Interactive for “Girls”. Roughly half the respondents
thought that boys and girls have the same abilities –
compared to less than one third of boys. A small majority
of the girls felt that “people think we are only interested in
love and romance”.
Somewhat less than two thirds of the girls were told not to
brag about things they do well and were expected to spend
the bulk of their time on housework and taking care of
younger children. Stereotypical thinking had a practical
effect: girls who believe that they are as able as boys and
face the same opportunities are way more likely to plan to
go to college.
But do boys and girls have the same abilities? Absolutely
not. Boys are better at spatial orientation and math. Girls
are better at emotions and relationships. And do girls face
the same opportunities as boys? It would be perplexing if
they did, taking into account physiological, cognitive,
emotional, and reproductive disparities – not to mention
historical and cultural handicaps. It boils down to this
politically incorrect statement: girls are not boys and
never will be.
Still, there is a long stretch from “girls are not boys” to
“girls are inferior to boys” and thence to “girls should be
discriminated against or confined”. Much separates
stereotypes and generalizations from discriminatory
practice.
Discrimination prevails against races, genders, religions,
people with alternative lifestyles or sexual preferences,
ethnic groups, the poor, the rich, professionals, and any
other conceivable minority. It has little to do with
stereotypes and a lot to do with societal and economic
power matrices. Granted, most racists typecast blacks and
Indians, Jews and Latinos. But typecasting in itself does
not amount to racism, nor does it inevitably lead to
discriminatory conduct.
In a multi-annual study titled “Economic Insecurity,
Prejudicial Stereotypes, and Public Opinion on
Immigration Policy”, published by the Political Science
Quarterly, the authors Peter Burns and James Gimpel
substantiated the hypothesis that “economic self-interest
and symbolic prejudice have often been treated as rival
explanations for attitudes on a wide variety of issues, but
it is plausible that they are complementary on an issue
such as immigration. This would be the case if prejudice
were caused, at least partly, by economic insecurity.”
A long list of scholarly papers demonstrate how racism –
especially among the dispossessed, dislocated, and low-
skilled – surges during times of economic hardship or
social transition. Often there is a confluence of long-
established racial and ethnic stereotypes with a growing
sense of economic insecurity and social dislocation.
“Social Identity Theory” tells us that stereotypical
prejudice is a form of compensatory narcissism. The acts
of berating, demeaning, denigrating, and debasing others
serve to enhance the perpetrators’ self-esteem and regulate
their labile sense of self-worth. It is vicarious “pride by
proxy” – belonging to an “elite” group bestows superiority
on all its members. Not surprisingly, education has some
positive influence on racist attitudes and political
ideology.
Having been entangled – sometimes unjustly – with
bigotry and intolerance, the merits of stereotypes have
often been overlooked.
In an age of information overload, “nutshell” stereotypes
encapsulate information compactly and efficiently and
thus possess an undeniable survival value. Admittedly,
many stereotypes are self-reinforcing, self-fulfilling
prophecies. A young black man confronted by a white
supremacist may well respond violently and an Hispanic,
unable to find a job, may end up is a street gang.
But this recursiveness does not detract from the usefulness
of stereotypes as “reality tests” and serviceable
prognosticators. Blacks do commit crimes over and above
their proportion in the general population. Though
stereotypical in the extreme, it is a useful fact to know and
act upon. Hence racial profiling.
Stereotypes – like fables – are often constructed around
middle class morality and are prescriptive. They split the
world into the irredeemably bad – the other, blacks, Jews,
http://samvak.tripod.com/14.html
Hispanics, women, gay – and the flawlessly good, we, the
purveyors of the stereotype. While expressly unrealistic,
the stereotype teaches “what not to be” and “how not to
behave”. A by-product of this primitive rendition is
segregation.
A large body of scholarship shows that proximity and
familiarity actually polarize rather than ameliorate inter-
ethnic and inter-racial tensions. Stereotypes minimize
friction and violence by keeping minorities and the
majority apart. Venting and vaunting substitute for
vandalizing and worse. In time, as erstwhile minorities are
gradually assimilated and new ones emerge, conflict is
averted.
Moreover, though they frequently reflect underlying
deleterious emotions – such as rage or envy – not all
stereotypes are negative. Blacks are supposed to have
superior musical and athletic skills. Jews are thought to be
brainier in science and shrewder in business. Hispanics
uphold family values and ethnic cohesion. Gays are
sensitive and compassionate. And negative stereotypes are
attached even to positive social roles – athletes are dumb
and violent, soldiers inflexible and programmed.
Stereotypes are selective filters. Supporting data is
hoarded and information to the contrary is ignored. One
way to shape stereotypes into effective coping strategies is
to bombard their devotees with “exceptions”, contexts,
and alternative reasoning.
Blacks are good athletes because sports is one of the few
egalitarian career paths open to them. Jews, historically
excluded from all professions, crowded into science and
business and specialized. If gays are indeed more sensitive
or caring than the average perhaps it is because they have
been repressed and persecuted for so long. Athletes are
not prone to violence – violent athletes simply end up on
TV more often. And soldiers have to act reflexively to
survive in battle.
There is nothing wrong with stereotypes if they are
embedded in reality and promote the understanding of
social and historical processes. Western, multi-ethnic,
pluralistic civilization celebrates diversity and the
uniqueness and distinctiveness of its components.
Stereotypes merely acknowledge this variety.
USA Today Magazine reported in January a survey of 800
adults, conducted last year by social psychology
professors Amanda Diekman of Purdue University and
Alice Eagly of Northwestern University. They found that
far from being rigid and biased, stereotypes regarding the
personality traits of men and women have changed
dramatically to accurately reflect evolving gender roles.
Diekman noted that “women are perceived as having
become much more assertive, independent, and
competitive over the years … Our respondents – whether
they were old enough to have witnessed it or not –
recognized the role change that occurred when women
began working outside the home in large numbers and the
necessity of adopting characteristics that equip them to be
breadwinners.”
The Happiness of Others
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Is there any necessary connection between our actions and
the happiness of others? Disregarding for a moment the
murkiness of the definitions of “actions” in philosophical
literature – two types of answers were hitherto provided.
Sentient Beings (referred to, in this essay, as “Humans” or
“persons”) seem either to limit each other – or to enhance
each other’s actions. Mutual limitation is, for instance,
evident in game theory. It deals with decision outcomes
when all the rational “players” are fully aware of both the
outcomes of their actions and of what they prefer these
outcomes to be. They are also fully informed about the
other players: they know that they are rational, too, for
instance. This, of course, is a very farfetched idealization.
A state of unbounded information is nowhere and never to
be found. Still, in most cases, the players settle down to
one of the Nash equilibria solutions. Their actions are
constrained by the existence of the others.
The “Hidden Hand” of Adam Smith (which, among other
things, benignly and optimally regulates the market and
the price mechanisms) – is also a “mutually limiting”
model. Numerous single participants strive to maximize
their (economic and financial) outcomes – and end up
merely optimizing them.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
The reason lies in the existence of others within the
“market”. Again, they are constrained by other people‘s
motivations, priorities ands, above all, actions.
All the consequentialist theories of ethics deal with
mutual enhancement. This is especially true of the
Utilitarian variety. Acts (whether judged individually or in
conformity to a set of rules) are moral, if their outcome
increases utility (also known as happiness or pleasure).
They are morally obligatory if they maximize utility and
no alternative course of action can do so. Other versions
talk about an “increase” in utility rather than its
maximization. Still, the principle is simple: for an act to
be judged “moral, ethical, virtuous, or good” – it must
influence others in a way which will “enhance” and
increase their happiness.
The flaws in all the above answers are evident and have
been explored at length in the literature. The assumptions
are dubious (fully informed participants, rationality in
decision making and in prioritizing the outcomes, etc.).
All the answers are instrumental and quantitative: they
strive to offer a moral measuring rod. An “increase”
entails the measurement of two states: before and after the
act. Moreover, it demands full knowledge of the world
and a type of knowledge so intimate, so private – that it is
not even sure that the players themselves have conscious
access to it. Who goes around equipped with an
exhaustive list of his priorities and another list of all the
possible outcomes of all the acts that he may commit?
But there is another, basic flaw: these answers are
descriptive, observational, phenomenological in the
restrictive sense of these words. The motives, the drives,
the urges, the whole psychological landscape behind the
act are deemed irrelevant. The only thing relevant is the
increase in utility/happiness. If the latter is achieved – the
former might as well not have existed. A computer, which
increases happiness is morally equivalent to a person who
achieves a quantitatively similar effect. Even worse: two
persons acting out of different motives (one malicious and
one benevolent) will be judged to be morally equivalent if
their acts were to increase happiness similarly.
But, in life, an increase in utility or happiness or pleasure
is CONDITIONED upon, is the RESULT of the motives
behind the acts that led to it. Put differently: the utility
functions of two acts depend decisively on the motivation,
drive, or urge behind them. The process, which leads to
the act is an inseparable part of the act and of its
outcomes, including the outcomes in terms of the
subsequent increase in utility or happiness. We can safely
distinguish the “utility contaminated” act from the “utility
pure (or ideal)” act.
If a person does something which is supposed to increase
the overall utility – but does so in order to increase his
own utility more than the expected average utility increase
– the resulting increase will be lower. The maximum
utility increase is achieved overall when the actor forgoes
all increase in his personal utility. It seems that there is a
constant of utility increase and a conservation law
pertaining to it.
So that a disproportionate increase in one’s personal utility
translates into a decrease in the overall average utility. It
is not a zero sum game because of the infiniteness of the
potential increase – but the rules of distribution of the
utility added after the act, seem to dictate an averaging of
the increase in order to maximize the result.
The same pitfalls await these observations as did the
previous ones. The players must be in the possession of
full information at least regarding the motivation of the
other players. “Why is he doing this?” and “why did he do
what he did?” are not questions confined to the criminal
courts. We all want to understand the “why’s” of actions
long before we engage in utilitarian calculations of
increased utility. This also seems to be the source of many
an emotional reaction concerning human actions. We are
envious because we think that the utility increase was
unevenly divided (when adjusted for efforts invested and
for the prevailing cultural mores). We suspect outcomes
that are “too good to be true”. Actually, this very sentence
proves my point: that even if something produces an
increase in overall happiness it will be considered morally
dubious if the motivation behind it remains unclear or
seems to be irrational or culturally deviant.
Two types of information are, therefore, always needed:
one (discussed above) concerns the motives of the main
protagonists, the act-ors. The second type relates to the
world. Full knowledge about the world is also a necessity:
the causal chains (actions lead to outcomes), what
increases the overall utility or happiness and for whom,
etc.
To assume that all the participants in an interaction
possess this tremendous amount of information is an
idealization (used also in modern theories of economy),
should be regarded as such and not be confused with
reality in which people approximate, estimate, extrapolate
and evaluate based on a much more limited knowledge.
Two examples come to mind:
Aristotle described the “Great Soul”. It is a virtuous agent
(actor, player) that judges himself to be possessed of a
great soul (in a self-referential evaluative disposition). He
has the right measure of his worth and he courts the
appreciation of his peers (but not of his inferiors) which
he believes that he deserves by virtue of being virtuous.
He has a dignity of demeanour, which is also very self-
conscious. He is, in short, magnanimous (for instance, he
forgives his enemies their offences). He seems to be the
classical case of a happiness-increasing agent – but he is
not. And the reason that he fails in qualifying as such is
that his motives are suspect. Does he refrain from
assaulting his enemies because of charity and generosity
of spirit – or because it is likely to dent his pomposity? It
is sufficient that a POSSIBLE different motive exist – to
ruin the utilitarian outcome.
Adam Smith, on the other hand, adopted the spectator
theory of his teacher Francis Hutcheson. The morally
good is a euphemism. It is really the name provided to the
pleasure, which a spectator derives from seeing a virtue in
action. Smith added that the reason for this emotion is the
similarity between the virtue observed in the agent and the
virtue possessed by the observer.
It is of a moral nature because of the object involved: the
agent tries to consciously conform to standards of
behaviour which will not harm the innocent, while,
simultaneously benefiting himself, his family and his
friends. This, in turn, will benefit society as a whole. Such
a person is likely to be grateful to his benefactors and
sustain the chain of virtue by reciprocating. The chain of
good will, thus, endlessly multiply.
Even here, we see that the question of motive and
psychology is of utmost importance. WHY is the agent
doing what he is doing? Does he really conform to
society’s standards INTERNALLY? Is he GRATEFUL to
his benefactors? Does he WISH to benefit his friends?
These are all questions answerable only in the realm of
the mind. Really, they are not answerable at all.
The Egotistic Friend
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
What are friends for and how can a friendship be tested?
By behaving altruistically, would be the most common
answer and by sacrificing one’s interests in favour of one’s
friends. Friendship implies the converse of egoism, both
psychologically and ethically. But then we say that the
dog is “man’s best friend”. After all, it is characterized by
unconditional love, by unselfish behaviour, by sacrifice,
when necessary. Isn’t this the epitome of friendship?
Apparently not. On the one hand, the dog’s friendship
seems to be unaffected by long term calculations of
personal benefit. But that is not to say that it is not
affected by calculations of a short-term nature. The
owner, after all, looks after the dog and is the source of its
subsistence and security. People – and dogs – have been
known to have sacrificed their lives for less. The dog is
selfish – it clings and protects what it regards to be its
territory and its property (including – and especially so –
the owner). Thus, the first condition, seemingly not
satisfied by canine attachment is that it be reasonably
unselfish.
There are, however, more important conditions:
a. For a real friendship to exist – at least one of the
friends must be a conscious and intelligent entity,
possessed of mental states. It can be an individual,
or a collective of individuals, but in both cases this
requirement will similarly apply.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
b. There must be a minimal level of identical mental
states between the terms of the equation of
friendship. A human being cannot be friends with
a tree (at least not in the fullest sense of the word).
c. The behaviour must not be deterministic, lest it be
interpreted as instinct driven. A conscious choice
must be involved. This is a very surprising
conclusion: the more “reliable”, the more
“predictable” – the less appreciated. Someone who
reacts identically to similar situations, without
dedicating a first, let alone a second thought to it –
his acts would be depreciated as “automatic
responses”.
For a pattern of behaviour to be described as “friendship”,
these four conditions must be met: diminished egoism,
conscious and intelligent agents, identical mental states
(allowing for the communication of the friendship) and
non-deterministic behaviour, the result of constant
decision making.
A friendship can be – and often is – tested in view of these
criteria. There is a paradox underlying the very notion of
testing a friendship. A real friend would never test his
friend’s commitment and allegiance. Anyone who puts his
friend to a test (deliberately) would hardly qualify as a
friend himself. But circumstances can put ALL the
members of a friendship, all the individuals (two or more)
in the “collective” to a test of friendship. Financial
hardship encountered by someone would surely oblige his
friends to assist him – even if he himself did not take the
initiative and explicitly asked them to do so. It is life that
tests the resilience and strength and depth of true
friendships – not the friends themselves.
In all the discussions of egoism versus altruism –
confusion between self-interest and self-welfare prevails.
A person may be urged on to act by his self-interest,
which might be detrimental to his (long-term) self-
welfare. Some behaviours and actions can satisfy short-
term desires, urges, wishes (in short: self-interest) – and
yet be self- destructive or otherwise adversely effect the
individual’s future welfare. (Psychological) Egoism
should, therefore, be re-defined as the active pursuit of
self- welfare, not of self-interest. Only when the person
caters, in a balanced manner, to both his present (self-
interest) and his future (self-welfare) interests – can we
call him an egoist. Otherwise, if he caters only to his
immediate self-interest, seeks to fulfil his desires and
disregards the future costs of his behaviour – he is an
animal, not an egoist.
Joseph Butler separated the main (motivating) desire from
the desire that is self- interest. The latter cannot exist
without the former. A person is hungry and this is his
desire. His self-interest is, therefore, to eat. But the hunger
is directed at eating – not at fulfilling self-interests. Thus,
hunger generates self-interest (to eat) but its object is
eating. Self-interest is a second order desire that aims to
satisfy first order desires (which can also motivate us
directly).
This subtle distinction can be applied to disinterested
behaviours, acts, which seem to lack a clear self-interest
or even a first order desire. Consider why do people
contribute to humanitarian causes? There is no self-
interest here, even if we account for the global picture
(with every possible future event in the life of the
contributor).
No rich American is likely to find himself starving in
Somalia, the target of one such humanitarian aid mission.
But even here the Butler model can be validated. The first
order desire of the donator is to avoid anxiety feelings
generated by a cognitive dissonance. In the process of
socialization we are all exposed to altruistic messages.
They are internalized by us (some even to the extent of
forming part of the almighty superego, the conscience). In
parallel, we assimilate the punishment inflicted upon
members of society who are not “social” enough,
unwilling to contribute beyond that which is required to
satisfy their self interest, selfish or egoistic, non-
conformist, “too” individualistic, “too” idiosyncratic or
eccentric, etc. Completely not being altruistic is “bad” and
as such calls for “punishment”. This no longer is an
outside judgement, on a case by case basis, with the
penalty inflicted by an external moral authority. This
comes from the inside: the opprobrium and reproach, the
guilt, the punishment (read Kafka). Such impending
punishment generates anxiety whenever the person judges
himself not to have been altruistically “sufficient”. It is to
avoid this anxiety or to quell it that a person engages in
altruistic acts, the result of his social conditioning. To use
the Butler scheme: the first-degree desire is to avoid the
agonies of cognitive dissonance and the resulting anxiety.
This can be achieved by committing acts of altruism. The
second-degree desire is the self-interest to commit
altruistic acts in order to satisfy the first-degree desire. No
one engages in contributing to the poor because he wants
them to be less poor or in famine relief because he does
not want others to starve. People do these apparently
selfless activities because they do not want to experience
that tormenting inner voice and to suffer the acute anxiety,
which accompanies it.
Altruism is the name that we give to successful
indoctrination. The stronger the process of socialization,
the stricter the education, the more severely brought up
the individual, the grimmer and more constraining his
superego – the more of an altruist he is likely to be.
Independent people who really feel comfortable with their
selves are less likely to exhibit these behaviours.
This is the self-interest of society: altruism enhances the
overall level of welfare. It redistributes resources more
equitably, it tackles market failures more or less
efficiently (progressive tax systems are altruistic), it
reduces social pressures and stabilizes both individuals
and society. Clearly, the self-interest of society is to make
its members limit the pursuit of their own self-interest?
