Essay

Write a minimum 5 pages reflection critical analysis’ essay entitled “Is morality relative or are there objective moral truths?” This essay should explore the ethical, scientific, historic and socio-cultural dimensions of the readings. You have to read two readings
(links you will find below the assignment description), one written by Ruth Benedict, “The Case for Moral Relativism” and a second written by Louis P. Pojman entitled “The Case Against Moral Relativism.”

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

 

What position do you hold regarding the essay’s question? Do you agree or disagree with the positions stated in the two readings? In order to prove your thesis make reference to the required readings from Unit 1 and 2
, to the Instructor’s Lecture
, as well as to two readings included in this assignment. In the Instructor’s Lecture you have an additional bibliography.

 

Refer to Essay’s Rubrics in order to see the grading system.

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

 

In your essay you should:

 

  1. Use both readings as well as the rest of the required readings included in the Learning Modules.

  2. Give answers to the following questions:

  1. Regarding Benedict’s paper:

  1. Is Benedict correct in saying that our culture is “but one entry in a long series of possible adjustments”? What are the implications of this statement?

  2. Can we separate the descriptive (or fact-stating) aspect of anthropological study from the prescriptive (evaluative) aspect of evaluating cultures? Are there some independent criteria by which we can say that some cultures are better than others? Can you think how this project might begin?

  3. What are the implications of Benedict’s claim that morality is simply whatever a culture deems normal behavior? Is this a satisfactory equation? Can you apply it to the institution of slavery or the Nazi policy of anti-Semitism?

  4. What is the significance of Benedict’s statement, “The very eyes with which we see the problem are conditioned by the long traditional habits of our own society”? Can we apply the conceptual relativism embodied in this statement to her own position? (taken form Pojman L.P., Vaughn L., The Moral Life, New York 2007, p. 165.)

 

    b. Regarding Pojman’s paper:

 

  • Is Pojman correct in thinking most American students tend to be moral relativists? If he is, why is this? What is the attraction of relativism? If he’s not correct, explain your answer.

  • Explain the difference between subjective ethical relativism and conventionalism.

  • Sometimes people argue that since there are no universal moral truths, each culture’s morality is as good as every other, so we ought not to interfere in its practices. Assess this argument.

  • Does moral relativism have a bad effect on society? Reread the tape-recorded conversation between serial murderer Ted Bundy and one of his victims (pages 171-172) in which Bundy attempts to justify the murder of his victim on the basis of the idea that all moral values are subjective. Analyze Bundy’s discussion. How would the relativist respond to Bundy’s claim that relativism justifies rape and murder? What do you think? Why? (taken form Pojman L.P., Vaughn L., The Moral Life, New York 2007, pp. 190-191.)

     

    Here are the readings :

     http://www.colorado.edu/philosophy/heathwood/pdf/benedict_relativism  https://interbb.blackboard.com/courses/1/201413.1648/messaging/users/_21111_1/attachments/42d595b4d22c47ef9bb6374cf1e389e9/PojmanCase%281%29  

    ADefense of Ethical Relativism

    RUTH BENEDICT

    From Benedict, Ruth “Anthropology and the Abnormal,” Journal of General Psychology, 10, 1934.

    Ruth Benedict (1887-1948), a foremost American anthropologist, taught at

    Columbia University, and she is best known for her book Pattern of Culture

    (1935). Benedict views social systems as communities with common beliefs

    and practices, which have become integrated patterns of ideas and practices.

    Like a work of art, a culture chooses which theme from its repertoire of

    basic tendencies to emphasize and then produces a grand design, favoring

    those tendencies. The final systems differ from one another in striking ways,

    but we have no reason to say that one system is better than another. Once a

    society has made the choice, normalcy will look different, depending on the

    idea-practice pattern of the culture.

    Benedict views morality as dependent on the varying histories and

    environments of different cultures. In this essay she assembles an

    impressive amount of data from her anthropological research of tribal

    behavior on an island in northwest Melanesia from which she draws her

    conclusion that moral relativism is the correct view of moral principles.