There are many opinions and theories. They can be
grouped into:
a. Those who see an inverse relation between the
two: the more satisfied the self interests of the
individuals comprising a society – the worse off
that society will end up. What is meant by “better
off” is a different issue but at least the
commonsense, intuitive, meaning is clear and begs
no explanation. Many religions and strands of
moral absolutism espouse this view.
b. Those who believe that the more satisfied the self-
interests of the individuals comprising a society –
the better off this society will end up. These are
the “hidden hand” theories. Individuals, which
strive merely to maximize their utility, their
happiness, their returns (profits) – find themselves
inadvertently engaged in a colossal endeavour to
better their society.
This is mostly achieved through the dual mechanisms
of market and price. Adam Smith is an example (and
other schools of the dismal science).
c. Those who believe that a delicate balance must
exist between the two types of self-interest: the
private and the public. While most individuals will
be unable to obtain the full satisfaction of their
self-interest – it is still conceivable that they will
attain most of it. On the other hand, society must
not fully tread on individuals’ rights to self-
fulfilment, wealth accumulation and the pursuit of
happiness. So, it must accept less than maximum
satisfaction of its self-interest. The optimal mix
exists and is, probably, of the minimax type. This
is not a zero sum game and society and the
individuals comprising it can maximize their worst
outcomes.
The French have a saying: “Good bookkeeping – makes
for a good friendship”. Self-interest, altruism and the
interest of society at large are not necessarily
incompatible.
The Distributive Justice of the Market
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also published by United Press International (UPI)
Also Read
The Principal-Agent Conundrum
The Green-Eyed Capitalist
The Misconception of Scarcity
The public outcry against executive pay and compensation
followed disclosures of insider trading, double dealing,
and outright fraud. But even honest and productive
entrepreneurs often earn more money in one year than
Albert Einstein did in his entire life. This strikes many –
especially academics – as unfair. Surely Einstein’s
contributions to human knowledge and welfare far exceed
anything ever accomplished by sundry businessmen?
Fortunately, this discrepancy is cause for constructive
jealousy, emulation, and imitation. It can, however, lead
to an orgy of destructive and self-ruinous envy.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://www.upi.com/view.cfm?StoryID=20020814-111702-4527r
http://samvak.tripod.com/pp165.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/pp168.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/scarcity.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/pp167.html
Entrepreneurs recombine natural and human resources in
novel ways. They do so to respond to forecasts of future
needs, or to observations of failures and shortcomings of
current products or services. Entrepreneurs are
professional – though usually intuitive – futurologists. This
is a valuable service and it is financed by systematic risk
takers, such as venture capitalists. Surely they all deserve
compensation for their efforts and the hazards they
assume?
Exclusive ownership is the most ancient type of such
remuneration. First movers, entrepreneurs, risk takers,
owners of the wealth they generated, exploiters of
resources – are allowed to exclude others from owning or
exploiting the same things. Mineral concessions, patents,
copyright, trademarks – are all forms of monopoly
ownership. What moral right to exclude others is gained
from being the first?
Nozick advanced Locke’s Proviso. An exclusive
ownership of property is just only if “enough and as good
is left in common for others”. If it does not worsen other
people’s lot, exclusivity is morally permissible. It can be
argued, though, that all modes of exclusive ownership
aggravate other people’s situation. As far as everyone, bar
the entrepreneur, are concerned, exclusivity also prevents
a more advantageous distribution of income and wealth.
Exclusive ownership reflects real-life irreversibility. A
first mover has the advantage of excess information and of
irreversibly invested work, time, and effort. Economic
enterprise is subject to information asymmetry: we know
nothing about the future and everything about the past.
This asymmetry is known as “investment risk”. Society
compensates the entrepreneur with one type of asymmetry
– exclusive ownership – for assuming another, the
investment risk.
One way of looking at it is that all others are worse off by
the amount of profits and rents accruing to owner-
entrepreneurs. Profits and rents reflect an intrinsic
inefficiency. Another is to recall that ownership is the
result of adding value to the world. It is only reasonable to
expect it to yield to the entrepreneur at least this value
added now and in the future.
In a “Theory of Justice” (published 1971, p. 302), John
Rawls described an ideal society thus:
“(1) Each person is to have an equal right to the most
extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible
with a similar system of liberty for all. (2) Social and
economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are
both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged,
consistent with the just savings principle, and (b) attached
to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair
equality of opportunity. ”
It all harks back to scarcity of resources – land, money,
raw materials, manpower, creative brains. Those who can
afford to do so, hoard resources to offset anxiety
regarding future uncertainty. Others wallow in paucity.
http://samvak.tripod.com/scarcity.html
The distribution of means is thus skewed. “Distributive
justice” deals with the just allocation of scarce resources.
Yet, even the basic terminology is somewhat fuzzy. What
constitutes a resource? what is meant by allocation? Who
should allocate resources – Adam Smith’s “invisible
hand”, the government, the consumer, or business? Should
it reflect differences in power, in intelligence, in
knowledge, or in heredity? Should resource allocation be
subject to a principle of entitlement? Is it reasonable to
demand that it be just – or merely efficient? Are justice
and efficiency antonyms?
Justice is concerned with equal access to opportunities.
Equal access does not guarantee equal outcomes,
invariably determined by idiosyncrasies and differences
between people. Access leveraged by the application of
natural or acquired capacities – translates into accrued
wealth. Disparities in these capacities lead to
discrepancies in accrued wealth.
The doctrine of equal access is founded on the
equivalence of Men. That all men are created equal and
deserve the same respect and, therefore, equal treatment is
not self evident. European aristocracy well into this
century would have probably found this notion abhorrent.
Jose Ortega Y Gasset, writing in the 1930’s, preached that
access to educational and economic opportunities should
be premised on one’s lineage, up bringing, wealth, and
social responsibilities.
A succession of societies and cultures discriminated
against the ignorant, criminals, atheists, females,
homosexuals, members of ethnic, religious, or racial
groups, the old, the immigrant, and the poor. Communism
– ostensibly a strict egalitarian idea – foundered because it
failed to reconcile strict equality with economic and
psychological realities within an impatient timetable.
Philosophers tried to specify a “bundle” or “package” of
goods, services, and intangibles (like information, or
skills, or knowledge). Justice – though not necessarily
happiness – is when everyone possesses an identical
bundle. Happiness – though not necessarily justice – is
when each one of us possesses a “bundle” which reflects
his or her preferences, priorities, and predilections. None
of us will be too happy with a standardized bundle,
selected by a committee of philosophers – or bureaucrats,
as was the case under communism.
The market allows for the exchange of goods and services
between holders of identical bundles. If I seek books, but
detest oranges – I can swap them with someone in return
for his books. That way both of us are rendered better off
than under the strict egalitarian version.
Still, there is no guarantee that I will find my exact match
– a person who is interested in swapping his books for my
oranges. Illiquid, small, or imperfect markets thus inhibit
the scope of these exchanges. Additionally, exchange
participants have to agree on an index: how many books
for how many oranges? This is the price of oranges in
terms of books.
Money – the obvious “index” – does not solve this
problem, merely simplifies it and facilitates exchanges. It
does not eliminate the necessity to negotiate an “exchange
rate”. It does not prevent market failures. In other words:
money is not an index. It is merely a medium of exchange
and a store of value. The index – as expressed in terms of
money – is the underlying agreement regarding the values
of resources in terms of other resources (i.e., their relative
values).
The market – and the price mechanism – increase
happiness and welfare by allowing people to alter the
composition of their bundles. The invisible hand is just
and benevolent. But money is imperfect. The
aforementioned Rawles demonstrated (1971), that we
need to combine money with other measures in order to
place a value on intangibles.
The prevailing market theories postulate that everyone has
the same resources at some initial point (the “starting
gate”). It is up to them to deploy these endowments and,
thus, to ravage or increase their wealth. While the initial
distribution is equal – the end distribution depends on how
wisely – or imprudently – the initial distribution was used.
Egalitarian thinkers proposed to equate everyone’s income
in each time frame (e.g., annually). But identical incomes
do not automatically yield the same accrued wealth. The
latter depends on how the income is used – saved,
invested, or squandered. Relative disparities of wealth are
bound to emerge, regardless of the nature of income
distribution.
Some say that excess wealth should be confiscated and
redistributed. Progressive taxation and the welfare
state
aim to secure this outcome. Redistributive mechanisms
reset the “wealth clock” periodically (at the end of every
month, or fiscal year). In many countries, the law dictates
which portion of one’s income must be saved and, by
implication, how much can be consumed. This conflicts
with basic rights like the freedom to make economic
choices.
The legalized expropriation of income (i.e., taxes) is
morally dubious. Anti-tax movements have sprung all
over the world and their philosophy permeates the
ideology of political parties in many countries, not least
the USA. Taxes are punitive: they penalize enterprise,
success, entrepreneurship, foresight, and risk assumption.
Welfare, on the other hand, rewards dependence and
parasitism.
According to Rawles’ Difference Principle, all tenets of
justice are either redistributive or retributive. This ignores
non-economic activities and human inherent variance.
Moreover, conflict and inequality are the engines of
growth and innovation – which mostly benefit the least
advantaged in the long run. Experience shows that
unmitigated equality results in atrophy, corruption and
stagnation. Thermodynamics teaches us that life and
motion are engendered by an irregular distribution of
energy. Entropy – an even distribution of energy – equals
death and stasis.
What about the disadvantaged and challenged – the
mentally retarded, the mentally insane, the paralyzed, the
chronically ill? For that matter, what about the less
talented, less skilled, less daring? Dworkin (1981)
proposed a compensation scheme. He suggested a model
of fair distribution in which every person is given the
same purchasing power and uses it to bid, in a fair
auction, for resources that best fit that person’s life plan,
goals and preferences.
Having thus acquired these resources, we are then
permitted to use them as we see fit. Obviously, we end up
with disparate economic results. But we cannot complain –
we were given the same purchasing power and the
freedom to bid for a bundle of our choice.
Dworkin assumes that prior to the hypothetical auction,
people are unaware of their own natural endowments but
are willing and able to insure against being naturally
disadvantaged. Their payments create an insurance pool to
compensate the less fortunate for their misfortune.
This, of course, is highly unrealistic. We are usually very
much aware of natural endowments and liabilities – both
ours and others’. Therefore, the demand for such insurance
is not universal, nor uniform. Some of us badly need and
want it – others not at all. It is morally acceptable to let
willing buyers and sellers to trade in such coverage (e.g.,
by offering charity or alms) – but may be immoral to make
it compulsory.
Most of the modern welfare programs are involuntary
Dworkin schemes. Worse yet, they often measure
differences in natural endowments arbitrarily, compensate
for lack of acquired skills, and discriminate between types
of endowments in accordance with cultural biases and
fads.
Libertarians limit themselves to ensuring a level playing
field of just exchanges, where just actions always result in
just outcomes. Justice is not dependent on a particular
distribution pattern, whether as a starting point, or as an
outcome. Robert Nozick “Entitlement Theory” proposed
in 1974 is based on this approach.
That the market is wiser than any of its participants is a
pillar of the philosophy of capitalism. In its pure form, the
theory claims that markets yield patterns of merited
distribution – i.e., reward and punish justly. Capitalism
generate just deserts. Market failures – for instance, in the
provision of public goods – should be tackled by
governments. But a just distribution of income and wealth
does not constitute a market failure and, therefore, should
not be tampered with.
The Agent-Principal Conundrum
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also published by United Press International (UPI
In the catechism of capitalism, shares represent the part-
ownership of an economic enterprise, usually a firm. The
value of shares is determined by the replacement value of
the assets of the firm, including intangibles such as
goodwill. The price of the share is determined by
transactions among arm’s length buyers and sellers in an
efficient and liquid market. The price reflects expectations
regarding the future value of the firm and the stock’s
future stream of income – i.e., dividends.
Alas, none of these oft-recited dogmas bears any
resemblance to reality. Shares rarely represent ownership.
The float – the number of shares available to the public – is
frequently marginal. Shareholders meet once a year to
vent and disperse. Boards of directors are appointed by
management – as are auditors. Shareholders are not
represented in any decision making process – small or big.
The dismal truth is that shares reify the expectation to find
future buyers at a higher price and thus incur capital gains.
In the Ponzi scheme known as the stock exchange, this
expectation is proportional to liquidity – new suckers – and
volatility. Thus, the price of any given stock reflects
merely the consensus as to how easy it would be to
offload one’s holdings and at what price.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://www.upi.com/view.cfm?StoryID=20020725-113250-6845r
Another myth has to do with the role of managers. They
are supposed to generate higher returns to shareholders by
increasing the value of the firm’s assets and, therefore, of
the firm. If they fail to do so, goes the moral tale, they are
booted out mercilessly. This is one manifestation of the
“Principal-Agent Problem”. It is defined thus by the
Oxford Dictionary of Economics:
“The problem of how a person A can motivate person B to
act for A’s benefit rather than following (his) self-
interest.”
The obvious answer is that A can never motivate B not to
follow B’s self-interest – never mind what the incentives
are. That economists pretend otherwise – in “optimal
contracting theory” – just serves to demonstrate how
divorced economics is from human psychology and, thus,
from reality.
Managers will always rob blind the companies they run.
They will always manipulate boards to collude in their
shenanigans. They will always bribe auditors to bend the
rules. In other words, they will always act in their self-
interest. In their defense, they can say that the damage
from such actions to each shareholder is minuscule while
the benefits to the manager are enormous. In other words,
this is the rational, self-interested, thing to do.
But why do shareholders cooperate with such corporate
brigandage? In an important Chicago Law Review article
whose preprint was posted to the Web a few weeks ago –
titled “Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the
Design of Executive Compensation” – the authors
demonstrate how the typical stock option granted to
managers as part of their remuneration rewards mediocrity
rather than encourages excellence.
But everything falls into place if we realize that
shareholders and managers are allied against the firm – not
pitted against each other. The paramount interest of both
shareholders and managers is to increase the value of the
stock – regardless of the true value of the firm. Both are
concerned with the performance of the share – rather than
the performance of the firm. Both are preoccupied with
boosting the share’s price – rather than the company’s
business.
Hence the inflationary executive pay packets.
Shareholders hire stock manipulators – euphemistically
known as “managers” – to generate expectations regarding
the future prices of their shares. These snake oil salesmen
and snake charmers – the corporate executives – are
allowed by shareholders to loot the company providing
they generate consistent capital gains to their masters by
provoking persistent interest and excitement around the
business. Shareholders, in other words, do not behave as
owners of the firm – they behave as free-riders.
The Principal-Agent Problem arises in other social
interactions and is equally misunderstood there. Consider
taxpayers and their government. Contrary to conservative
lore, the former want the government to tax them
providing they share in the spoils.
They tolerate corruption in high places, cronyism,
nepotism, inaptitude and worse – on condition that the
government and the legislature redistribute the wealth
they confiscate. Such redistribution often comes in the
form of pork barrel projects and benefits to the middle-
class.
This is why the tax burden and the government’s share of
GDP have been soaring inexorably with the consent of the
citizenry. People adore government spending precisely
because it is inefficient and distorts the proper allocation
of economic resources. The vast majority of people are
rent-seekers. Witness the mass demonstrations that erupt
whenever governments try to slash expenditures,
privatize, and eliminate their gaping deficits. This is one
reason the IMF with its austerity measures is universally
unpopular.
Employers and employees, producers and consumers –
these are all instances of the Principal-Agent Problem.
Economists would do well to discard their models and go
back to basics. They could start by asking:
Why do shareholders acquiesce with executive
malfeasance as long as share prices are rising?
Why do citizens protest against a smaller government –
even though it means lower taxes?
Could it mean that the interests of shareholders and
managers are identical? Does it imply that people prefer
tax-and-spend governments and pork barrel politics to the
Thatcherite alternative?
Nothing happens by accident or by coercion. Shareholders
aided and abetted the current crop of corporate executives
enthusiastically. They knew well what was happening.
They may not have been aware of the exact nature and
extent of the rot – but they witnessed approvingly the
public relations antics, insider trading, stock option
resetting , unwinding, and unloading, share price
manipulation, opaque transactions, and outlandish pay
packages. Investors remained mum throughout the
corruption of corporate America. It is time for the
hangover.
Legalizing Crime
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also Read:
Narcissists, Ethnic or Religious Affiliation, and
Terrorists
The state has a monopoly on behavior usually deemed
criminal. It murders, kidnaps, and locks up people.
Sovereignty has come to be identified with the unbridled –
and exclusive – exercise of violence. The emergence of
modern international law has narrowed the field of
permissible conduct. A sovereign can no longer commit
genocide or ethnic cleansing with impunity, for instance.
Many acts – such as the waging of aggressive war, the
mistreatment of minorities, the suppression of the freedom
of association – hitherto sovereign privilege, have
thankfully been criminalized. Many politicians, hitherto
immune to international prosecution, are no longer so.
Consider Yugoslavia’s Milosevic and Chile’s Pinochet.
But, the irony is that a similar trend of criminalization –
within national legal systems – allows governments to
oppress their citizenry to an extent previously unknown.
Hitherto civil torts, permissible acts, and common
behavior patterns are routinely criminalized by legislators
and regulators. Precious few are decriminalized.
http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/cv.html
http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/12.html
http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/12.html
Consider, for instance, the criminalization in the
Economic Espionage Act (1996) of the misappropriation
of trade secrets and the criminalization of the violation of
copyrights in the Digital Millennium Copyright Act
(2000) – both in the USA. These used to be civil torts.
They still are in many countries. Drug use, common
behavior in England only 50 years ago – is now criminal.
The list goes on.
Criminal laws pertaining to property have malignantly
proliferated and pervaded every economic and private
interaction. The result is a bewildering multitude of laws,
regulations statutes, and acts.
The average Babylonian could have memorizes and
assimilated the Hammurabic code 37 centuries ago – it
was short, simple, and intuitively just.
English criminal law – partly applicable in many of its
former colonies, such as India, Pakistan, Canada, and
Australia – is a mishmash of overlapping and
contradictory statutes – some of these hundreds of years
old – and court decisions, collectively known as “case
law”.
Despite the publishing of a Model Penal Code in 1962 by
the American Law Institute, the criminal provisions of
various states within the USA often conflict. The typical
American can’t hope to get acquainted with even a
negligible fraction of his country’s fiendishly complex and
hopelessly brobdignagian criminal code. Such inevitable
ignorance breeds criminal behavior – sometimes
inadvertently – and transforms many upright citizens into
delinquents.
In the land of the free – the USA – close to 2 million adults
are behind bars and another 4.5 million are on probation,
most of them on drug charges. The costs of
criminalization – both financial and social – are mind
boggling. According to “The Economist”, America’s
prison system cost it $54 billion a year – disregarding the
price tag of law enforcement, the judiciary, lost product,
and
rehabilitation.
What constitutes a crime? A clear and consistent
definition has yet to transpire.
There are five types of criminal behavior: crimes against
oneself, or “victimless crimes” (such as suicide, abortion,
and the consumption of drugs), crimes against others
(such as murder or mugging), crimes among consenting
adults (such as incest, and in certain countries,
homosexuality and euthanasia), crimes against collectives
(such as treason, genocide, or ethnic cleansing), and
crimes against the international community and world
order (such as executing prisoners of war). The last two
categories often overlap.
The Encyclopedia Britannica provides this definition of a
crime:
“The intentional commission of an act usually deemed
socially harmful or dangerous and specifically defined,
prohibited, and punishable under the criminal law.”
But who decides what is socially harmful? What about
acts committed unintentionally (known as “strict liability
offenses” in the parlance)? How can we establish intention
– “mens rea”, or the “guilty mind” – beyond a reasonable
doubt?
A much tighter definition would be: “The commission of
an act punishable under the criminal law.” A crime is
what the law – state law, kinship law, religious law, or any
other widely accepted law – says is a crime. Legal systems
and texts often conflict.
Murderous blood feuds are legitimate according to the
15th century “Qanoon”, still applicable in large parts of
Albania. Killing one’s infant daughters and old relatives is
socially condoned – though illegal – in India, China,
Alaska, and parts of Africa. Genocide may have been
legally sanctioned in Germany and Rwanda – but is
strictly forbidden under international law.
Laws being the outcomes of compromises and power
plays, there is only a tenuous connection between justice
and morality. Some “crimes” are categorical imperatives.
Helping the Jews in Nazi Germany was a criminal act –
yet a highly moral one.
The ethical nature of some crimes depends on
circumstances, timing, and cultural context. Murder is a
vile deed – but assassinating Saddam Hussein may be
morally commendable. Killing an embryo is a crime in
some countries – but not so killing a fetus. A “status
offense” is not a criminal act if committed by an adult.
Mutilating the body of a live baby is heinous – but this is
the essence of Jewish circumcision. In some societies,
criminal guilt is collective. All Americans are held
blameworthy by the Arab street for the choices and
actions of their leaders. All Jews are accomplices in the
“crimes” of the “Zionists”.
In all societies, crime is a growth industry. Millions of
professionals – judges, police officers, criminologists,
psychologists, journalists, publishers, prosecutors,
lawyers, social workers, probation officers, wardens,
sociologists, non-governmental-organizations, weapons
manufacturers, laboratory technicians, graphologists, and
private detectives – derive their livelihood, parasitically,
from crime. They often perpetuate models of punishment
and retribution that lead to recidivism rather than to to the
reintegration of criminals in society and their
rehabilitation.
Organized in vocal interest groups and lobbies, they harp
on the insecurities and phobias of the alienated urbanites.
They consume ever growing budgets and rejoice with
every new behavior criminalized by exasperated
lawmakers. In the majority of countries, the justice system
is a dismal failure and law enforcement agencies are part
of the problem, not its solution.
The sad truth is that many types of crime are considered
by people to be normative and common behaviors and,
thus, go unreported. Victim surveys and self-report studies
conducted by criminologists reveal that most crimes go
unreported. The protracted fad of criminalization has
rendered criminal many perfectly acceptable and recurring
behaviors and acts. Homosexuality, abortion, gambling,
prostitution, pornography, and suicide have all been
criminal offenses at one time or another.
But the quintessential example of over-criminalization is
drug abuse.
There is scant medical evidence that soft drugs such as
cannabis or MDMA (“Ecstasy”) – and even cocaine – have
an irreversible effect on brain chemistry or functioning.
Last month an almighty row erupted in Britain when Jon
Cole, an addiction researcher at Liverpool University,
claimed, to quote “The Economist” quoting the
“Psychologist”, that:
“Experimental evidence suggesting a link between
Ecstasy use and problems such as nerve damage and brain
impairment is flawed … using this ill-substantiated cause-
and-effect to tell the ‘chemical generation’ that they are
brain damaged when they are not creates public health
problems of its own.”
Moreover, it is commonly accepted that alcohol abuse and
nicotine abuse can be at least as harmful as the abuse of
marijuana, for instance. Yet, though somewhat curbed,
alcohol consumption and cigarette smoking are legal. In
contrast, users of cocaine – only a century ago
recommended by doctors as tranquilizer – face life in jail
in many countries, death in others. Almost everywhere pot
smokers are confronted with prison terms.
The “war on drugs” – one of the most expensive and
protracted in history – has failed abysmally. Drugs are
more abundant and cheaper than ever. The social costs
have been staggering: the emergence of violent crime
where none existed before, the destabilization of drug-
producing countries, the collusion of drug traffickers with
terrorists, and the death of millions – law enforcement
agents, criminals, and users.
Few doubt that legalizing most drugs would have a
beneficial effect. Crime empires would crumble
overnight, users would be assured of the quality of the
products they consume, and the addicted few would not
be incarcerated or stigmatized – but rather treated and
rehabilitated.
That soft, largely harmless, drugs continue to be illicit is
the outcome of compounded political and economic
pressures by lobby and interest groups of manufacturers
of legal drugs, law enforcement agencies, the judicial
system, and the aforementioned long list of those who
benefit from the status quo.
Only a popular movement can lead to the
decriminalization of the more innocuous drugs. But such a
crusade should be part of a larger campaign to reverse the
overall tide of criminalization. Many “crimes” should
revert to their erstwhile status as civil torts. Others should
be wiped off the statute books altogether. Hundreds of
thousands should be pardoned and allowed to reintegrate
in society, unencumbered by a past of transgressions
against an inane and inflationary penal code.
This, admittedly, will reduce the leverage the state has
today against its citizens and its ability to intrude on their
lives, preferences, privacy, and leisure. Bureaucrats and
politicians may find this abhorrent. Freedom loving
people should rejoice.
The Insanity of the Defense
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Also Read
On Disease
Althusser, Competing Interpellations and the Third Text
The Use and Abuse of Differential Diagnoses
The Myth of Mental Illness
“You can know the name of a bird in all the languages
of the world, but when you’re finished, you’ll know
absolutely nothing whatever about the bird… So let’s
look at the bird and see what it’s doing – that’s what
counts. I learned very early the difference between
knowing the name of something and knowing
something.”
Richard Feynman, Physicist and 1965 Nobel Prize
laureate (1918-1988)
“You have all I dare say heard of the animal spirits and
how they are transfused from father to son etcetera
etcetera – well you may take my word that nine parts in
ten of a man’s sense or his nonsense, his successes and
miscarriages in this world depend on their motions and
activities, and the different tracks and trains you put
them into, so that when they are once set a-going,
whether right or wrong, away they go cluttering like hey-
go-mad.”
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/disease.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/13.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/mentalillness.html
Lawrence Sterne (1713-1758), “The Life and Opinions of
Tristram Shandy, Gentleman” (1759)
I. The Insanity Defense
II. The Concept of Mental Disease – An Overview
III. Personality Disorders
IV. The Biochemistry and Genetics of Mental Health
V. The Variance of Mental Disease
VI. Mental Disorders and the Social Order
VII. Mental Ailment as a Useful Metaphor
I. The Insanity Defense
“It is an ill thing to knock against a deaf-mute, an
imbecile, or a minor. He that wounds them is culpable,
but if they wound him they are not culpable.” (Mishna,
Babylonian Talmud)
If mental illness is culture-dependent and mostly serves as
an organizing social principle – what should we make of
the insanity defense (NGRI- Not Guilty by Reason of
Insanity)?
A person is held not responsible for his criminal actions if
s/he cannot tell right from wrong (“lacks substantial
capacity either to appreciate the criminality
(wrongfulness) of his conduct” – diminished capacity), did
not intend to act the way he did (absent “mens rea”)
and/or could not control his behavior (“irresistible
impulse”). These handicaps are often associated with
“mental disease or defect” or “mental retardation”.
Mental health professionals prefer to talk about an
impairment of a “person’s perception or understanding of
reality”. They hold a “guilty but mentally ill” verdict to be
contradiction in terms. All “mentally-ill” people operate
within a (usually coherent) worldview, with consistent
internal logic, and rules of right and wrong (ethics). Yet,
these rarely conform to the way most people perceive the
world. The mentally-ill, therefore, cannot be guilty
because s/he has a tenuous grasp on reality.
Yet, experience teaches us that a criminal maybe mentally
ill even as s/he maintains a perfect reality test and thus is
held criminally responsible (Jeffrey Dahmer comes to
mind). The “perception and understanding of reality”, in
other words, can and does co-exist even with the severest
forms of mental illness.
This makes it even more difficult to comprehend what is
meant by “mental disease”. If some mentally ill maintain a
grasp on reality, know right from wrong, can anticipate
the outcomes of their actions, are not subject to irresistible
impulses (the official position of the American Psychiatric
Association) – in what way do they differ from us,
“normal” folks?
http://www.psych.org/public_info/insanity.cfm
http://www.psych.org/public_info/insanity.cfm
http://www.psych.org/public_info/insanity.cfm
This is why the insanity defense often sits ill with mental
health pathologies deemed socially “acceptable” and
“normal” – such as religion or love.
Consider the following case:
A mother bashes the skulls of her three sons. Two of them
die. She claims to have acted on instructions she had
received from God. She is found not guilty by reason of
insanity. The jury determined that she “did not know right
from wrong during the killings.”
But why exactly was she judged insane?
Her belief in the existence of God – a being with
inordinate and inhuman attributes – may be irrational.
But it does not constitute insanity in the strictest sense
because it conforms to social and cultural creeds and
codes of conduct in her milieu. Billions of people
faithfully subscribe to the same ideas, adhere to the same
transcendental rules, observe the same mystical rituals,
and claim to go through the same experiences. This shared
psychosis is so widespread that it can no longer be
deemed pathological, statistically speaking.
She claimed that God has spoken to her.
As do numerous other people. Behavior that is considered
psychotic (paranoid-schizophrenic) in other contexts is
lauded and admired in religious circles. Hearing voices
and seeing visions – auditory and visual delusions – are
considered rank manifestations of righteousness and
sanctity.
http://samvak.tripod.com/lovepathology.html
http://story.news.yahoo.com/news?tmpl=story&cid=519&ncid=716&e=3&u=/ap/20040404/ap_on_re_us/children_slain
http://story.news.yahoo.com/news?tmpl=story&cid=519&ncid=716&e=3&u=/ap/20040404/ap_on_re_us/children_slain
http://story.news.yahoo.com/news?tmpl=story&cid=519&ncid=716&e=3&u=/ap/20040404/ap_on_re_us/children_slain
Perhaps it was the content of her hallucinations that
proved her insane?
She claimed that God had instructed her to kill her boys.
Surely, God would not ordain such evil?
Alas, the Old and New Testaments both contain examples
of God’s appetite for human sacrifice. Abraham was
ordered by God to sacrifice Isaac, his beloved son (though
this savage command was rescinded at the last moment).
Jesus, the son of God himself, was crucified to atone for
the sins of humanity.
A divine injunction to slay one’s offspring would sit well
with the Holy Scriptures and the Apocrypha as well as
with millennia-old Judeo-Christian traditions of
martyrdom and sacrifice.
Her actions were wrong and incommensurate with both
human and divine (or natural) laws.
Yes, but they were perfectly in accord with a literal
interpretation of certain divinely-inspired texts, millennial
scriptures, apocalyptic thought systems, and
fundamentalist religious ideologies (such as the ones
espousing the imminence of “rapture”). Unless one
declares these doctrines and writings insane, her actions
are not.
We are forced to the conclusion that the murderous
mother is perfectly sane. Her frame of reference is
different to ours. Hence, her definitions of right and
wrong are idiosyncratic. To her, killing her babies was the
right thing to do and in conformity with valued teachings
and her own epiphany. Her grasp of reality – the
immediate and later consequences of her actions – was
never impaired.
It would seem that sanity and insanity are relative terms,
dependent on frames of cultural and social reference, and
statistically defined. There isn’t – and, in principle, can
never emerge – an “objective”, medical, scientific test to
determine mental health or disease unequivocally.
II. The Concept of Mental Disease – An Overview
Someone is considered mentally “ill” if:
1. His conduct rigidly and consistently deviates from
the typical, average behaviour of all other people
in his culture and society that fit his profile
(whether this conventional behaviour is moral or
rational is immaterial), or
2. His judgment and grasp of objective, physical
reality is impaired, and
3. His conduct is not a matter of choice but is innate
and irresistible, and
4. His behavior causes him or others discomfort, and
is
5. Dysfunctional, self-defeating, and self-destructive
even by his own yardsticks.
Descriptive criteria aside, what is the essence of mental
disorders? Are they merely physiological disorders of the
brain, or, more precisely of its chemistry? If so, can they
be cured by restoring the balance of substances and
secretions in that mysterious organ? And, once
equilibrium is reinstated – is the illness “gone” or is it still
lurking there, “under wraps”, waiting to erupt? Are
psychiatric problems inherited, rooted in faulty genes
(though amplified by environmental factors) – or brought
on by abusive or wrong nurturance?
These questions are the domain of the “medical” school of
mental health.
Others cling to the spiritual view of the human psyche.
They believe that mental ailments amount to the
metaphysical discomposure of an unknown medium – the
soul. Theirs is a holistic approach, taking in the patient in
his or her entirety, as well as his milieu.
The members of the functional school regard mental
health disorders as perturbations in the proper, statistically
“normal”, behaviours and manifestations of “healthy”
individuals, or as dysfunctions. The “sick” individual – ill
at ease with himself (ego-dystonic) or making others
unhappy (deviant) – is “mended” when rendered
functional again by the prevailing standards of his social
and cultural frame of reference.
In a way, the three schools are akin to the trio of blind
men who render disparate descriptions of the very same
elephant. Still, they share not only their subject matter –
but, to a counter intuitively large degree, a faulty
methodology.
As the renowned anti-psychiatrist, Thomas Szasz, of the
State University of New York, notes in his article “The
Lying Truths of Psychiatry”, mental health scholars,
regardless of academic predilection, infer the etiology of
mental disorders from the success or failure of treatment
modalities.
This form of “reverse engineering” of scientific models is
not unknown in other fields of science, nor is it
unacceptable if the experiments meet the criteria of the
scientific method. The theory must be all-inclusive
(anamnetic), consistent, falsifiable, logically compatible,
monovalent, and parsimonious. Psychological “theories” –
even the “medical” ones (the role of serotonin and
dopamine in mood disorders, for instance) – are usually
none of these things.
The outcome is a bewildering array of ever-shifting
mental health “diagnoses” expressly centred around
Western civilisation and its standards (example: the
ethical objection to suicide). Neurosis, a historically
fundamental “condition” vanished after 1980.
Homosexuality, according to the American Psychiatric
Association, was a pathology prior to 1973. Seven years
later, narcissism was declared a “personality disorder”,
almost seven decades after it was first described by Freud.
III. Personality Disorders
Indeed, personality disorders are an excellent example of
the kaleidoscopic landscape of “objective” psychiatry.
The classification of Axis II personality disorders –
deeply ingrained, maladaptive, lifelong behavior patterns
– in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual, fourth edition,
text revision [American Psychiatric Association. DSM-
IV-TR, Washington, 2000] – or the DSM-IV-TR for short
– has come under sustained and serious criticism from its
inception in 1952, in the first edition of the DSM.
The DSM IV-TR adopts a categorical approach,
postulating that personality disorders are “qualitatively
distinct clinical syndromes” (p. 689). This is widely
doubted. Even the distinction made between “normal” and
“disordered” personalities is increasingly being rejected.
The “diagnostic thresholds” between normal and
abnormal are either absent or weakly supported.
The polythetic form of the DSM’s Diagnostic Criteria –
only a subset of the criteria is adequate grounds for a
diagnosis – generates unacceptable diagnostic
heterogeneity. In other words, people diagnosed with the
same personality disorder may share only one criterion or
none.
The DSM fails to clarify the exact relationship between
Axis II and Axis I disorders and the way chronic
childhood and developmental problems interact with
personality
disorders.
The differential diagnoses are vague and the personality
disorders are insufficiently demarcated. The result is
excessive co-morbidity (multiple Axis II diagnoses).
The DSM contains little discussion of what
distinguishes normal character (personality), personality
traits, or personality style (Millon) – from personality
disorders.
A dearth of documented clinical experience regarding
both the disorders themselves and the utility of various
treatment modalities.
Numerous personality disorders are “not otherwise
specified” – a catchall, basket “category”.
Cultural bias is evident in certain disorders (such as the
Antisocial and the Schizotypal).
The emergence of dimensional alternatives to the
categorical approach is acknowledged in the DSM-IV-TR
itself:
“An alternative to the categorical approach is the
dimensional perspective that Personality Disorders
represent maladaptive variants of personality traits that
merge imperceptibly into normality and into one
another” (p.689)
The following issues – long neglected in the DSM – are
likely to be tackled in future editions as well as in current
research. But their omission from official discourse
hitherto is both startling and telling:
The longitudinal course of the disorder(s) and their
temporal stability from early childhood onwards;
The genetic and biological underpinnings of
personality disorder(s);
The development of personality psychopathology
during childhood and its emergence in
adolescence;
The interactions between physical health and
disease and personality disorders;
The effectiveness of various treatments – talk
therapies as well as psychopharmacology.
IV. The Biochemistry and Genetics of Mental Health
Certain mental health afflictions are either correlated with
a statistically abnormal biochemical activity in the brain –
or are ameliorated with medication. Yet the two facts are
not ineludibly facets of the same underlying phenomenon.
In other words, that a given medicine reduces or abolishes
certain symptoms does not necessarily mean they were
caused by the processes or substances affected by the
drug administered. Causation is only one of many possible
connections and chains of events.
To designate a pattern of behaviour as a mental health
disorder is a value judgment, or at best a statistical
observation. Such designation is effected regardless of the
facts of brain science. Moreover, correlation is not
causation. Deviant brain or body biochemistry (once
called “polluted animal spirits”) do exist – but are they
truly the roots of mental perversion? Nor is it clear which
triggers what: do the aberrant neurochemistry or
biochemistry cause mental illness – or the other way
around?