    MODERN SOCIAL ANTHROPOLOGY has become more and more a study of

    the varieties and common elements of cultural environment and the consequences

    of these in human behavior. For such a surly of diverse social orders primitive

    peoples fortunately provide a laboratory not yet entirely vitiated by the spread of a

    standardized worldwide civilization. Dyaks and Hopis, Fijians and Yakuts arc

    significant for psychological and sociological study because only among these

    simpler peoples has there been sufficient isolation to give opportunity for the

    development of localized social forms. In the higher cultures the standardization of

    custom and belief over a couple of continents has given a false sense of the

    inevitability of the particular forms at have gained currency, and we need to turn to

    a wider survey in order to check the conclusions we hastily base upon this near-

    universality of familiar customs. Most of the simpler cultures did not gain the wide

    currency of the one which, out of our experience, we identify with human nature,

    but this was for various historical reasons, and certainly not for any that gives us as

    its carriers a monopoly of social good or of social sanity. Modern civilization, from

    this point of view, becomes not a necessary pinnacle of human achievement but

    one entry in a long series of possible adjustments.

    These adjustments, whether they are in mannerisms like the ways of showing

    anger, or joy, or grief in any society, or in major human drives like those of sex,

    prove to be far more variable than experience in any one culture would suggest. In

    certain fields, such as that of religion or of formal marriage arrangements, these

    wide limits of variability are well known and can be fairly described. In others it is

    not yet possible to give a generalized account, but that does not absolve us of the

    task of indicating the significance of the work that has been done and of die

    problems that have arisen.

    One of these problems relates to the customary modern normal-abnormal

    categories and our conclusions regarding them. In how far are such categories

    culturally determined, or in how far can we with assurance regard them as absolute?

    In how far can we regard inability to function socially as abnormality, or in how far

    is it necessary to regard this as a function of the culture?

    As a matter of fact, one of the most striking facts that emerge front a stud of

    widely varying cultures is the ease with which our abnormals function in other

    cultures. It does not matter what kind of “abnormality” we choose for illustration,

    those which indicate extreme instability, or those which are more in the nature of

    character traits like sadism or delusions grandeur or of persecution, there are well-

    described cultures in which these abnormals function at ease and with honor, and

    apparently without danger or difficulty to the society.

    The most notorious of these is trance and catalepsy. Even a very mild mystic is

    aberrant in our culture. But most peoples have regarded even extreme psychic

    manifestations not only as normal and desirable, but even as characteristic of

    highly valued and gifted individuals. This was true even in our own cultural

    background in that period when Catholicism made the ecstatic experience the mark

    of sainthood. It is hard for its, born and brought up in a culture that makes no use

    of the experience, to realize how important a role it may play and how many

    individuals are capable of it, once it has been given an honorable place in any

    society….

    Cataleptic and trance phenomena are, of course, only one illustration of the fact

    that those whom we regard as abnornials may function adequately in other cultures.

    Many of our culturally discarded traits are selected for elaboration in different

    societies. Homosexuality is an excellent example, for in this case our attention is

    not constantly diverted, as in the consideration of trance, to the interruption of

    routine activity which it implies. Homosexuality poses problem very simply. A

    tendency toward this trait in our culture exposes an individual to all the conflicts to

    which all aberrants are always exposed, and we tend to identify the consequences

    of this conflict with homosexuality. But these consequences are obviously local

    and cultural. Homosexuals in many societies are not incompetent, but they may be

    such if the culture asks adjustments of them that would strain any man’s vitality.

    Wherever homosexuality has been given an honorable place in any society, those

    to whom it is congenial have filled adequately the honorable roles society assigns

    to them. Plato’s Republic is, of course, the most convincing statement of such a

    reading of homosexuality. It is presented as one of the major means to the good life,

    and it was generally so regarded in Greece at that time.