That psychoactive medication alters behaviour and mood
is indisputable. So do illicit and legal drugs, certain foods,
and all interpersonal interactions. That the changes
brought about by prescription are desirable – is debatable
and involves tautological thinking. If a certain pattern of
behaviour is described as (socially) “dysfunctional” or
(psychologically) “sick” – clearly, every change would be
welcomed as “healing” and every agent of transformation
would be called a “cure”.
The same applies to the alleged heredity of mental illness.
Single genes or gene complexes are frequently
“associated” with mental health diagnoses, personality
traits, or behaviour patterns. But too little is known to
establish irrefutable sequences of causes-and-effects.
Even less is proven about the interaction of nature and
nurture, genotype and phenotype, the plasticity of the
brain and the psychological impact of trauma, abuse,
upbringing, role models, peers, and other environmental
elements.
Nor is the distinction between psychotropic substances
and talk therapy that clear-cut. Words and the interaction
with the therapist also affect the brain, its processes and
chemistry – albeit more slowly and, perhaps, more
profoundly and irreversibly. Medicines – as David Kaiser
reminds us in “Against Biologic Psychiatry” (Psychiatric
Times, Volume XIII, Issue 12, December 1996) – treat
symptoms, not the underlying processes that yield them.
V. The Variance of Mental Disease
If mental illnesses are bodily and empirical, they should
be invariant both temporally and spatially, across cultures
and societies. This, to some degree, is, indeed, the case.
Psychological diseases are not context dependent – but the
pathologizing of certain behaviours is. Suicide, substance
abuse, narcissism, eating disorders, antisocial ways,
schizotypal symptoms, depression, even psychosis are
considered sick by some cultures – and utterly normative
or advantageous in others.
This was to be expected. The human mind and its
dysfunctions are alike around the world. But values differ
from time to time and from one place to another. Hence,
disagreements about the propriety and desirability of
human actions and inaction are bound to arise in a
symptom-based diagnostic system.
As long as the pseudo-medical definitions of mental
health disorders continue to rely exclusively on signs and
symptoms – i.e., mostly on observed or reported
behaviours – they remain vulnerable to such discord and
devoid of much-sought universality and rigor.
VI. Mental Disorders and the Social Order
The mentally sick receive the same treatment as carriers
of AIDS or SARS or the Ebola virus or smallpox. They
are sometimes quarantined against their will and coerced
into involuntary treatment by medication, psychosurgery,
or electroconvulsive therapy. This is done in the name of
the greater good, largely as a preventive policy.
Conspiracy theories notwithstanding, it is impossible to
ignore the enormous interests vested in psychiatry and
psychopharmacology. The multibillion dollar industries
involving drug companies, hospitals, managed healthcare,
private clinics, academic departments, and law
enforcement agencies rely, for their continued and
exponential growth, on the propagation of the concept of
“mental illness” and its corollaries: treatment and
research.
VII. Mental Ailment as a Useful Metaphor
Abstract concepts form the core of all branches of human
knowledge. No one has ever seen a quark, or untangled a
chemical bond, or surfed an electromagnetic wave, or
visited the unconscious. These are useful metaphors,
theoretical entities with explanatory or descriptive power.
“Mental health disorders” are no different. They are
shorthand for capturing the unsettling quiddity of “the
Other”. Useful as taxonomies, they are also tools of social
coercion and conformity, as Michel Foucault and Louis
Althusser observed. Relegating both the dangerous and
the idiosyncratic to the collective fringes is a vital
technique of social engineering.
The aim is progress through social cohesion and the
regulation of innovation and creative destruction.
Psychiatry, therefore, is reifies society’s preference of
evolution to revolution, or, worse still, to mayhem. As is
often the case with human endeavour, it is a noble cause,
unscrupulously and dogmatically pursued.
http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html
AC/DC – a Deliberation Regarding the Impeachment
of the President of the United States of America
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
Review the Responses of US Senators
In the hallways of the Smithsonian, two moralists are
debating the impeachment of the President of the United
States of America, Mr. William Jefferson Clinton. One is
clearly Anti-Clinton (AC) the other, a Democrat (DC), is
not so much for him as he is for the rational and pragmatic
application of moral principles.
AC (expectedly): “The President should be impeached”.
DC (no less expectedly): “But, surely, even you are not
trying to imply that he has committed high crimes and
misdemeanours, as the Constitution demands as grounds
for the impeachment of a sitting President!”
AC: “But I do. Perjury is such a high crime because it
undermines the very fabric of trust between fellow
citizens and between the citizen and the system of justice,
the courts.”
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/senator.html
DC: “A person is innocent until proven guilty. No sound
proof of perjurious conduct on behalf of the President has
been provided as yet. Perjurious statements have to be
deliberate and material. Even if the President deliberately
lied under oath – his lies were not material to a case,
which was later dismissed on the grounds of a lack of
legal merit. Legal hairsplitting and jousting are an
integral part of the defence in most court cases, civil and
criminal. It is a legitimate – and legal – component of any
legal battle, especially one involving interpretations,
ambiguous terminology and the substantiation of
intentions. The President should not be denied the
procedural and substantive rights available to all the
other citizens of his country. Nor should he be subjected
to a pre-judgment of his presumed guilt.”
AC: “This, precisely, is why an impeachment trial by the
Senate is called for. It is only there that the President can
credibly and rigorously establish his innocence. All I am
saying is that IF the President is found by the Senate to
have committed perjury – he should be impeached.
Wherever legal hairsplitting and jousting is permissible as
a legal tactic – it should and will be made available to the
President. As to the pre-judgment by the Press – I agree
with you, there is no place for it but, then, in this the
President has been treated no differently than others. The
pertinent fact is that perjury is a high misdemeanour, in
the least, that is, an impeachable offence.”
DC: “It was clearly not the intention of the Fathers of our
Constitution to include perjury in the list of impeachable
offences. Treason is more like it. Moreover, to say that the
President will receive a fair trial from the hands of his
peers in the Senate – is to lie. The Senate and its
committees is a political body, heavily tilted, currently,
against the President. No justice can be had where politics
rears its ugly head. Bias and prejudice will rule this mock
trial.”
AC: “Man is a political animal, said the Greek
philosophers of antiquity. Where can you find an
assembly of people free of politics? What is this discourse
that we are having if not a political one? Is not the
Supreme Court of the land a politically appointed entity?
The Senate is no better and no worse, it is but a mirror, a
reflection of the combined will of the people. Moreover,
in pursuing the procedures of impeachment – the Senate
will have proved its non-political mettle in this case. The
nation, in all opinion polls, wants this matter dropped. If it
is not – it is a proof of foresight and civil courage, of
leadership and refusal to succumb to passing fads.”
DC: “And what about my first argument – that perjury,
even once proven, was not considered by the authors of
the Constitution to have been an impeachable offence?”
AC: “The rules of the land – even the Constitution – are
nothing but an agreement between those who subscribe to
it and for as long as they do. It is a social contract, a pact.
Men – even the authors of the Constitution – being mortal,
relegated the right to amend it and to interpret it to future
generations. The Constitution is a vessel, each generation
fills it as it sees fit. It is up to us to say what current
meaning this document harbours. We are not to be
constrained by the original intentions of the authors.
These intentions are meaningless as circumstances
change. It is what we read into the Constitution that forms
its specific contents. With changing mores and values and
with the passage of events – each generation generates its
own version of this otherwise immortal set of principles.”
DC: “I find it hard to accept that there is no limit to this
creative deconstruction. Surely it is limited by common
sense, confined to logic, subordinate to universal human
principles. One can stretch the meanings of words only
thus far. It takes a lot of legal hairsplitting to bring perjury
– not proven yet – under one roof with
treason.”
AC: “Let us ignore the legal issues and leave them to their
professionals. Let us talk about what really bothers us all,
including you, I hope and trust. This President has lied.
He may have lied under oath, but he definitely lied on
television and in the spacious rooms of the White House.
He lied to his family, to his aides, to the nation, to
Congress…”
DC: “For what purpose do you enumerate them?”
AC: “Because it is one thing to lie to your family and
another thing to lie to Congress. A lie told to the nation, is
of a different magnitude altogether. To lie to your closest
aides and soi dissant confidantes – again is a separate
matter…”
DC: “So you agree that there are lies and there are lies?
That lying is not a monolithic offence? That some lies
are worse than others, some are permissible, some even
ethically mandatory?”
AC: “No, I do not. To lie is to do a morally objectionable
thing, no matter what the circumstances. It is better to shut
up. Why didn’t the President invoke the Fifth
Amendment, the right not to incriminate himself by his
own lips?”
DC: “Because as much information is contained in
abstaining to do something as in doing it and because if he
did so, he would have provoked riotous rumours.
Rumours are always worse than the truth. Rumours are
always worse than the most defiled lie. It is better to lie
than to provoke rumours.”
AC: “Unless your lies are so clearly lies that you provoke
rumours regarding what is true, thus inflicting a double
blow upon the public peace that you were mandated to
and undertook to preserve…”
DC: “Again, you make distinctions between types of lies
– this time, by their efficacy. I am not sure this is
progress. Let me give you examples of the three cases:
where one would do morally well to tell the truth, where
one would achieve morally commendable outcomes only
by lying and the case where lying is as morally
permissible as telling the truth. Imagine a young sick
adult. Her life is at peril but can be saved if she were to
agree to consume a certain medicine. This medicament,
however, will render her sterile. Surely, she must be told
the truth. It should be entirely her decision how to
continue his life: in person or through her progeny. Now,
imagine that this young woman, having suffered greatly
already, informed her doctor that should she learn that her
condition is terminal and that she needs to consume
medicines with grave side effects in order to prolong it or
even to save it altogether – she is determined to take her
life and has already procured the means to do so. Surely, it
is mandatory to lie to this young woman in order to save
her life. Imagine now the third situation: that she also
made a statement that having a child is her only,
predominant, all pervasive, wish in life. Faced with two
conflicting statements, some may choose to reveal the
truth to her – others, to withhold it, and with the same
amount of moral justification.”
AC: “And what are we to learn from this?”
DC: “That the moral life is a chain of dilemmas, almost
none of which is solvable. The President may have lied in
order to preserve his family, to protect his only child, to
shield his aides from embarrassing legal scrutiny, even to
protect his nation from what he perceived to have been the
destructive zeal of the special prosecutor. Some of his lies
should be considered at least common, if not morally
permissible.”
AC: “This is a slippery slope. There is no end to this
moral relativism. It is a tautology. You say that in some
cases there are morally permissible reasons to lie. When I
ask you how come – you say to me that people lie only
when they have good reasons to lie. But this the crux of
your mistake: good reasons are not always sufficient,
morally permissible, or even necessary reasons. Put more
plainly: no one lies without a reason. Does the fact that a
liar has a reason to lie – absolve him?”
DC: “Depends what is the reason. This is what I tried to
establish in my little sad example above. To lie about a
sexual liaison – even under oath – may be morally
permissible if the intention is to shield other meaningful
individuals from harm, or in order to buttress the
conditions, which will allow one to fulfil one’s side of a
contract. The President has a contract with the American
people, sealed in two elections. He has to perform. It is his
duty no less than he has a duty to tell the truth. Conflict
arises only when two equally powerful principles clash.
The very fact that there is a controversy in the public
demonstrates the moral ambiguity of this situation.
The dysfunction of the American presidency has already
cost trillions of dollars in a collapsing global economy.
Who knows how many people died and will die in the
pursuit of the high principle of vincit omnia veritas (the
truth always prevails)? If I could prove to you that one
person – just one person – committed suicide as a result of
the financial turmoil engendered by the Clinton affair,
would you still stick to your lofty ideals?”
AC: “You inadvertently, I am sure, broached the heart of
this matter. The President is in breach of his contracts.
Not one contract – but many. As all of us do – he has a
contract with other fellow beings, he is a signatory to a
Social Treaty. One of the articles of this treaty calls to
respect the Law by not lying under oath. Another calls for
striving to maintain a generally truthful conduct towards
the other signatories. The President has a contract with
his wife, which he clearly violated, by committing
adultery. Professing to be a believing man, he is also in
breach of his contract with his God as set forth in the
Holy Scriptures. But the President has another, very
powerful and highly specific contract with the American
people. It is this contract that has been violated savagely
and expressly by the President.”
DC: “The American people does not seem to think so, but,
prey, continue…”
AC: “Before I do, allow me just to repeat. To me, there is
no moral difference between one lie and another. All lies
are loathsome and lead, in the long run, to hell whatever
the good intentions, which paved the way there. As far as
I am concerned, President Clinton is a condemned man on
these grounds only. But the lies one chooses and the
victims he chooses to expose to his misbehaviour – reflect
his personality, his inner world, what type of human
being he is. It is the only allowance I make. All lies are
prohibited as all murders are. But there are murders most
foul and there are lies most abominable and obnoxious.
What are we to learn about the President from his choice
of arms and adversaries? That he is a paranoid, a
narcissist, lacks empathy, immature, unable to postpone
his satisfactions, to plan ahead, to foresee the outcomes of
his actions. He has a sense of special, unwarranted
entitlement, he judges his environment and the world, at
large, erroneously. In short: he is dangerously wrong for
the job that he has acquired through deception.”
DC: “Through elections…”
AC: “Nay, through deception brought about by elections.
He lied to the American people about who he is and what
he stands for. He did not frankly expose or discuss his
weaknesses and limitations. He sold his voters on an
invented, imaginary image, the product of spin-doctors
and opinion polls, which had no common denominator
with reality. This is gross deception.”
DC: “But now that the American people know everything
– they still prefer him over others, approve of his
performance and applaud his professional
achievements…”
AC: “This is the power of incumbency. It was the same
with Nixon until one month before his resignation. Or, do
you sanction his actions as well?”
DC: “Frankly, I will compare President Clinton to
President Andrew Johnson rather than to President
Nixon. The shattering discovery about Nixon was that he
was an uncommon criminal. The shattering discovery
about Clinton is that he is human. Congress chastises him
not for having done what he did – in this he has many
illustrious precedents. No, he is accused of being
indiscreet, of failing to hide the truth, to evade the facts.
He is reproached for his lack of efficiency at
concealment. He is criticized, therefore, both for being
evasive and for not being sufficiently protective of his
secrets. It is hard to win such a case, I tell you. It is also
hypocritical in the extreme.”
AC: “Do you agree that the President of the United States
is party to a contract with the American People?”
DC: “Absolutely.”
AC: “Would you say that he is enjoined by this contract to
uphold the dignity of his office?’
DC:”I think that most people would agree to this.”
AC: “And do you agree with me that fornicating in the
White House would tend to diminish rather than uphold
this dignity – and, therefore, constitute a violation of this
contract? That it shows utter disregard and disrespect to
the institutions of this country and to their standing?”
DC: “I assume that you mean to say fornication in
general, not only in the White House. To answer you, I
must analyse this complex issue into its components.
First, I assume that you agree with me that sex between
consenting adults is almost always legally allowed and,
depending on the circumstances and the culture, it is,
usually, morally acceptable. The President’s relationship
with Miss Lewinsky did not involve sexual harassment or
coercion and, therefore, was sex between consenting
adults. Legally, there could be nothing against it. The
problem, therefore, is cast in moral terms. Would you care
to define it?”
AC: “The President has engaged in sexual acts – some
highly unusual -with a woman much younger than he,
in a building belonging to the American public and put
at his disposal solely for the performance of his duties.
Moreover, his acts constituted adultery, which is a
morally reprehensible act. He acted secretly and tried to
conceal the facts using expressly illegal and immoral
means – namely by lying.”
DC: “I took the pains of noting down everything you said.
You said that the President has engaged in sexual acts and
there can be no dispute between us that this does not
constitute a problem. You said that some of them were
highly unusual. This is a value judgement, so dependent
on period and culture, that it is rendered meaningless by
its derivative nature. What to one is repulsive is to the
other a delightful stimulus. Of course, this applies only to
consenting adults and when life itself is not jeopardized.
Then you mentioned the age disparity between the
President and his liaison. This is sheer bigotry. I am
inclined to think that this statement is motivated more by
envy than by moral judgement…”
AC: “I beg to differ! His advantages in both position and
age do raise the spectre of exploitation, even of abuse! He
took advantage of her, capitalized on her lack of
experience and innocence, used her as a sex slave, an
object, there just to fulfil his desires and realize his
fantasies.”
DC: “Then there is no meaning to the word consent, nor
to the legal age of consent. The line must be drawn
somewhere. The President did not make explicit promises
and then did not own up to them. Expectations and
anticipation can develop in total vacuum, in a manner
unsubstantiated, not supported by any observable
behaviour. It is an open question who was using who in
this lurid tale – at least, who was hoping to use who. The
President, naturally, had much more to offer to Miss
Lewinsky than she could conceivably have offered to him.
Qui bono is a useful guide in reality as well as in mystery
books.”
AC: “This is again the same Presidential pattern of deceit,
half truths and plain lies. The President may not have
promised anything explicitly – but he sure did implicitly,
otherwise why would Miss Lewinsky have availed herself
sexually? Even if we adopt your more benevolent version
of events and assume that Miss Lewinsky approached this
avowed and professional womanizer with the intention of
taking advantage of him – clearly, a deal must have been
struck. ”
DC: “Yes, but we don’t know its nature and its
parameters. It is therefore useless to talk about this empty,
hypothetical entity. You also said that he committed these
acts of lust in a building belonging to the American public
and put at his disposal solely for the performance of his
duties. This is half-true, of course. This is also the home
of the President, his castle. He has to endure a lot in order
to occupy this mansion and the separation between private
and public life is only on paper. Presidents have no private
lives but only public ones. Why should we reproach them
for mixing the public with the private? This is a double
standard: when it suits our predatory instincts, our
hypocrisy and our search for a scapegoat – we disallow
the private life of a President. When these same low
drives can be satisfied by making this distinction – we
trumpet it. We must make up our minds: either Presidents
are not allowed to have private lives and then they should
be perfectly allowed to engage in all manner of normally
private behaviour in public and on public property (and
even at the public’s expense). Or the distinction is relevant
– in which case we should adopt the “European model”
and not pry into the lives of our Presidents, not expose
them, and not demand their public flagellation for very
private sins.”