    The cultural attitude toward homosexuals has not always been on such a high

    ethical plane, but it has been very varied. Among many American Indian tribes

    there exists the institution of the berdache, as the French called them. These men-

    women were men who at puberty or thereafter took the dress and the occupations

    of women. Sometimes they married other men and lived with them. Sometimes

    they were men with no inversion, persons of weak sexual endowment who chose

    this role to avoid the jeers of the women. The berdaches were never regarded as of

    first-rate supernatural power, as similar men-women were in Siberia, but rather as

    leaders in women’s occupations, good healers in certain diseases, or, among certain

    tribes, as the genial organizers of social affairs. In any case, they were socially

    placed. They were not left exposed to the conflicts that visit the deviant who is

    excluded from participation in the recognized patterns of his society.

    The most spectacular illustrations of the extent to which normality may be

    culturally defined are those cultures where an abnormality of our culture is the

    cornerstone of their social structure. It is not possible to do justice to these

    possibilities in a short discussion. A recent study of an island of northwest

    Melanesia by Fortune describes a society built upon traits which we regard as

    beyond the border of paranoia. In this tribe the exogamic groups look upon each

    other as prime manipulators of black magic, so that one marries always into an

    enemy group which remains for life one’s deadly and unappeasable foes. They look

    upon a good garden crop as a confession of theft, for everyone is engaged in

    making magic to induce into his garden the productiveness of his neighbors’;

    therefore no secrecy in the island is so rigidly insisted upon as the secrecy of a

    man’s harvesting of his yams. Their polite phrase at the acceptance of a gift is,

    “And if you now poison me, how shall I repay you this present?” Their

    preoccupation with poisoning is constant; no woman ever leaves her cooking pot

    for a moment unattended. Even the great affinal economic exchanges that are

    characteristic of this Melanesian culture area are quite altered in Dobu since they

    are incompatible with this fear and distrust that pervades the culture. They go

    farther and people the whole world outside their own quarters with such malignant

    spirits that all-night feasts and ceremonials simply do not occur here. They have

    even rigorous religiously enforced customs that forbid the sharing of seed even in

    one family group. Anyone else’s food is deadly poison to you, so that communality

    of’ stores is out of the question. For some months before harvest the whole society

    is on the verge of starvation, but if one falls to the temptation and eat up one’s seed

    yams, one is an outcast and a beachcomber for life. There is no corning back. It

    involves, as a matter of course, divorce and the breaking of all social ties.

    Now in this society where no one may work with another and no one may share

    with another, Fortune describes the individual who was regarded by all his fellows

    as crazy. He was not one of those who periodically ran amok and, beside himself

    and frothing at the mouth, fell with a knife upon anyone lie could reach. Such

    behavior they did not regard as putting anyone outside the pale. They did not even

    put the individuals who were known to be liable to these attacks under any kind of

    control. They merely fled when they saw the attack coming oil and kept out of the

    way. “He would be all right tomorrow.” Brit there was one man of sunny, kindly

    disposition who liked work and liked to be helpful. The compulsion was too strong

    for him to repress it in favor of the opposite tendencies of his culture. Men and

    women never spoke of him without laughing; he was silly and simple and

    definitely crazy. Nevertheless, to the ethnologist used to a culture that has, in

    Christianity, made his type the model of all virtue, he seemed a pleasant fellow….

    … Among the Kwakiutl it did not matter whether a relative had died in bed of

    disease, or by the hand of an enemy, in either case death was an affront to he wiped

    out by the death of another person. The fact that one had been caused to mourn was

    proof that one had been put upon. A chief’s sister and her daughter had gone up to

    Victoria, and either because they drank bad whiskey or because their boat capsized

    they never came back. The chief called together his warriors, “Now I ask you,

    tribes, who shall wail? Shall I do it or shall another?” The spokesman answered, of

    course, “Not you, Chief. Let some other of the tribes.” Immediately they set up the

    war pole to announce their intention of wiping out the injury, and gather a war

    party. They set out, and found seven men and two children asleep and killed them.

    “Then they felt good when they arrived at Sebaa in the evening.”

    The point which is of interest to us is that in our society those who on that

    occasion would feel good when they arrived at Sebaa that evening would be the

    definitely abnormal. There would be some, even in our society, but it is not a

    recognized and approved mood under the circumstance. On the Northwest Coast

    those are favored and fortunate to whom that mood under those circumstances is

    congenial, and those to whom it is repugnant are unlucky. This latter minority can

    register ill their own culture only by doing violence to their congenial responses

    and acquiring other that are difficult for them. The person, for instance, who, like a

    Plains Indian whose wife has been taken from him, is too proud to fight, can deal

    with the Northwest Coast civilization only by ignoring its strongest bents. If he

    cannot achieve it, lie is the deviant in that culture, their instance of abnormality.

    This head-hunting that takes place on the Northwest Coast after a death is no

    matter of blood revenge or of organized vengeance. There is no effort to tie tip the

    subsequent killing with any responsibility on the part of the victim for the death of

    the person who is being mourned. A chief whose son has died goes visiting

    wherever his fancy dictates, and he says to his host, “My prince has died today, and

    you go with him.” Then lie kills him. In this, according to their interpretation, he

    acts nobly because he has not been downed. He has thrust back in return. The

    whole procedure is meaningless without the fundamental paranoid reading of be-

    reavement. Death, like all the other untoward accidents of existence, confounds

    man’s pride and can only be handled in the category of insults.

    The behavior honored upon the Northwest Coast is one which is recognized as

    abnormal in our civilization, and yet it is sufficiently close to the attitudes of our

    own culture to be intelligible to its and to have a definite vocabulary with which we

    may discuss it. The megalomaniac paranoid trend is a definite danger in our society.

    It is encouraged by some of our major preoccupations, and it confronts us with a

    choice of two possible attitudes. One is to brand it as abnormal and reprehensible,

    and is the attitude we have chosen in our civilization. The other is to make it an

    essential attribute of ideal man, and this is the solution in the culture of the

    Northwest Coast.

    These illustrations, which it has been possible to indicate only in the briefest

    manner, force upon us the fact that normality is culturally defined. An adult shaped

    to the drives and standards of either of these cultures, if lie were transported into

    our civilization, would fall into our categories of abnormality. He would be faced

    with the psychic dilemmas of the socially unavailable. In his own culture, however,

    he is the pillar of society, the end result of socially inculcated mores, and the

    problem of personal instability in his case simply does not arise.

    No one civilization can possibly utilize in its mores the whole potential range of

    human behavior. Just as there are great numbers of possible phonetic articulations,

    and the possibility of language depends on a selection and standardization of a few

    of these in order that speech communication may be possible at all, so the

    possibility of organized behavior of every sort, from the fashions of local dress and

    houses to the dicta of a people’s ethics and religion, depends upon a similar

    selection among the possible behavior traits. In the field of recognized economic

    obligations or sex tabus this selection is as nonrational and subconscious a process

    as it is in the field of phonetics. It is a process which goes on in the group for long

    periods of time and is historically conditioned by innumerable accidents of

    isolation or of contact of peoples. In any comprehensive study of psychology, the

    selection that different cultures have made in the course of history within the great

    circumference of potential behavior is of great significance.

    Every society, beginning with some slight inclination in one direction or

    another, carries its preference farther and farther, integrating itself more and mole

    completely upon its chosen basis, and discarding those type of behavior that are

    uncongenial. Most of those organizations of personality that seem to us most

    uncontrovertibly abnormal have been used by different civilizations in the very

    foundations of their institutional life. Conversely the most valued traits of our

    normal individuals have been looked on in differently organized cultures as

    aberrant. Normality, in short, within a very wide range, is culturally defined. It is

    primarily a term for the socially elaborated segment of human behavior in any

    culture; and abnormality, a term for the segment that particular civilization does

    not use. The very eyes with which we see the problem are conditioned by the long

    traditional habits of our own society.

    It is a point that has been made more often in relation to ethics than in relation

    to psychiatry. We do not any longer make the mistake of deriving the morality of

    our locality and decade directly from the inevitable constitution of human nature.

    We do not elevate it to the dignity of a first principle. We recognize that morality

    differs in every society, and is a convenient term for socially approved habits.

    Mankind has always preferred to say, “It is a morally good,” rather than “It is

    habitual,” and the fact of this preference is matter enough for a critical science of

    ethics. But historically the two phrases are synonymous.