AC: “This is a gross misrepresentation of the process that
led to the current sorry state of affairs. The President got
himself embroiled in numerous other legal difficulties
long before the Monika Lewinsky story erupted. The
special prosecutor was appointed to investigate
Whitewater and other matters long before the President’s
sexual shenanigans hit the courts. The President lied under
oath in connection with a private, civil lawsuit brought
against him by Paula Jones. It is all the President’s doing.
Decapitating the messenger – the special prosecutor – is
an old and defunct Roman habit.”
DC: “Then you proceeded to accuse the President of
adultery. Technically, there can be no disagreement. The
President’s actions – however sexual acts are defined –
constitute unequivocal adultery. But the legal and
operational definitions of adultery are divorced from the
emotional and moral discourse of the same phenomenon.
We must not forget that you stated that the adulterous acts
committed by the President have adversely affected the
dignity of his office and this is what seems to have
bothered you…”
AC: “Absolutely misrepresented. I do have a problem
with adultery in general and I wholeheartedly disagree
with it…”
DC: “I apologize. So, let us accord these two rather
different questions – the separate treatment that they
deserve. First, surely you agree with me that there can be
no dignity where there is no truth, for you said so
yourself. A marital relationship that fails abysmally to
provide the parties with sexual or emotional gratification
and is maintained in the teeth of such failure – is a lie. It is
a lie because it gives observers false information
regarding the state of things. What is better – to continue a
marriage of appearances and mutual hell – or to find
emotional and sexual fulfilment elsewhere? When the
pursuit of happiness is coupled with the refusal to pretend,
to pose, in other words, to lie, isn’t this commendable?
President Clinton admitted to marital problems and there
seems to be an incompatibility, which reaches to the roots
of this bond between himself and his wife.
Sometimes marriages start as one thing – passion, perhaps
or self delusion – and end up as another: mutual
acceptance, a warm habit, companionship. Many
marriages withstand marital infidelity precisely because
they are not conventional, or ideal marriages. By forgoing
sex, a partnership is sometimes strengthened and a true,
disinterested friendship is formed. I say that by insisting
on being true to himself, by refusing to accept social
norms of hypocrisy, conventions of make-belief and
camouflage, by exposing the lacunas in his marriage, by,
thus, redefining it and by pursuing his own sexual and
emotional happiness – the President has acted honestly.
He did not compromise the dignity of his office.”
AC: “Dysfunctional partnerships should be dissolved.
The President should have divorced prior to indulging his
sexual appetite. Sexual exclusivity is an integral –
possibly the most important – section of the marriage
contract. The President ignored his vows, dishonoured his
word, breached his contract with the First Lady.”
DC: “People stay together only if they feel that the
foundation upon which they based their relationship is
still sound. Mr. Clinton and Mrs. Clinton redefined their
marriage to exclude sexual exclusivity, an impossibility
under the circumstances. But they did not exclude
companionship and friendship. It is here that the President
may have sinned, in lying to his best friend, his wife.
Adultery is committed only when a party strays out of the
confines of the marital contract. I postulate that the
President was well within his agreement with Mrs.
Clinton when he sought sexual gratification elsewhere.”
AC: “Adultery is a sin not only against the partner. The
marriage contract is signed by three parties: the man, the
woman and God between them. The President sinned
against God. This cannot be ameliorated by any human
approval or permission. Whether his wife accepted him as
he is and disregarded his actions – is irrelevant. And if
you are agnostic or an atheist, still you can replace the
word ‗God’ by the words „Social Order’. President
Clinton’s behaviour undermines the foundations of our
social order. The family is the basic functional unit and its
proper functioning is guaranteed by the security of sexual
and emotional exclusivity. To be adulterous is to rebel
against civilization. It is an act of high social and moral
treason.”
DC: “While I may share your nostalgia – I am compelled
to inform you that even nostalgia is not what it used to be.
There is no such thing as ‗The Family’. There are a few
competing models, some of them involving only a single
person and his or her offspring. There is nothing to
undermine. The social order is in such a flux that it is
impossible to follow, let alone define or capture. Adultery
is common. This could be a sign of the times – or the
victory of honesty and openness over pretension and
hypocrisy. No one can cast a stone at President Clinton in
this day and age.”
AC: “But that’s precisely it! The President is not a mirror,
a reflection of the popular will. Our President is a leader
with awesome powers. These powers were given to him to
enable him to set example, to bear a standard – to be a
standard. I do demand of my President to be morally
superior to me – and this is no hypocrisy. This is a job
description. To lead, a leader needs to inspire shame and
guilt through his model. People must look up to him, wish
they were like him, hope, dream, aspire and conspire to be
like him. A true leader provokes inner tumult,
psychological conflicts, strong emotions – because he
demands the impossible through the instance of his
personality. A true leader moves people to sacrifice
because he is worthy of their sacrifice, because he
deserves it. He definitely does not set an example of moral
disintegration, recklessness, short-sightedness and
immaturity. The President is given unique power, status
and privileges – only because he has been recognized as a
unique and powerful and privileged individual. Whether
such recognition has been warranted or not is what
determines the quality of the presidency.”
DC: “Not being a leader, or having been misjudged by the
voters to be one – do not constitute impeachable offences.
I reject your view of the presidency. It is too fascist for
me, it echoes with the despicable Fuhrerprinzip. A leader
is no different from the people that elected him. A leader
has strong convictions shared by the majority of his
compatriots. A leader also has the energy to implement
the solutions that he proposes and the willingness to
sacrifice certain aspects of his life (like his privacy) to do
so. If a leader is a symbol of his people – then he must, in
many ways, be like them.
He cannot be as alien as you make him out to be. But
then, if he is alien by virtue of being superior or by virtue
of being possessed of superhuman qualities – how can we,
mere mortals, judge him? This is the logical fallacy in
your argument: if the President is a symbol, then he must
be very much similar to us and we should not subject him
to a judgement more severe than the one meted to
ourselves. If the President is omnipotent, omniscient,
omnipresent, or otherwise, superhuman – then he is above
our ability to judge. And if the President is a standard
against whom we should calibrate our lives and actions –
then he must reflect the mores of his times, the
kaleidoscopic nature of the society that bred him, the flux
of norms, conventions, paradigms and doctrines which
formed the society which chose him. A standard too
remote, too alien, too detached – will not do. People will
ignore it and revert to other behavioural benchmarks and
normative yardsticks. The President should, therefore, be
allowed to be “normal”, he should be forgiven. After all
forgiveness is as prominent a value as being truthful.
AC: “This allowance, alas, cannot be made. Even if I
were to accept your thesis about ‗The President as a
regular Human Being’ – still his circumstances are not
regular. The decisions that he faces – and very frequently
– affect the lives of billions. The conflicting pressures that
he is under, the gigantic amounts of information that he
must digest, the enormity of the tasks facing him and the
strains and stresses that are surely the results of these – all
call for a special human alloy. If cracks are found in this
alloy in room temperature – it raises doubts regarding its
ability to withstand harsher conditions. If the President
lies concerning a personal matter, no matter how
significant – who will guarantee veracity rather than
prevarication in matters more significant to us?
If he is afraid of a court of law – how is he likely to
command our armies in a time of war? If he is evasive in
his answers to the Grand Jury – how can we rely on his
resolve and determination when confronting world leaders
and when faced with extreme situations? If he loses his
temper over petty matters – who will guarantee his
coolheadedness when it is really required? If criminal in
small, household matters – why not in the international
arena?”
DC: “Because this continuum is false. There is little
correlation between reactive patterns in the personal
realms – and their far relatives in the public domain.
Implication by generalization is a logical fallacy. The
most adulterous, querulous, and otherwise despicable
people have been superb, far sighted statesmen. The most
generous, benevolent, easygoing ones have become
veritable political catastrophes. The public realm is not
the personal realm writ large. It is true that the leader’s
personality interacts with his circumstances to yield policy
choices. But the relevance of his sexual predilections in
this context is dubious indeed. It is true that his morals
and general conformity to a certain value system will
influence his actions and inactions – influence, but not
determine them. It is true that his beliefs, experience,
personality, character and temperament will colour the
way he does things – but rarely what he does and rarely
more than colour. Paradoxically, in times of crisis, there is
a tendency to overlook the moral vices of a leader (or, for
that matter, his moral virtues). If a proof was needed that
moral and personal conduct are less relevant to proper
leadership – this is it. When it really matters, we ignore
these luxuries of righteousness and get on with the
business of selecting a leader.
Not a symbol, not a standard bearer, not a superman.
Simply a human being – with all the flaws and
weaknesses of one – who can chart the water and navigate
to safety flying in the face of adverse circumstances.”
AC: “Like everything else in life, electing a leader is a
process of compromise, a negotiation between the ideal
and the real. I just happen to believe that a good leader is
the one who is closer to the ideal. You believe that one
has to be realistic, not to dream, not to expect. To me, this
is mental death. My criticism is a cry of the pain of
disillusionment. But if I have to choose between deluding
myself again and standing firmly on a corrupt and
degenerate ground – I prefer, and always will, the levity of
dreams.”
The Rights of Animals
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
―Animal rights‖ is a catchphrase akin to ―human rights‖.
It involves, however, a few pitfalls. First, animals exist
only as a concept. Otherwise, they are cuddly cats, curly
dogs, cute monkeys. A rat and a puppy are both animals
but our emotional reaction to them is so different that we
cannot really lump them together. Moreover: what rights
are we talking about? The right to life? The right to be
free of pain? The right to food? Except the right to free
speech – all other rights could be applied to animals.
Law professor Steven Wise, argues in his book, “Drawing
the Line: Science and the Case for Animal Rights”, for the
extension to animals of legal rights accorded to infants.
Many animal species exhibit awareness, cognizance and
communication skills typical of human toddlers and of
humans with arrested development. Yet, the latter enjoy
rights denied the former.
According to Wise, there are four categories of practical
autonomy – a legal standard for granting “personhood”
and the rights it entails. Practical autonomy involves the
ability to be desirous, to intend to fulfill and pursue one’s
desires, a sense of self-awareness, and self-sufficiency.
Most animals, says Wise, qualify. This may be going too
far. It is easier to justify the moral rights of animals than
their legal rights.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
But when we say “animals”, what we really mean is non-
human organisms. This is such a wide definition that it
easily pertains to extraterrestrial aliens. Will we witness
an Alien Rights movement soon? Unlikely. Thus, we are
forced to narrow our field of enquiry to non-human
organisms reminiscent of humans, the ones that provoke
in us empathy.
Even this is way too fuzzy. Many people love snakes, for
instance, and deeply empathize with them. Could we
accept the assertion (avidly propounded by these people)
that snakes ought to have rights – or should we consider
only organisms with extremities and the ability to feel
pain?
Historically, philosophers like Kant (and Descartes,
Malebranche, and Aquinas) rejected the idea of animal
rights. They regarded animals as the organic equivalents
of machines, driven by coarse instincts, unable to
experience pain (though their behavior sometimes
deceives us into erroneously believing that they do).
Thus, any ethical obligation that we have towards animals
is a derivative of our primary obligation towards our
fellow humans (the only ones possessed of moral
significance). These are called the theories of indirect
moral obligations. Thus, it is wrong to torture animals
only because it desensitizes us to human suffering and
makes us more prone to using violence on humans.
Malebranche augmented this line of thinking by “proving”
that animals cannot suffer pain because they are not
descended from Adam. Pain and suffering, as we all
know, are the exclusive outcomes of Adam’s sins.
Kant and Malebranche may have been wrong. Animals
may be able to suffer and agonize. But how can we tell
whether another Being is truly suffering pain or not?
Through empathy. We postulate that – since that Being
resembles us – it must have the same experiences and,
therefore, it deserves our pity.
Yet, the principle of resemblance has many drawbacks.
One, it leads to moral relativism.
Consider this maxim from the Jewish Talmud: “Do not do
unto thy friend that which you hate”. An analysis of this
sentence renders it less altruistic than it appears. We are
encouraged to refrain from doing only those things that
WE find hateful. This is the quiddity of moral relativism.
The saying implies that it is the individual who is the
source of moral authority. Each and every one of us is
allowed to spin his own moral system, independent of
others. The Talmudic dictum establishes a privileged
moral club (very similar to later day social
contractarianism) comprised of oneself and one’s
friend(s). One is encouraged not to visit evil upon one’s
friends, all others seemingly excluded. Even the broadest
interpretation of the word “friend” could only read:
“someone like you” and substantially excludes strangers.
Two, similarity is a structural, not an essential, trait.
Empathy as a differentiating principle is structural: if X
looks like me and behaves like me – then he is privileged.
Moreover, similarity is not necessarily identity. Monkeys,
dogs and dolphins are very much like us, both structurally
and behaviorally. Even according to Wise, it is quantity
(the degree of observed resemblance), not quality
(identity, essence), that is used in determining whether an
animal is worthy of holding rights, whether is it a morally
significant person. The degree of figurative and functional
likenesses decide whether one deserves to live, pain-free
and happy.
The quantitative test includes the ability to communicate
(manipulate vocal-verbal-written symbols within
structured symbol systems). Yet, we ignore the fact that
using the same symbols does not guarantee that we attach
to them the same cognitive interpretations and the same
emotional resonance (‘private languages”). The same
words, or symbols, often have different meanings.
Meaning is dependent upon historical, cultural, and
personal contexts. There is no telling whether two people
mean the same things when they say “red”, or “sad”, or
“I”, or “love”. That another organism looks like us,
behaves like us and communicates like us is no guarantee
that it is – in its essence – like us. This is the subject of the
famous Turing Test: there is no effective way to
distinguish a machine from a human when we rely
exclusively on symbol manipulation.
Consider pain once more.
http://samvak.tripod.com/turing.html
To say that something does not experience pain cannot be
rigorously defended. Pain is a subjective experience.
There is no way to prove or to disprove that someone is or
is not in pain. Here, we can rely only on the subject’s
reports. Moreover, even if we were to have an
analgometer (pain gauge), there would have been no way
to show that the phenomenon that activates the meter is
one and the same for all subjects, SUBJECTIVELY, i.e.,
that it is experienced in the same way by all the subjects
examined.
Even more basic questions regarding pain are impossible
to answer: What is the connection between the piercing
needle and the pain REPORTED and between these two
and electrochemical patterns of activity in the brain? A
correlation between these three phenomena can be
established – but not their identity or the existence of a
causative process. We cannot prove that the waves in the
subject’s brain when he reports pain – ARE that pain. Nor
can we show that they CAUSED the pain, or that the pain
caused them.
It is also not clear whether our moral percepts are
conditioned on the objective existence of pain, on the
reported existence of pain, on the purported existence of
pain (whether experienced or not, whether reported or
not), or on some independent laws.
If it were painless, would it be moral to torture someone?
Is the very act of sticking needles into someone immoral –
or is it immoral because of the pain it causes, or supposed
to inflict? Are all three components (needle sticking, a
sensation of pain, brain activity) morally equivalent? If so,
is it as immoral to merely generate the same patterns of
brain activity, without inducing any sensation of pain and
without sticking needles in the subject?
If these three phenomena are not morally equivalent –
why aren’t they? They are, after all, different facets of the
very same pain – shouldn’t we condemn all of them
equally? Or should one aspect of pain (the subject’s report
of pain) be accorded a privileged treatment and status?
Yet, the subject’s report is the weakest proof of pain! It
cannot be verified. And if we cling to this descriptive-
behavioral-phenomenological definition of pain than
animals qualify as well. They also exhibit all the
behaviors normally ascribed to humans in pain and they
report feeling pain (though they do tend to use a more
limited and non-verbal vocabulary).
Pain is, therefore, a value judgment and the reaction to it
is culturally dependent. In some cases, pain is perceived
as positive and is sought. In the Aztec cultures, being
chosen to be sacrificed to the Gods was a high honor.
How would we judge animal rights in such historical and
cultural contexts? Are there any “universal” values or does
it all really depend on interpretation?
If we, humans, cannot separate the objective from the
subjective and the cultural – what gives us the right or
ability to decide for other organisms? We have no way of
knowing whether pigs suffer pain.
We cannot decide right and wrong, good and evil for
those with whom we can communicate, let alone for
organisms with which we fail to do even this.
Is it GENERALLY immoral to kill, to torture, to pain?
The answer seems obvious and it automatically applies to
animals. Is it generally immoral to destroy? Yes, it is and
this answer applies to the inanimate as well. There are
exceptions: it is permissible to kill and to inflict pain in
order to prevent a (quantitatively or qualitatively) greater
evil, to protect life, and when no reasonable and feasible
alternative is available.
The chain of food in nature is morally neutral and so are
death and disease. Any act which is intended to sustain
life of a higher order (and a higher order in life) – is
morally positive or, at least neutral. Nature decreed so.
Animals do it to other animals – though, admittedly, they
optimize their consumption and avoid waste and
unnecessary pain. Waste and pain are morally wrong. This
is not a question of hierarchy of more or less important
Beings (an outcome of the fallacy of
anthropomorphesizing Nature).
The distinction between what is (essentially) US – and
what just looks and behaves like us (but is NOT us) is
false, superfluous and superficial. Sociobiology is already
blurring these lines. Quantum Mechanics has taught us
that we can say nothing about what the world really IS. If
things look the same and behave the same, we better
assume that they are the same.
http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html
The attempt to claim that moral responsibility is reserved
to the human species is self defeating. If it is so, then we
definitely have a moral obligation towards the weaker and
meeker. If it isn’t, what right do we have to decide who
shall live and who shall die (in pain)?
The increasingly shaky “fact” that species do not
interbreed “proves” that species are distinct, say some.
But who can deny that we share most of our genetic
material with the fly and the mouse? We are not as
dissimilar as we wish we were. And ever-escalating
cruelty towards other species will not establish our genetic
supremacy – merely our moral inferiority.
Just War or a Just War?
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
In an age of terrorism, guerilla and total warfare the
medieval doctrine of Just War needs to be re-defined.
Moreover, issues of legitimacy, efficacy and morality
should not be confused. Legitimacy is conferred by
institutions. Not all morally justified wars are, therefore,
automatically legitimate. Frequently the efficient
execution of a battle plan involves immoral or even illegal
acts.
As international law evolves beyond the ancient percepts
of sovereignty, it should incorporate new thinking about
pre-emptive strikes, human rights violations as casus belli
and the role and standing of international organizations,
insurgents and liberation movements.