    The concept of the normal is properly a variant of the concept of the good. It is

    that which society has approved. A normal action is one which falls well within the

    limits of expected behavior for a particular society. Its variability among different

    peoples is essentially a function of the variability of the behavior patterns that

    different societies have created for themselves, and can never be wholly divorced

    from a consideration of culturally institutionalized types of behavior.

    Each culture is a more or less elaborate working-out of the potentialities of the

    segment it has chosen. In so far as a civilization is well integrated and consistent

    within itself, it will tend to carry farther and farther, according to its nature, its

    initial impulse toward a particular type of action, and from the point of view of any

    other culture those elaborations will include more and more extreme and aberrant

    traits.

    Each of these traits, in proportion as it reinforces the chosen behavior patterns

    of that culture, is for that culture normal. Those individuals to whom it is congenial

    either congenitally, or as the result of childhood sets, are accorded prestige in that

    culture, and are not visited with the social contempt or disapproval which their

    traits would call clown upon them in a society that was differently organized. On

    the other hand, those individuals whose characteristics are not congenial to the

    selected type of human behavior in that community are the deviants, no matter how

    valued their personality traits may be in a contrasted civilization.

    The Dohuan who is not easily susceptible to fear of treachery, who enjoys work

    and likes to be helpful, is their neurotic and regarded as silly. On the Northwest

    Coast the person who finds it difficult to read life in terms of an insult contest will

    be the person upon whom fall all the difficulties of the culturally unprovided for.

    The person who does not find it easy to humiliate a neighbor, nor to see

    humiliation in his own experience, who is genial and loving, may, of course, find

    some unstandardized way of achieving satisfactions in his society, but not in the

    major patterned responses that his culture requires of him. If he is born to play an

    important role in a family with many hereditary privileges, he can succeed only by

    doing violence to his whole personality. If he does not succeed, he has betrayed his

    culture; that is, he is abnormal.

    I have spoken of individuals as having sets toward certain types of behavior,

    and of these sets as running sometimes counter to the types of behavior which are

    institutionalized in the culture to which they belong. From all that we know of

    contrasting cultures it seems clear that differences of temperament occur in every

    society. The matter has never been made the subject of investigation, but from the

    available material it would appeal that these temperament types are very likely of

    universal recurrence. That is, there is an ascertainable range of human behavior

    that is found wherever a sufficiently large series of individuals is observed. But the

    proportion in which behavior types stand to one another in different societies is not

    universal. The vast majority of individuals in any group are shaped to the fashion

    of that culture. In other words, most individuals are plastic to the moulding force of

    the society into which they are born. In a society that values trance, as in India,

    they will have supernormal experience. In a society that institutionalizes

    homosexuality, they will be homosexual. In a society that sets the gathering of

    possessions as the chief human objective, they will amass property. The deviants,

    whatever the type of behavior the culture has institutionalized, will remain few in

    number, and there seems no more difficulty in moulding the vast malleable majori-

    ty to the “normality” of what we consider an aberrant trait, such as delusions of

    reference, than to the normality of such accepted behavior patterns as

    acquisitiveness. The small proportion of the number of the deviants in any culture

    is not a function of the sure instinct with which that society has built itself upon the

    fundamental sanities, but of the universal fact that, happily, the majority of

    mankind quite readily take any shape that is presented to them.

    Héctor E. López-Sierra, Ph.D.

    Associate Professor

    Humanistic Studies Faculty

    Metropolitan Campus

    Inter American University of Puerto Rico

    1

    Measuring Morality: What is

    Right and Wrong?

    2

    Introduction

    • One can say that every ethical value involves some
    standard of behavior, and every standard is defined in a
    prescriptive manner.

    • Ethical standards are expressed in terms of “ought” and
    “should,” or “ought not” and “should not.” They transcend
    the language of description, speaking not only of “what is,”
    but rather “what should be.”

    • Where do we find such standards? What kinds of sources
    are available to us upon which to build an ethical system?
    The options are as follows:

    1. “Oughts” are derived from what “is.”