Yet, inevitably, what constitutes “justice” depends heavily
on the cultural and societal contexts, narratives, mores,
and values of the disputants. Thus, one cannot answer the
deceivingly simple question: “Is this war a just war?” –
without first asking: “According to whom? In which
context? By which criteria? Based on what values? In
which period in history and where?”
Being members of Western Civilization, whether by
choice or by default, our understanding of what
constitutes a just war is crucially founded on our shifting
perceptions of the West.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
Imagine a village of 220 inhabitants. It has one heavily
armed police constable flanked by two lightly equipped
assistants. The hamlet is beset by a bunch of ruffians who
molest their own families and, at times, violently lash out
at their neighbors. These delinquents mock the authorities
and ignore their decisions and decrees.
Yet, the village council – the source of legitimacy – refuses
to authorize the constable to apprehend the villains and
dispose of them, by force of arms if need be. The elders
see no imminent or present danger to their charges and are
afraid of potential escalation whose evil outcomes could
far outweigh anything the felons can achieve.
Incensed by this laxity, the constable – backed only by
some of the inhabitants – breaks into the home of one of
the more egregious thugs and expels or kills him. He
claims to have acted preemptively and in self-defense, as
the criminal, long in defiance of the law, was planning to
attack its representatives.
Was the constable right in acting the way he did?
On the one hand, he may have saved lives and prevented a
conflagration whose consequences no one could predict.
On the other hand, by ignoring the edicts of the village
council and the expressed will of many of the denizens, he
has placed himself above the law, as its absolute
interpreter and enforcer.
What is the greater danger? Turning a blind eye to the
exploits of outlaws and outcasts, thus rendering them ever
more daring and insolent – or acting unilaterally to counter
such pariahs, thus undermining the communal legal
foundation and, possibly, leading to a chaotic situation of
“might is right”? In other words, when ethics and
expedience conflict with legality – which should
prevail?
Enter the medieval doctrine of “Just War” (justum bellum,
or, more precisely jus ad bellum), propounded by Saint
Augustine of Hippo (fifth century AD), Saint Thomas
Aquinas (1225-1274) in his “Summa Theologicae”,
Francisco de Vitoria (1548-1617), Francisco Suarez
(1548-1617), Hugo Grotius (1583-1645) in his influential
tome “Jure Belli ac Pacis” (“On Rights of War and
Peace”, 1625), Samuel Pufendorf (1632-1704), Christian
Wolff (1679-1754), and Emerich de Vattel (1714-1767).
Modern thinkers include Michael Walzer in “Just and
Unjust Wars” (1977), Barrie Paskins and Michael Dockrill
in “The Ethics of War” (1979), Richard Norman in
“Ethics, Killing, and War” (1995), Thomas Nagel in “War
and Massacre”, and Elizabeth Anscombe in “War and
Murder”.
According to the Catholic Church’s rendition of this
theory, set forth by Bishop Wilton D. Gregory of the
United States Conference of Catholic Bishops in his
Letter to President Bush on Iraq, dated September 13,
2002, going to war is justified if these conditions are met:
“The damage inflicted by the aggressor on the nation or
community of nations [is] lasting, grave, and certain; all
other means of putting an end to it must have been
shown to be impractical or ineffective; there must be
serious prospects of success; the use of arms must not
produce evils and disorders graver than the evil to be
eliminated.”
A just war is, therefore, a last resort, all other peaceful
conflict resolution options having been exhausted.
The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy sums up the
doctrine thus:
“The principles of the justice of war are commonly held to
be:
(1) Having just cause (especially and, according to the
United Nations Charter, exclusively, self-defense)
(2) Being (formally) declared by a proper authority
(3) Possessing a right intention
(4) Having a reasonable chance of success
(5) The end being proportional to the means used.”
Yet, the evolution of warfare – the invention of nuclear
weapons, the propagation of total war, the ubiquity of
guerrilla and national liberation movements, the
emergence of global, border-hopping terrorist
organizations, of totalitarian regimes, and rogue or failed
states – requires these principles to be modified by adding
these tenets:
(6) That the declaring authority is a lawfully and
democratically elected government
(7) That the declaration of war reflects the popular will
(Extension of 3) The right intention is to act in just cause.
(Extension of 4) … or a reasonable chance of avoiding an
annihilating defeat
(Extension of 5) That the outcomes of war are preferable
to the outcomes of the preservation of peace.
Still, the doctrine of just war, conceived in Europe in eras
past, is fraying at the edges. Rights and corresponding
duties are ill-defined or mismatched. What is legal is not
always moral and what is legitimate is not invariably
legal. Political realism and quasi-religious idealism sit
uncomfortably within the same conceptual framework.
Norms are vague and debatable while customary law is
only partially subsumed in the tradition (i.e., in treaties,
conventions and other instruments, as well in the actual
conduct of states).
The most contentious issue is, of course, what constitutes
“just cause”. Self-defense, in its narrowest sense (reaction
to direct and overwhelming armed aggression), is a
justified casus belli. But what about the use of force to
(deontologically, consequentially, or ethically):
(1) Prevent or ameliorate a slow-motion or permanent
humanitarian crisis
(2) Preempt a clear and present danger of aggression
(“anticipatory or preemptive self-defense” against what
Grotius called “immediate danger”)
(3) Secure a safe environment for urgent and
indispensable humanitarian relief operations
(4) Restore democracy in the attacked state (“regime
change”)
(5) Restore public order in the attacked state
(6) Prevent human rights violations or crimes against
humanity or violations of international law by the attacked
state
(7) Keep the peace (“peacekeeping operations”) and
enforce compliance with international or bilateral treaties
between the aggressor and the attacked state or the
attacked state and a third party
(8) Suppress armed infiltration, indirect aggression, or
civil strife aided and abetted by the attacked state
(9) Honor one’s obligations to frameworks and treaties of
collective self-defense
(10) Protect one’s citizens or the citizens of a third party
inside the attacked state
(11) Protect one’s property or assets owned by a third
party inside the attacked state
(12) Respond to an invitation by the authorities of the
attacked state – and with their expressed consent – to
militarily intervene within the territory of the attacked
state
(13) React to offenses against the nation’s honor or its
economy
Unless these issues are resolved and codified, the entire
edifice of international law – and, more specifically, the
law of war – is in danger of crumbling. The contemporary
multilateral regime proved inadequate and unable to
effectively tackle genocide (Rwanda, Bosnia), terror (in
Africa, Central Asia, and the Middle East), weapons of
mass destruction (Iraq, India, Israel, Pakistan, North
Korea), and tyranny (in dozens of members of the United
Nations).
This feebleness inevitably led to the resurgence of “might
is right” unilateralism, as practiced, for instance, by the
United States in places as diverse as Grenada and Iraq.
This pernicious and ominous phenomenon is coupled with
contempt towards and suspicion of international
organizations, treaties, institutions, undertakings, and the
prevailing consensual order.
In a unipolar world, reliant on a single superpower for its
security, the abrogation of the rules of the game could
lead to chaotic and lethal anarchy with a multitude of
“rebellions” against the emergent American Empire.
International law – the formalism of “natural law” – is only
one of many competing universalist and missionary value
systems. Militant Islam is another. The West must adopt
the former to counter the latter.
Cannibalism and Human Sacrifice
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
“I believe that when man evolves a civilization higher
than the mechanized but still primitive one he has now,
the eating of human flesh will be sanctioned. For then
man will have thrown off all of his superstitions and
irrational taboos.”
(Diego Rivera)
“One calls ‘barbarism’ whatever he is not accustomed
to.”
(Montaigne, On Cannibalism)
“Then Jesus said unto them, Verily, verily, I say unto
you, Except ye eat the flesh of the Son of man, and drink
his blood, ye have no life in you. Whoso eateth my flesh,
and drinketh my blood, hath eternal life; and I will raise
him up at the last day. For my flesh is meat indeed, and
my blood is drink indeed.”
(New Testament, John 6:53-55)
Cannibalism (more precisely, anthropophagy) is an age-
old tradition that, judging by a constant stream of
flabbergasted news reports, is far from extinct. Much-
debated indications exist that our Neanderthal, Proto-
Neolithic, and Neolithic (Stone Age) predecessors were
cannibals. Similarly contested claims were made with
regards to the 12th century advanced Anasazi culture in
the southwestern United States and the Minoans in Crete
(today’s Greece).
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
The Britannica Encyclopedia (2005 edition) recounts how
the “Binderwurs of central India ate their sick and aged
in the belief that the act was pleasing to their goddess,
Kali.” Cannibalism may also have been common among
followers of the Shaktism cults in India.
Other sources attribute cannibalism to the 16th century
Imbangala in today’s Angola and Congo, the Fang in
Cameroon, the Mangbetu in Central Africa, the Ache in
Paraguay, the Tonkawa in today’s Texas, the Calusa in
current day Florida, the Caddo and Iroquois confederacies
of Indians in North America, the Cree in Canada, the
Witoto, natives of Colombia and Peru, the Carib in the
Lesser Antilles (whose distorted name – Canib – gave rise
to the word “cannibalism”), to Maori tribes in today’s New
Zealand, and to various peoples in Sumatra (like the
Batak).
The Wikipedia numbers among the practitioners of
cannibalism the ancient Chinese, the Korowai tribe of
southeastern Papua, the Fore tribe in New Guinea (and
many other tribes in Melanesia), the Aztecs, the people of
Yucatan, the Purchas from Popayan, Colombia, the
denizens of the Marquesas Islands of Polynesia, and the
natives of the captaincy of Sergipe in Brazil.
From Congo and Central Africa to Germany and from
Mexico to New Zealand, cannibalism is enjoying a
morbid revival of interest, if not of practice. A veritable
torrent of sensational tomes and movies adds to our
ambivalent fascination with man-eaters.
Cannibalism is not a monolithic affair. It can be divided
thus:
I. Non-consensual consumption of human flesh post-
mortem
For example, when the corpses of prisoners of war are
devoured by their captors. This used to be a common
exercise among island tribes (e.g., in Fiji, the Andaman
and Cook islands) and is still the case in godforsaken
battle zones such as Congo (formerly Zaire), or among the
defeated Japanese soldiers in World War II.
Similarly, human organs and fetuses as well as mummies
are still being gobbled up – mainly in Africa and Asia – for
remedial and medicinal purposes and in order to enhance
one’s libido and vigor.
On numerous occasions the organs of dead companions,
colleagues, family, or neighbors were reluctantly ingested
by isolated survivors of horrid accidents (the Uruguay
rugby team whose plane crashed in the Andes, the boat
people fleeing Asia), denizens of besieged cities (e.g.,
during the siege of Leningrad), members of exploratory
expeditions gone astray (the Donner Party in Sierra
Nevada, California and John Franklin’s Polar expedition),
famine-stricken populations (Ukraine in the 1930s, China
in the 1960s), and the like.
Finally, in various pre-nation-state and tribal societies,
members of the family were encouraged to eat specific
parts of their dead relatives as a sign of respect or in order
to partake of the deceased’s wisdom, courage, or other
positive traits (endocannibalism).
II. Non-consensual consumption of human flesh from a
live source
For example, when prisoners of war are butchered for the
express purpose of being eaten by their victorious
enemies.
A notorious and rare representative of this category of
cannibalism is the punitive ritual of being eaten alive. The
kings of the tribes of the Cook Islands were thought to
embody the gods. They punished dissent by dissecting
their screaming and conscious adversaries and consuming
their flesh piecemeal, eyeballs first.
The Sawney Bean family in Scotland, during the reign of
King James I, survived for decades on the remains (and
personal belongings) of victims of their murderous sprees.
Real-life serial killers, like Jeffrey Dahmer, Albert Fish,
Sascha Spesiwtsew, Fritz Haarmann, Issei Sagawa, and
Ed Gein, lured, abducted, and massacred countless people
and then consumed their flesh and preserved the inedible
parts as trophies. These lurid deeds inspired a slew of
books and films, most notably The Silence of the Lambs
with Hannibal (Lecter) the Cannibal as its protagonist.
III. Consensual consumption of human flesh from live
and dead human bodies
Armin Meiwes, the “Master Butcher (Der
Metzgermeister)”, arranged over the Internet to meet
Bernd Jurgen Brandes on March 2001. Meiwes amputated
the penis of his guest and they both ate it. He then
proceeded to kill Brandes (with the latter’s consent
recorded on video), and snack on what remained of him.
Sexual cannibalism is a paraphilia and an extreme – and
thankfully, rare – form of fetishism.
http://samvak.tripod.com/serialkillers.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/factoidg.html
The Aztecs willingly volunteered to serve as human
sacrifices (and to be tucked into afterwards). They firmly
believed that they were offerings, chosen by the gods
themselves, thus being rendered immortal.
Dutiful sons and daughters in China made their amputated
organs and sliced tissues (mainly the liver) available to
their sick parents (practices known as Ko Ku and Ko
Kan). Such donation were considered remedial. Princess
Miao Chuang who surrendered her severed hands to her
ailing father was henceforth deified.
Non-consensual cannibalism is murder, pure and simple.
The attendant act of cannibalism, though aesthetically and
ethically reprehensible, cannot aggravate this supreme
assault on all that we hold sacred.
But consensual cannibalism is a lot trickier. Modern
medicine, for instance, has blurred the already thin line
between right and wrong.
What is the ethical difference between consensual, post-
mortem, organ harvesting and consensual, post-mortem
cannibalism?
Why is stem cell harvesting (from aborted fetuses)
morally superior to consensual post-mortem cannibalism?
When members of a plane-wrecked rugby team, stranded
on an inaccessible, snow-piled, mountain range resort to
eating each other in order to survive, we turn a blind eye
to their repeated acts of cannibalism – but we condemn the
very same deed in the harshest terms if it takes place
between two consenting, and even eager adults in
Germany. Surely, we don’t treat murder, pedophilia, and
incest the same way!
As the Auxiliary Bishop of Montevideo said after the
crash:
“… Eating someone who has died in order to survive is
incorporating their substance, and it is quite possible to
compare this with a graft. Flesh survives when
assimilated by someone in extreme need, just as it does
when an eye or heart of a dead man is grafted onto a
living man…”
(Read, P.P. 1974. Alive. Avon, New York)
Complex ethical issues are involved in the apparently
straightforward practice of consensual cannibalism.
Consensual, in vivo, cannibalism (a-la Messrs. Meiwes
and Brandes) resembles suicide. The cannibal is merely
the instrument of voluntary self-destruction. Why would
we treat it different to the way we treat any other form of
suicide pact?
Consensual cannibalism is not the equivalent of drug
abuse because it has no social costs. Unlike junkies, the
cannibal and his meal are unlikely to harm others. What
gives society the right to intervene, therefore?
If we own our bodies and, thus, have the right to smoke,
drink, have an abortion, commit suicide, and will our
organs to science after we die – why don’t we possess the
inalienable right to will our delectable tissues to a
discerning cannibal post-mortem (or to victims of famine
in Africa)?
When does our right to dispose of our organs in any way
we see fit crystallize? Is it when we die? Or after we are
dead? If so, what is the meaning and legal validity of a
living will? And why can’t we make a living will and
bequeath our cadaverous selves to the nearest cannibal?
Do dead people have rights and can they claim and invoke
them while they are still alive? Is the live person the same
as his dead body, does he “own” it, does the state have
any rights in it? Does the corpse stll retain its previous
occupant’s “personhood”? Are cadavers still human, in
any sense of the word?
We find all three culinary variants abhorrent. Yet, this
instinctive repulsion is a curious matter. The onerous
demands of survival should have encouraged cannibalism
rather than make it a taboo. Human flesh is protein-rich.
Most societies, past and present (with the exception of the
industrialized West), need to make efficient use of rare
protein-intensive resources.
If cannibalism enhances the chances of survival – why is it
universally prohibited? For many a reason.
I. The Sanctity of Life
Historically, cannibalism preceded, followed, or
precipitated an act of murder or extreme deprivation (such
as torture). It habitually clashed with the principle of the
sanctity of life. Once allowed, even under the strictest
guidelines, cannibalism tended to debase and devalue
human life and foster homicide, propelling its
practitioners down a slippery ethical slope towards
bloodlust and orgiastic massacres.
http://samvak.tripod.com/death.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/human.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/torturepsychology.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html
II. The Afterlife
Moreover, in life, the human body and form are
considered by most religions (and philosophers) to be the
abode of the soul, the divine spark that animates us all.
The post-mortem integrity of this shrine is widely thought
to guarantee a faster, unhindered access to the afterlife, to
immortality, and eventual reincarnation (or karmic cycle
in eastern religions).
For this reason, to this very day, orthodox Jews refuse to
subject their relatives to a post-mortem autopsy and organ
harvesting. Fijians and Cook Islanders used to consume
their enemies’ carcasses in order to prevent their souls
from joining hostile ancestors in heaven.
III. Chastening Reminders
Cannibalism is a chilling reminder of our humble origins
in the animal kingdom. To the cannibal, we are no better
and no more than cattle or sheep. Cannibalism confronts
us with the irreversibility of our death and its finality.
Surely, we cannot survive our demise with our cadaver
mutilated and gutted and our skeletal bones scattered,
gnawed, and chewed on?
IV. Medical Reasons
Infrequently, cannibalism results in prion diseases of the
nervous system, such as kuru. The same paternalism that
gave rise to the banning of drug abuse, the outlawing of
suicide, and the Prohibition of alcoholic drinks in the
1920s – seeks to shelter us from the pernicious medical
outcomes of cannibalism and to protect others who might
become our victims.
http://samvak.tripod.com/animal.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/factoidpq.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/suicide.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/factoidpq.html
V. The Fear of Being Objectified
Being treated as an object (being objectified) is the most
torturous form of abuse. People go to great lengths to seek
empathy and to be perceived by others as three
dimensional entities with emotions, needs, priorities,
wishes, and preferences.
The cannibal reduces others by treating them as so much
meat. Many cannibal serial killers transformed the organs
of their victims into trophies. The Cook Islanders sought
to humiliate their enemies by eating, digesting, and then
defecating them – having absorbed their mana (prowess,
life force) in the process.
VI. The Argument from Nature
Cannibalism is often castigated as “unnatural”. Animals,
goes the myth, don’t prey on their own kind.
Alas, like so many other romantic lores, this is untrue.
Most species – including our closest relatives, the
chimpanzees – do cannibalize. Cannibalism in nature is
widespread and serves diverse purposes such as
population control (chickens, salamanders, toads), food
and protein security in conditions of scarcity
(hippopotamuses, scorpions, certain types of dinosaurs),
threat avoidance (rabbits, mice, rats, and hamsters), and
the propagation of genetic material through exclusive
mating (Red-back spider and many mantids).
Moreover, humans are a part of nature. Our deeds and
misdeeds are natural by definition. Seeking to tame nature
is a natural act. Seeking to establish hierarchies and
subdue or relinquish our enemies are natural propensities.
http://samvak.tripod.com/abuse.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/empathy.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/serialkillers.html
By avoiding cannibalism we seek to transcend nature.
Refraining from cannibalism is the unnatural act.
VIII. The Argument from Progress
It is a circular syllogism involving a tautology and goes
like this:
Cannibalism is barbaric. Cannibals are, therefore,
barbarians. Progress entails the abolition of this practice.
The premises – both explicit and implicit – are axiomatic
and, therefore, shaky. What makes cannibalism barbarian?
And why is progress a desirable outcome? There is a
prescriptive fallacy involved, as well:
Because we do not eat the bodies of dead people – we
ought not to eat them.
VIII. Arguments from Religious Ethics
The major monotheistic religions are curiously mute when
it comes to cannibalism. Human sacrifice is denounced
numerous times in the Old Testament – but man-eating
goes virtually unmentioned. The Eucharist in Christianity
– when the believers consume the actual body and blood
of Jesus – is an act of undisguised cannibalism:
“That the consequence of Transubstantiation, as a
conversion of the total substance, is the transition of the
entire substance of the bread and wine into the Body and
Blood of Christ, is the express doctrine of the Church
….”
(Catholic Encyclopedia)
“CANON lI.-If any one saith, that, in the sacred and
holy sacrament of the Eucharist, the substance of the
bread and wine remains conjointly with the body and
blood of our Lord Jesus Christ, and denieth that
wonderful and singular conversion of the whole
substance of the bread into the Body, and of the whole
substance of the wine into the Blood-the species Only of
the bread and wine remaining-which conversion indeed
the Catholic Church most aptly calls
Transubstantiation; let him be anathema.
CANON VIII.-lf any one saith, that Christ, given in the
Eucharist, is eaten spiritually only, and not also
sacramentally and really; let him be anathema.”
(The Council of Trent, The Thirteenth Session – The
canons and decrees of the sacred and oecumenical
Council of Trent, Ed. and trans. J. Waterworth
(London: Dolman, 1848), 75-91.)
Still, most systems of morality and ethics impute to Man a
privileged position in the scheme of things (having been
created in the “image of God”). Men and women are
supposed to transcend their animal roots and inhibit their
baser instincts (an idea incorporated into Freud’s tripartite
model of the human psyche). The anthropocentric
chauvinistic view is that it is permissible to kill all other
animals in order to consume their flesh. Man, in this
respect, is sui generis.
Yet, it is impossible to rigorously derive a prohibition to
eat human flesh from any known moral system. As
Richard Routley-Silvan observes in his essay “In Defence
of Cannibalism”, that something is innately repugnant
does not make it morally prohibited. Moreover, that we
http://samvak.tripod.com/psychoanalysis.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/psychoanalysis.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/psychoanalysis.html
find cannibalism nauseating is probably the outcome of
upbringing and conditioning rather than anything innate.
Euthanasia and the Right to Die
By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
I. Definitions of Types of Euthanasia
Euthanasia is often erroneously described as “mercy
killing”. Most forms of euthanasia are, indeed, motivated
by (some say: misplaced) mercy. Not so others. In Greek,
“eu” means both “well” and “easy” and “Thanatos” is
death.
Euthanasia is the intentional premature termination of
another person’s life either by direct intervention (active
euthanasia) or by withholding life-prolonging measures
and resources (passive euthanasia), either at the express
or implied request of that person (voluntary euthanasia),
or in the absence of such approval (non-voluntary
euthanasia). Involuntary euthanasia – where the
individual wishes to go on living – is an euphemism for
murder.
To my mind, passive euthanasia is immoral. The abrupt
withdrawal of medical treatment, feeding, and hydration
results in a slow and (potentially) torturous death. It took
Terri Schiavo 13 days to die, when her tubes were
withdrawn in the last two weeks of March 2005. It is
morally wrong to subject even animals to such gratuitous
suffering. Moreover, passive euthanasia allows us to
evade personal responsibility for the patient’s death. In
active euthanasia, the relationship between the act (of
administering a lethal medication, for instance) and its
consequences is direct and unambiguous.
http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html
As the philosopher John Finnis notes, to qualify as
euthanasia, the termination of life has to be the main and
intended aim of the act or omission that lead to it. If the
loss of life is incidental (a side effect), the agent is still
morally responsible but to describe his actions and
omissions as euthanasia would be misleading.
Volntariness (accepting the foreseen but unintended
consequences of one’s actions and omissions) should be
distinguished from intention.
Still, this sophistry obscures the main issue:
If the sanctity of life is a supreme and overriding value
(“basic good”), it ought to surely preclude and proscribe
all acts and omissions which may shorten it, even when
the shortening of life is a mere deleterious side effect.
But this is not the case. The sanctity and value of life
compete with a host of other equally potent moral
demands. Even the most devout pro-life ethicist accepts
that certain medical decisions – for instance, to administer
strong analgesics – inevitably truncate the patient’s life.
Yet, this is considered moral because the resulting
euthanasia is not the main intention of the pain-relieving
doctor.
Moreover, the apparent dilemma between the two values
(reduce suffering or preserve life) is non-existent.
There are four possible situations. Imagine a patient
writhing with insufferable pain.
1. The patient’s life is not at risk if she is not medicated
with painkillers (she risks dying if she is medicated)
2. The patient’s life is not at risk either way, medicated or
not
3. The patient’s life is at risk either way, medicated or not
4. The patient’s life is at risk if she is not medicated with
painkillers
In all four cases, the decisions our doctor has to make are
ethically clear cut. He should administer pain-alleviating
drugs, except when the patient risks dying (in 1 above).
The (possible) shortening of the patient’s life (which is
guesswork, at best) is immaterial.
II. Who is or Should Be Subject to Euthanasia? The
Problem of Dualism vs. Reductionism
With the exception of radical animal rights activists, most
philosophers and laymen consider people – human beings
– to be entitled to “special treatment”, to be in possession
of unique rights (and commensurate obligations), and to
be capable of feats unparalleled in other species.
Thus, opponents of euthanasia universally oppose the
killing of “persons”. As the (pro-euthanasia) philosopher
John Harris puts it:
” … concern for their welfare, respect for their wishes,
respect for the intrinsic value of their lives and respect
for their interests.”
Ronald Dworkin emphasizes the investments – made by
nature, the person involved, and others – which euthanasia
wastes. But he also draws attention to the person’s “critical
interests” – the interests whose satisfaction makes life
http://samvak.tripod.com/animal.html
better to live. The manner of one’s own death may be such
a critical interest. Hence, one should have the right to
choose how one dies because the “right kind” of death
(e.g., painless, quick, dignified) reflects on one’s entire
life, affirms and improves it.
But who is a person? What makes us human? Many
things, most of which are irrelevant to our discussion.
Broadly speaking, though, there are two schools of
thought:
(i) That we are rendered human by the very event of our
conception (egg meets sperm), or, at the latest, our birth;
or
(ii) That we are considered human only when we act and
think as conscious humans do.
The proponents of the first case (i) claim that merely
possessing a human body (or the potential to come to
possess such a body) is enough to qualify us as “persons”.
There is no distinction between mind and abode – thought,
feelings, and actions are merely manifestations of one
underlying unity. The fact that some of these
manifestations have yet to materialize (in the case of an
embryo) or are mere potentials (in the case of a comatose
patient) does not detract from our essential,
incontrovertible, and indivisible humanity. We may be
immature or damaged persons – but we are persons all the
same (and always will be persons).
Though considered “religious” and “spiritual”, this notion
is actually a form of reductionism. The mind, “soul”, and
http://samvak.tripod.com/human.html
“spirit” are mere expressions of one unity, grounded in
our “hardware” – in our bodies.
Those who argue the second case (ii) postulate that it is
possible to have a human body which does not host a
person. People in Persistent Vegetative States, for instance
– or fetuses, for that matter – are human but also non-
persons. This is because they do not yet – or are unable to
– exercise their faculties. Personhood is complexity. When
the latter ceases, so does the former. Personhood is
acquired and is an extensive parameter, a total, defining
state of being. One is either awake or asleep, either dead
or alive, either in a state of personhood or not
The latter approach involves fine distinctions between
potential, capacity, and skill. A human body (or fertilized
egg) have the potential to think, write poetry, feel pain,
and value life. At the right phase of somatic development,
this potential becomes capacity and, once it is
competently exercised – it is a skill.
Embryos and comatose people may have the potential to
do and think – but, in the absence of capacities and skills,
they are not full-fledged persons. Indeed, in all important
respects, they are already dead.
Taken to its logical conclusion, this definition of a person
also excludes newborn infants, the severely retarded, the
hopelessly quadriplegic, and the catatonic. “Who is a
person” becomes a matter of culturally-bound and
medically-informed judgment which may be influenced
by both ignorance and fashion and, thus, be arbitrary and
immoral.
Imagine a computer infected by a computer virus which
cannot be quarantined, deleted, or fixed. The virus
disables the host and renders it “dead”. Is it still a
computer? If someone broke into my house and stole it,
can I file an insurance claim? If a colleague destroys it,
can I sue her for the damages? The answer is yes. A
computer is a computer for as long as it exists physically
and a cure is bound to be found even against the most
trenchant virus.
The definition of personhood must rely on objective,
determinate and determinable criteria. The anti-euthanasia
camp relies on bodily existence as one such criterion. The
pro-euthanasia faction has yet to reciprocate.
III. Euthanasia and Suicide
Self-sacrifice, avoidable martyrdom, engaging in life
risking activities, refusal to prolong one’s life through
medical treatment, euthanasia, overdosing, and self-
destruction that is the result of coercion – are all closely
related to suicide. They all involve a deliberately self-
inflicted death.
But while suicide is chiefly intended to terminate a life –
the other acts are aimed at perpetuating, strengthening,
and defending values or other people. Many – not only
religious people – are appalled by the choice implied in
suicide – of death over life. They feel that it demeans life
and abnegates its meaning.
Life’s meaning – the outcome of active selection by the
individual – is either external (such as “God’s plan”) or
internal, the outcome of an arbitrary frame of reference,
such as having a career goal. Our life is rendered
meaningful only by integrating into an eternal thing,
process, design, or being. Suicide makes life trivial
because the act is not natural – not part of the eternal
framework, the undying process, the timeless cycle of
birth and death. Suicide is a break with eternity.
Henry Sidgwick said that only conscious (i.e., intelligent)
beings can appreciate values and meanings. So, life is
significant to conscious, intelligent, though finite, beings –
because it is a part of some eternal goal, plan, process,
thing, design, or being. Suicide flies in the face of
Sidgwick’s dictum. It is a statement by an intelligent and
conscious being about the meaninglessness of life.
If suicide is a statement, than society, in this case, is
against the freedom of expression. In the case of suicide,
free speech dissonantly clashes with the sanctity of a
meaningful life. To rid itself of the anxiety brought on by
this conflict, society cast suicide as a depraved or even
criminal act and its perpetrators are much castigated.
The suicide violates not only the social contract but, many
will add, covenants with God or nature. St. Thomas
Aquinas wrote in the “Summa Theologiae” that – since
organisms strive to survive – suicide is an unnatural act.
Moreover, it adversely affects the community and violates
the property rights of God, the imputed owner of one’s
spirit. Christianity regards the immortal soul as a gift and,
in Jewish writings, it is a deposit. Suicide amounts to the
abuse or misuse of God’s possessions, temporarily lodged
in a corporeal mansion.
This paternalism was propagated, centuries later, by Sir
William Blackstone, the codifier of British Law. Suicide –
being self-murder – is a grave felony, which the state has a
right to prevent and to punish for. In certain countries this
still is the case. In Israel, for instance, a soldier is
considered to be “military property” and an attempted
suicide is severely punished as “the corruption of an army
chattel”.
Paternalism, a malignant mutation of benevolence, is
about objectifying people and treating them as
possessions. Even fully-informed and consenting adults
are not granted full, unmitigated autonomy, freedom, and
privacy. This tends to breed “victimless crimes”. The
“culprits” – gamblers, homosexuals, communists, suicides,
drug addicts, alcoholics, prostitutes – are “protected from
themselves” by an intrusive nanny state.
The possession of a right by a person imposes on others a
corresponding obligation not to act to frustrate its
exercise. Suicide is often the choice of a mentally and
legally competent adult. Life is such a basic and deep set
phenomenon that even the incompetents – the mentally
retarded or mentally insane or minors – can fully gauge its
significance and make “informed” decisions, in my view.
The paternalists claim counterfactually that no competent
adult “in his right mind” will ever decide to commit
suicide. They cite the cases of suicides who survived and
felt very happy that they have – as a compelling reason to
intervene. But we all make irreversible decisions for
which, sometimes, we are sorry. It gives no one the right
to interfere.
Paternalism is a slippery slope. Should the state be
allowed to prevent the birth of a genetically defective
child or forbid his parents to marry in the first place?
Should unhealthy adults be forced to abstain from
smoking, or steer clear from alcohol? Should they be
coerced to exercise?
Suicide is subject to a double moral standard. People are
permitted – nay, encouraged – to sacrifice their life only in
certain, socially sanctioned, ways. To die on the
battlefield or in defense of one’s religion is commendable.
This hypocrisy reveals how power structures – the state,
institutional religion, political parties, national movements
– aim to monopolize the lives of citizens and adherents to
do with as they see fit. Suicide threatens this monopoly.
Hence the taboo.
Does one have a right to take one’s life?
The answer is: it depends. Certain cultures and societies
encourage suicide. Both Japanese kamikaze and Jewish
martyrs were extolled for their suicidal actions. Certain
professions are knowingly life-threatening – soldiers,
firemen, policemen. Certain industries – like the
manufacture of armaments, cigarettes, and alcohol – boost
overall mortality rates.
In general, suicide is commended when it serves social
ends, enhances the cohesion of the group, upholds its
values, multiplies its wealth, or defends it from external
and internal threats. Social structures and human
collectives – empires, countries, firms, bands, institutions –
often commit suicide. This is considered to be a healthy
process.
More about suicide, the meaning of life, and related
considerations – HERE.
Back to our central dilemma:
http://samvak.tripod.com/suicide.html
Is it morally justified to commit suicide in order to avoid
certain, forthcoming, unavoidable, and unrelenting torture,
pain, or coma?
Is it morally justified to ask others to help you to commit
suicide (for instance, if you are incapacitated)?
Imagine a society that venerates life-with-dignity by
making euthanasia mandatory – would it then and there be
morally justified to refuse to commit suicide or to help in
it?
IV. Euthanasia and Murder
Imagine killing someone before we have ascertained her
preferences as to the manner of her death and whether she
wants to die at all. This constitutes murder even if, after
the fact, we can prove conclusively that the victim wanted
to die.
Is murder, therefore, merely the act of taking life,
regardless of circumstances – or is it the nature of the
interpersonal interaction that counts? If the latter, the
victim’s will counts – if the former, it is irrelevant.
V. Euthanasia, the Value of Life, and the Right to Life
Few philosophers, legislators, and laymen support non-
voluntary or involuntary euthanasia. These types of
“mercy” killing are associated with the most heinous
crimes against humanity committed by the Nazi regime on
both its own people and other nations. They are and were
also an integral part of every program of active eugenics.
http://samvak.tripod.com/eugenics.html
The arguments against killing someone who hasn’t
expressed a wish to die (let alone someone who has
expressed a desire to go on living) revolve around the
right to life. People are assumed to value their life, cherish
it, and protect it. Euthanasia – especially the non-voluntary
forms – amounts to depriving someone (as well as their
nearest and dearest) of something they value.
The right to life – at least as far as human beings are
concerned – is a rarely questioned fundamental moral
principle. In Western cultures, it is assumed to be
inalienable and indivisible (i.e., monolithic). Yet, it is
neither. Even if we accept the axiomatic – and therefore
arbitrary – source of this right, we are still faced with
intractable dilemmas. All said, the right to life may be
nothing more than a cultural construct, dependent on
social mores, historical contexts, and exegetic systems.
Rights – whether moral or legal – impose obligations or
duties on third parties towards the right-holder. One has a
right AGAINST other people and thus can prescribe to
them certain obligatory behaviors and proscribe certain
acts or omissions. Rights and duties are two sides of the
same Janus-like ethical coin.
This duality confuses people. They often erroneously
identify rights with their attendant duties or obligations,
with the morally decent, or even with the morally
permissible. One’s rights inform other people how they
MUST behave towards one – not how they SHOULD or
OUGHT to act morally. Moral behavior is not dependent
on the existence of a right. Obligations are.
To complicate matters further, many apparently simple
and straightforward rights are amalgams of more basic
moral or legal principles. To treat such rights as unities is
to mistreat them.
Take the right to life. It is a compendium of no less than
eight distinct rights: the right to be brought to life, the
right to be born, the right to have one’s life maintained,
the right not to be killed, the right to have one’s life
saved, the right to save one’s life (wrongly reduced to the
right to self-defence), the right to terminate one’s life, and
the right to have one’s life terminated.
None of these rights is self-evident, or unambiguous, or
universal, or immutable, or automatically applicable. It is
safe to say, therefore, that these rights are not primary as
hitherto believed – but derivative.
Go HERE to learn more about the Right to Life.
Of the eight strands comprising the right to life, we are
concerned with a mere two.
The Right to Have One’s Life Maintained
This leads to a more general quandary. To what extent can
one use other people’s bodies, their property, their time,
their resources and to deprive them of pleasure, comfort,
material possessions, income, or any other thing – in order
to maintain one’s life?
Even if it were possible in reality, it is indefensible to
maintain that I have a right to sustain, improve, or prolong
my life at another’s expense. I cannot demand – though I
can morally expect – even a trivial and minimal sacrifice
from another in order to prolong my life. I have no right to
do so.
http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html
Of course, the existence of an implicit, let alone explicit,
contract between myself and another party would change
the picture. The right to demand sacrifices commensurate
with the provisions of the contract would then crystallize
and create corresponding duties and obligations.
No embryo has a right to sustain its life, maintain, or
prolong it at its mother’s expense. This is true regardless
of how insignificant the sacrifice required of her is.