    • Definition:

    – Mortimer Adler: An attempt “to get conclusions in the imperative mood
    from premises entirely in the indicative mood.” This view presupposes the
    origination of value is found in the facts, the observation of nature.

    – G. G. Simpson: What is ethically right is related in some way to what is
    materially true. A man runs a red light. He cannot draw a conclusion of
    whether or not to run the red light without having an earlier presupposition
    or standard in place concerning that ethical choice: “One shouldn’t run red
    lights.”

    • Example:

    – Behaviorism: All of our actions are the result of either our genetic make-up
    or our environment. This system presupposes that nothing exists beyond
    the material realm. What is called mind is reduced to physical and chemical
    reactions. We cannot act upon the world; rather, the world acts upon us.

    • Critique:

    – There can be no human responsibility for actions. Behaviorists themselves
    appeal to a standard of justice when wronged. Contrary to the contention of
    the behaviorists, there are both philosophical reasons and scientific
    evidence to support the belief that we do possess an immaterial substance.

    Critique…

    • To have true moral values, people must get them from somewhere other

    than the actual world of description. This view destroys the very concepts of

    good and evil, because “what is” contains both.

    • To speak of good and evil becomes non-essential. Charles Manson said, “If

    God is one, what is bad?” Baudelaire lamented, “If God exists, he is the

    Devil.”

    • This view does not answer the question of predatorial/survival life in nature.

    All that we call “human” would be destroyed if people practiced this natural

    ethic consistently and universally. Not many hold this view seriously. T. H.

    Huxley admitted that, although evolution is true, it leads to bad ethics. Even

    evolutionists choose not to live in such a world. Instead, they philosophically

    smuggle Christian ethics arbitrarily into their system and hold it romantically

    upon their naturalistic base.

    2. The Consensus Ethic (Majority Rule)

    • Definition:

    – Whatever a cultural group approves of is deemed right; whatever

    the group disapproves of is wrong. In America, we find the most

    popular expression of cultural relativism demonstrated in the

    opinion poll.

    • Example:

    – Utilitarianism-This moral theory seeks to maximize, by your

    actions, the greatest good for the greatest number of people. The

    emphasis is on the group, not the individual.

    • Critique:

    – Bentham and Mill could not agree on whether to evaluate on a

    quantitative or qualitative basis. The questions we need to ask are:

    What is good? or Good for whom? Justice, does it matter? Is it as

    or more important than the good of the group?

    Critique…

    • Ethics by majority may actually have little to do with morality. For
    example, if 55% of the German people assented to the
    extermination of Jewry by Hitler and his henchmen, then their
    actions were “right,” and other cultures should have withheld any
    criticism of German sovereignty in their own internal affairs.

    • Cultural relativism is really “status-quoism,” providing no strong
    motive for social change. It is also capricious over time. For
    example, in 1859, slavery in the United States was socially
    acceptable and abortion was illegal. Today, the reverse is true.

    • Those who prefer this ethical foundation must face one very
    dangerous fact: If there is no standard by which society can be
    judged and held accountable, then society becomes the judge.
    When that happens, no one is safe–minorities, the unborn, the
    elderly, the handicapped, and perhaps even the blond-headed or the
    left handed!

    3. The Arbitrary Ethic (Power)

    • Definition:

    – An individual or elitist group sets itself up as arbiter of values and
    uses the necessary force to maintain these values. As
    democratic consensus rules from below, arbitrary absolutists rule
    from above.

    • Example: Marxism:

    – The will of men (party) decides on the values based on
    subjective principles of dialectic materialism. Lenin would call
    any action useful to the party moral action; he would call it
    immoral if it is harmful to the party.

    • Critique:

    – The arbiter can be a dictator, a parliament, a supreme court, a
    political party, or any elite configuration which has the power to
    impose its will upon the populace.

    Critique…

    • What is enforced is based solely upon what the arbiter decides will be
    enforced. The Catholic Inquisitors summarily tortured and executed
    unrepentant heretics. Soviet Russia was ruthlessly governed by an all-
    powerful Central Committee.