Yet, by knowingly and intentionally conceiving the
embryo, the mother can be said to have signed a contract
with it. The contract causes the right of the embryo to
demand such sacrifices from his mother to crystallize. It
also creates corresponding duties and obligations of the
mother towards her embryo.
We often find ourselves in a situation where we do not
have a given right against other individuals – but we do
possess this very same right against society. Society owes
us what no constituent-individual does.
Thus, we all have a right to sustain our lives, maintain,
prolong, or even improve them at society’s expense – no
matter how major and significant the resources required.
Public hospitals, state pension schemes, and police forces
may be needed in order to fulfill society’s obligations to
prolong, maintain, and improve our lives – but fulfill them
it must.
Still, each one of us can sign a contract with society –
implicitly or explicitly – and abrogate this right. One can
volunteer to join the army. Such an act constitutes a
contract in which the individual assumes the duty or
obligation to give up his or her life.
The Right not to be Killed
It is commonly agreed that every person has the right not
to be killed unjustly. Admittedly, what is just and what is
unjust is determined by an ethical calculus or a social
contract – both constantly in flux.
Still, even if we assume an Archimedean immutable point
of moral reference – does A’s right not to be killed mean
that third parties are to refrain from enforcing the rights of
other people against A? What if the only way to right
wrongs committed by A against others – was to kill A?
The moral obligation to right wrongs is about restoring the
rights of the wronged.
If the continued existence of A is predicated on the
repeated and continuous violation of the rights of others –
and these other people object to it – then A must be killed
if that is the only way to right the wrong and re-assert the
rights of A’s victims.
The Right to have One’s Life Saved
There is no such right because there is no moral obligation
or duty to save a life. That people believe otherwise
demonstrates the muddle between the morally
commendable, desirable, and decent (“ought”, “should”)
and the morally obligatory, the result of other people’s
rights (“must”). In some countries, the obligation to save a
life is codified in the law of the land. But legal rights and
obligations do not always correspond to moral rights and
obligations, or give rise to them.
VI. Euthanasia and Personal Autonomy
The right to have one’s life terminated at will (euthanasia),
is subject to social, ethical, and legal strictures. In some
countries – such as the Netherlands – it is legal (and
socially acceptable) to have one’s life terminated with the
help of third parties given a sufficient deterioration in the
quality of life and given the imminence of death. One has
to be of sound mind and will one’s death knowingly,
intentionally, repeatedly, and forcefully.
Should we have a right to die (given hopeless medical
circumstances)? When our wish to end it all conflicts with
society’s (admittedly, paternalistic) judgment of what is
right and what is good for us and for others – what should
prevail?
One the one hand, as Patrick Henry put it, “give me
liberty or give me death”. A life without personal
autonomy and without the freedom to make unpopular
and non-conformist decisions is, arguably, not worth
living at all!
As Dworkin states:
“Making someone die in a way that others approve, but
he believes a horrifying contradiction of his life, is a
devastating, odious form of tyranny”.
Still, even the victim’s express wishes may prove to be
transient and circumstantial (due to depression,
misinformation, or clouded judgment). Can we regard
them as immutable and invariable? Moreover, what if the
circumstances prove everyone – the victim included –
wrong? What if a cure to the victim’s disease is found ten
minutes after the euthanasia?
VII. Euthanasia and Society
It is commonly accepted that where two equally potent
values clash, society steps in as an arbiter. The right to
material welfare (food, shelter, basic possessions) often
conflicts with the right to own private property and to
benefit from it. Society strikes a fine balance by, on the
one hand, taking from the rich and giving to the poor
(through redistributive taxation) and, on the other hand,
prohibiting and punishing theft and looting.
Euthanasia involves a few such finely-balanced values:
the sanctity of life vs. personal autonomy, the welfare of
the many vs. the welfare of the individual, the relief of
pain vs. the prolongation and preservation of life.
Why can’t society step in as arbiter in these cases as well?
Moreover, what if a person is rendered incapable of
expressing his preferences with regards to the manner and
timing of his death – should society step in (through the
agency of his family or through the courts or legislature)
and make the decision for him?
In a variety of legal situations, parents, court-appointed
guardians, custodians, and conservators act for, on behalf
of, and in lieu of underage children, the physically and
mentally challenged and the disabled. Why not here?
We must distinguish between four situations:
1. The patient foresaw the circumstances and provided an
advance directive, asking explicitly for his life to be
terminated when certain conditions are met.
2. The patient did not provide an advanced directive but
expressed his preference clearly before he was
incapacitated. The risk here is that self-interested family
members may lie.
3. The patient did not provide an advance directive and
did not express his preference aloud – but the decision to
terminate his life is commensurate with both his character
and with other decisions he made.
4. There is no indication, however indirect, that the patient
wishes or would have wished to die had he been capable
of expression but the patient is no longer a “person” and,
therefore, has no interests to respect, observe, and protect.
Moreover, the patient is a burden to himself, to his nearest
and dearest, and to society at large. Euthanasia is the right,
just, and most efficient thing to do.
Society can legalize euthanasia in the first case and,
subject to rigorous fact checking, in the second and third
cases. To prevent economically-motivated murder
disguised as euthanasia, non-voluntary and involuntary
euthanasia (as set in the forth case above) should be
banned outright.
VIII. Slippery Slope Arguments
Issues in the Calculus of Rights – The Hierarchy of
Rights
The right to life supersedes – in Western moral and legal
systems – all other rights. It overrules the right to one’s
body, to comfort, to the avoidance of pain, or to
ownership of property. Given such lack of equivocation,
the amount of dilemmas and controversies surrounding
the right to life is, therefore, surprising.
When there is a clash between equally potent rights – for
instance, the conflicting rights to life of two people – we
can decide among them randomly (by flipping a coin, or
casting dice). Alternatively, we can add and subtract
rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic.
Thus, if the continued life of an embryo or a fetus
threatens the mother’s life – that is, assuming,
controversially, that both of them have an equal right to
life – we can decide to kill the fetus. By adding to the
mother’s right to life her right to her own body we
outweigh the fetus’ right to life.
The Difference between Killing and Letting Die
Counterintuitively, there is a moral gulf between killing
(taking a life) and letting die (not saving a life). The right
not to be killed is undisputed. There is no right to have
one’s own life saved. Where there is a right – and only
where there is one – there is an obligation. Thus, while
there is an obligation not to kill – there is no obligation to
save a life.
Anti-euthanasia ethicists fear that allowing one kind of
euthanasia – even under the strictest and explicit
conditions – will open the floodgates. The value of life
will be depreciated and made subordinate to
considerations of economic efficacy and personal
convenience. Murders, disguised as acts of euthanasia,
will proliferate and none of us will be safe once we reach
old age or become disabled.
Years of legally-sanctioned euthanasia in the Netherlands,
parts of Australia, and a state or two in the United States
tend to fly in the face of such fears. Doctors did not regard
these shifts in public opinion and legislative climate as a
blanket license to kill their charges. Family members
proved to be far less bloodthirsty and avaricious than
feared.
As long as non-voluntary and involuntary types of
euthanasia are treated as felonies, it seems safe to allow
patients to exercise their personal autonomy and grant
them the right to die. Legalizing the institution of
“advance directive” will go a long way towards regulating
the field – as would a new code of medical ethics that will
recognize and embrace reality: doctors, patients, and
family members collude in their millions to commit
numerous acts and omissions of euthanasia every day. It is
their way of restoring dignity to the shattered lives and
bodies of loved ones.
T H E A U T H O R
SHMUEL (SAM) VAKNIN
Curriculum Vitae
Click on blue text to access relevant web sites – thank you.
Born in 1961 in Qiryat-Yam, Israel.
Served in the Israeli Defence Force (1979-1982) in
training and education units.
Education
Graduated a few semesters in the Technion – Israel
Institute of Technology, Haifa.
Ph.D. in Philosophy (major: Philosophy of Physics) –
Pacific Western University, California, USA.
My doctoral thesis and other books are available through
the Library of Congress.
Graduate of numerous courses in Finance Theory and
International Trading.
Certified E-Commerce Concepts Analyst by Brainbench.
Certified in Psychological Counselling Techniques by
Brainbench.
http://philosophos.tripod.com/loc.html
http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/transcript/public/viewtranscript.xml?pid=781937
http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/business/aboutbrainbench.xml
http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/transcript/public/transcript_testdetails.xml?back=1&pid=781937&testid=6149637
http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/business/aboutbrainbench.xml
Certified Financial Analyst by Brainbench.
Full proficiency in Hebrew and in English.
Business Experience
1980 to 1983
Founder and co-owner of a chain of computerised
information kiosks in Tel-Aviv, Israel.
1982 to 1985
Senior positions with the Nessim D. Gaon Group of
Companies in Geneva, Paris and New-York (NOGA and
APROFIM SA):
– Chief Analyst of Edible Commodities in the Group’s
Headquarters in Switzerland
– Manager of the Research and Analysis Division
– Manager of the Data Processing Division
– Project Manager of the Nigerian Computerised Census
– Vice President in charge of RND and Advanced
Technologies
– Vice President in charge of Sovereign Debt Financing
1985 to 1986
Represented Canadian Venture Capital Funds in Israel.
1986 to 1987
General Manager of IPE Ltd. in London. The firm
financed international multi-lateral countertrade and
leasing transactions.
http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/transcript/public/viewtranscript.xml?pid=781937
http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/business/aboutbrainbench.xml
1988 to
1990
Co-founder and Director of “Mikbats-Tesuah”, a portfolio
management firm based in Tel-Aviv.
Activities included large-scale portfolio management,
underwriting, forex trading and general financial advisory
services.
1990 to Present
Freelance consultant to many of Israel’s Blue-Chip firms,
mainly on issues related to the capital markets in Israel,
Canada, the UK and the USA.
Consultant to foreign RND ventures and to Governments
on macro-economic
matters.
President of the Israel chapter of the Professors World
Peace Academy (PWPA) and (briefly) Israel
representative of the “Washington Times”.
1993 to 1994
Co-owner and Director of many business enterprises:
– The Omega and Energy Air-Conditioning Concern
– AVP Financial Consultants
– Handiman Legal Services
Total annual turnover of the group: 10 million USD.
Co-owner, Director and Finance Manager of COSTI Ltd.
– Israel’s largest computerised information vendor and
developer. Raised funds through a series of private
placements locally in the USA, Canada and London.
1993 to 1996
Publisher and Editor of a Capital Markets Newsletter
distributed by subscription only to dozens of subscribers
countrywide.
In a legal precedent in 1995 – studied in business schools
and law faculties across Israel – was tried for his role in
an attempted takeover of Israel’s Agriculture Bank.
Was interned in the State School of Prison Wardens.
Managed the Central School Library, wrote, published
and lectured on various occasions.
Managed the Internet and International News Department
of an Israeli mass media group, “Ha-Tikshoret and
Namer”.
Assistant in the Law Faculty in Tel-Aviv University (to
Prof. S.G. Shoham).
1996 to 1999
Financial consultant to leading businesses in Macedonia,
Russia and the Czech Republic. Collaborated with the
Agency of Transformation of Business with Social
Capital.
Economic commentator in “Nova Makedonija”,
“Dnevnik”, “Makedonija Denes”, “Izvestia”, “Argumenti i
Fakti”, “The Middle East Times”, “The New Presence”,
“Central Europe Review”, and other periodicals, and in
the economic programs on various channels of
Macedonian Television.
http://www.dnevnik.com.mk/
http://www.pritomnost.cz/index.php?fulltext=vaknin
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
Chief Lecturer in courses organised by the Agency of
Transformation, by the Macedonian Stock Exchange, and
by the Ministry of Trade.
1999 to 2002
Economic Advisor to the Government of the Republic of
Macedonia and to the Ministry of Finance.
2001 to 2003
Senior Business Correspondent for United Press
International (UPI).
Web and Journalistic Activities
Author of extensive Web sites in:
– Psychology (“Malignant Self Love”) – An Open
Directory Cool Site,
– Philosophy (“Philosophical Musings”),
– Economics and Geopolitics (“World in Conflict and
Transition”).
Owner of the Narcissistic Abuse Announcement and
Study List and the Narcissism Revisited mailing list (more
than 4900 members).
Owner of the Economies in Conflict and Transition Study
List and the Link and Factoid Study List.
http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/
http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/Personality/Narcissistic
http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/Personality/Narcissistic
http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/Personality/Narcissistic
http://philosophos.tripod.com/
http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/
http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/
http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/narcissisticabuse/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/narcissisticabuse/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/narcissisticabuse/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/conflictransition/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/conflictransition/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/conflictransition/
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/linknfactoid/
Editor of mental health disorders and Central and Eastern
Europe categories in various Web directories (Open
Directory, Search Europe, Mentalhelp.net).
Editor of the Narcissistic Personality Disorder, the Verbal
and Emotional Abuse, and the Spousal (Domestic) Abuse
and Violence topics on Suite 101 and Bellaonline.
Columnist and commentator in “The New Presence”,
United Press International (UPI), InternetContent,
eBookWeb, PopMatters, Global Politician, and “Central
Europe Review”.
Publications and Awards
“Managing Investment Portfolios in States of
Uncertainty”, Limon Publishers, Tel-Aviv, 1988
“The Gambling Industry”, Limon Publishers, Tel-Aviv,
1990
“Requesting My Loved One – Short Stories”, Yedioth
Aharonot, Tel-Aviv, 1997
“The Suffering of Being Kafka” (electronic book of
Hebrew and English Short Fiction), Prague and Skopje,
1998-2004
“The Macedonian Economy at a Crossroads – On the Way
to a Healthier Economy” (dialogues with Nikola
Gruevski), Skopje, 1998
“The Exporters’ Pocketbook”, Ministry of Trade, Republic
of Macedonia, Skopje, 1999
http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/
http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/
http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/
http://www.searcheurope.com/
http://www.mentalhelp.net/poc/view_doc.php/type/doc/id/419
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/npd
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/verbal_emotional_abuse
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/verbal_emotional_abuse
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/verbal_emotional_abuse
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/18046
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/18046
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/18046
http://www.bellaonline.com/archive/MentalHealth
http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html
http://www.popmatters.com/columns/archive.shtml
http://www.globalpolitician.com/search.asp?keyword=Vaknin
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
http://www.yediothsfarim.co.il/catalog1.asp?bID=3621609
http://samvak.tripod.com/sipurim.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/cvng.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/cvng.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/cvng.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/exporter.html
“Malignant Self Love – Narcissism Revisited”, Narcissus
Publications, Prague and Skopje, 1999, 2001, 2003, 2004
The Narcissism Series (e-books regarding relationships
with abusive narcissists), Skopje, 1999-2004
“After the Rain – How the West Lost the East”, Narcissus
Publications in association with Central Europe
Review/CEENMI, Prague and Skopje, 2000
Winner of numerous awards, among them Israel’s Council
of Culture and Art Prize for Maiden Prose (1997), The
Rotary Club Award for Social Studies (1976), and the
Bilateral Relations Studies Award of the American
Embassy in Israel (1978).
Hundreds of professional articles in all fields of finances
and the economy, and numerous articles dealing with
geopolitical and political economic issues published in
both print and Web periodicals in many countries.
Many appearances in the electronic media on subjects in
philosophy and the sciences, and concerning economic
matters.
Contact Details:
palma@unet.com.mk
vaknin@link.com.mk
http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/after.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/aftertherain.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/aftertherain.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/aftertherain.html
http://www.yediothsfarim.co.il/catalog1.asp?bID=3621609
http://www.yediothsfarim.co.il/catalog1.asp?bID=3621609
mailto:palma@unet.com.mk
mailto:vaknin@link.com.mk
My Web Sites:
Economy / Politics:
http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/
Psychology:
http://samvak.tripod.com/index.html
Philosophy:
http://philosophos.tripod.com/
Poetry:
http://samvak.tripod.com/contents.html
Return
http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/
http://samvak.tripod.com/index.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/contents.html
After the Rain
How the West
Lost the East
The Book
This is a series of articles written and published in 1996-2000 in Macedonia, in Russia,
in Egypt and in the Czech Republic.
How the West lost the East. The economics, the politics, the geopolitics, the
conspiracies, the corruption, the old and the new, the plough and the internet – it is all
here, in colourful and provocative prose.
From “The Mind of Darkness”:
“‘The Balkans’ – I say – ‘is the unconscious of the world’. People stop to digest this
metaphor and then they nod enthusiastically. It is here that the repressed memories of
history, its traumas and fears and images reside. It is here that the psychodynamics of
humanity – the tectonic clash between Rome and Byzantium, West and East, Judeo-
Christianity and Islam – is still easily discernible. We are seated at a New Year’s dining
table, loaded with a roasted pig and exotic salads. I, the Jew, only half foreign to this
cradle of Slavonics. Four Serbs, five Macedonians. It is in the Balkans that all ethnic
distinctions fail and it is here that they prevail anachronistically and atavistically.
Contradiction and change the only two fixtures of this tormented region. The women of
the Balkan – buried under provocative mask-like make up, retro hairstyles and too
narrow dresses. The men, clad in sepia colours, old fashioned suits and turn of the
century moustaches. In the background there is the crying game that is Balkanian
music: liturgy and folk and elegy combined. The smells are heavy with muskular
perfumes. It is like time travel. It is like revisiting one’s childhood.”
The Author
Sam Vaknin is the author of Malignant Self Love –
Narcissism Revisited and After the Rain – How the West
Lost the East. He is a columnist for Central Europe
Review and eBookWeb , a United Press International
(UPI) Senior Business Correspondent, and the editor of
mental health and Central East Europe categories in The
Open Directory and Suite101 .
Until recently, he served as the Economic Advisor to the
Government of Macedonia.
Visit Sam’s Web site at http://samvak.tripod.com
mailto:palma@unet.com.mk
http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/after.html
http://samvak.tripod.com/after.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html
http://www.ebookweb.org/
http://www.upi.com/results.cfm?Keywords=&Byline=Vaknin&DeskCode=All&IPTCCode=All&PubDateFromMonth=1&PubDateFromDay=01&PubDateFromYear=2001
http://www.upi.com/results.cfm?Keywords=&Byline=Vaknin&DeskCode=All&IPTCCode=All&PubDateFromMonth=1&PubDateFromDay=01&PubDateFromYear=2001
http://dmoz.org/
http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/npd
http://samvak.tripod.com/