    • It is important to remember that such arbiters can make something legal but
    not moral. The 1972 Roe vs. Wade decision legalizing abortion is the most
    pertinent contemporary example. The judges, choosing to ignore medical,
    legal, and religious precedents on the true humanity of the unborn, made an
    arbitrary, pragmatic decision. This ruling was legal, but not necessarily
    moral.

    • The great flaw in this approach is that it presupposes great trust in those
    who govern. History has not confirmed the wisdom of placing such
    confidence in those who wield absolute power. The balancing of power in
    the U.S. Constitution between the various branches of government reflects
    the wariness of its framers in giving undue authority to any federal entity.

    • Power corrupts; absolute power corrupts absolutely. It leads to despotism,
    and tyranny.

    4. The True Absolute (Transcendence)

    • Definition:

    – C. S. Lewis has here identified the “three parts of morality,” the first two of
    which humans are well-acquainted with: internal moral deficiencies and
    conflict with others through ethical choices. It is the third part for which all
    humans long: namely, some objective standard to which all humans must
    adhere. Such a standard necessarily transcends the world of description.
    It presupposes that God exists and has spoken or revealed such standards.

    • Example:

    – The Ten Commandments provide the boundaries for the definition of
    humanness; any act contrary to this true absolute is a violation of our
    humanity. Further, these standards are not merely external principles, but
    rather the very essence of the nature and character of God.

    • Critique:

    – Some things are right; some are wrong, and objectively so. This ethical
    system is based on normative principles rather than subjective utilitarian
    ones. It also provides a basis for conviction: what was right yesterday will be
    right today. The individual is protected against the whole of society–wicked
    kings, pragmatic judges, corrupt politicians, decadent populace. There is
    also a true and legitimate motive for fighting evil, an objective basis for
    social change.

    5. Natural Law and Divine Providence

    • Definition:

    – Thomas Aquinas plays in the natural law tradition. Every encyclopedia
    article on natural law thought refers to Aquinas.

    – For Aquinas, there are two key features of the natural law:

    1) God„ is the giver of the natural law, the natural law is just one
    aspect of divine providence.

    2) Human’s role as recipient of the natural law, the natural law
    constitutes the principles of practical rationality, those principles by
    which human action is to be judged as reasonable or
    unreasonable; and so the theory of natural law is from that
    perspective the preeminent part of the theory.

    • Example:

    – The Bible as the main resource for natural law.

    • Critique:

    – The Natural Law is primarily a Christian oriented discourse; which does not
    represent the views of other world religions, such as Hinduism.

    Bibliography for Moral Actions

    • Adams, R. M. (1988). Common projects and moral virtue. Midwest Studies in
    Philosophy, 13, 297–307.

    • Alston, W. P. (1967). Motives and motivation. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The encyclopedia
    of philosophy (Vol. 5, pp. 399–409). New York: Macmillan.

    • Blum, L. A. (1980). Friendship, altruism, and morality. London: Routledge & Kegan
    Paul.

    • Brandt, R. B. (1988). The structure of virtue. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 13, 64–
    82.

    • Brandt, R. B. (1996). Facts, values, and morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University
    Press.

    • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. A theory of normative judgment.
    Cambridge/Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    • John, O. P. & Gosling, S. D. (2000). Personality traits. In A. E. Kazdin (Ed.),
    Encyclopedia of psychology (Vol. 6, pp. 140–144). Oxford–New York: Oxford
    University Press.

    • McInerny, R. (1997). Ethica Thomistica: The Moral Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas.
    Washington: The Catholic University of America Press.

    • Pervin, L. A. (2000). Personality. In A. E. Kazdin (Ed.), Encyclopedia of psychology
    (Vol. 6, pp. 100–106). Oxford–New York: Oxford University Press.

    • Slote, M. (2001). Morals from motives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    • Smith, A. (1994). Theorie der ethischen Gefühle. Hamburg: Meiner. (Original
    erschienen 17906: The theory of moral sentiments)

    • Wright, G. H. v. (1983). Practical reason. Philosophical papers (Vol. 1): Oxford: Basil
    Blackwell.

    Bibliography for Natural Law and Ethics

    • Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologiae..

    • Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability .
    Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    • Duns Scotus, John. 1997. Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality. Ed. Allan Wolter. Washington,
    DC: Catholic University of America Press.

    • Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    • Finnis, John. 1998. Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    • Hare, John E. 2001. God’s Call. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.

    • Hobbes, Thomas. 1994. Elements of Law: Natural and Politic. Ed. J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford
    University Press. Cited as EL by chapter and section number.

    • Irwin, Terence. 2000. “Ethics as an Inexact Science: Aristotle’s Ambitions for Moral Theory.” In
    Brad Hooker and Margaret Little, eds. Moral Particularism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    • Kaczor, Christopher. 2002. Proportionalism and the Natural Law Tradition. Washington, DC:
    Catholic University of America Press.

    • Lisska, Anthony. 1996. Aquinas’s Theory of Natural Law: An Analytic Reconstruction. Oxford:
    Oxford University Press.

    • Locke, John. 1988. Essays on the Law of Nature. Ed. W. von Leyden. Oxford: Oxford University
    Press.

    • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1999. Dependent Rational Animals. Chicago: Open Court.

    • Moore, Michael. 1982. “Moral Reality.” Wisconsin Law Review [1982], pp. 1061-1156.

    • Porter, Jean. 2005. Nature as Reason: A Thomistic Theory of the Natural Law. Grand Rapids:
    Eerdmans.

    • Thompson, Michael. 2004. “Apprehending Human Form.” Modern Moral Philosophy, Cambridge,
    UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 47-74.

    Issues in Ethics

    1
    st
    EDITION

    Sam Vaknin, Ph.D.

    Editing and Design:

    Lidija Rangelovska

    Lidija Rangelovska

    A Narcissus Publications Imprint, Skopje 2002-5

    Not for Sale! Non-commercial edition.

    http://www.gutenberg.org/wiki/Main_Page

    http://www.gutenberg.org/wiki/Main_Page

    © 2002, 2005 Copyright Lidija Rangelovska.

    All rights reserved. This book, or any part thereof, may not be used or reproduced in

    any manner without written permission from:

    Lidija Rangelovska – write to:

    palma@unet.com.mk or to

    vaknin@link.com.mk

    Visit the Author Archive of Dr. Sam Vaknin in “Central Europe Review”:

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    Visit Sam Vaknin’s United Press International (UPI) Article Archive –

    Click HERE!

    Philosophical Musings and Essays

    http://samvak.tripod.com/culture.html

    Malignant Self Love – Narcissism Revisited

    http://samvak.tripod.com/

    Created by: LIDIJA RANGELOVSKA

    REPUBLIC OF MACEDONIA

    mailto:palma@unet.com.mk

    mailto:vaknin@link.com.mk

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/guide.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/

    C O N T E N T S

    I. Morality as a Mental State

    II. Affiliation and Morality

    III.

    Nature, Aesthetics, Pleasure, and Ethics

    IV.

    On Being Human

    V.

    The Encroachment of the Public

    VI.

    And Then There Were Too Many

    VII.

    Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species

    VIII.

    The Myth of the Right to Life

    IX.

    The Argument for Torture

    X.

    The Aborted Contract

    XI. In Our Own Image –

    The Debate about Cloning

    XII.

    Ethical Relativism and Absolute Taboos

    XIII.

    The Merits of Stereotypes

    XIV. The Happiness of Others

    XV. The Egotistic Friend

    XVI. The Distributive Justice of the Market

    XVII. The Agent-Principal Conundrum

    XVIII.

    Legalizing Crime

    XIX. The Insanity of the Defense

    XX. The Impeachment of the President

    XXI. The Rights of Animals

    XXII.

    Just War or a Just War?

    XXIII.

    Cannibalism and Human Sacrifice

    XXIV.

    Euthanasia and the Right to Die

    XXV. The Auth

    or

    XXVI. About “After the Rain”

    Morality as a Mental State

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    INTRODUCTION

    Moral values, rules, principles, and judgements are often

    thought of as beliefs or as true beliefs. Those who hold

    them to be true beliefs also annex to them a warrant or a

    justification (from the “real world”). Yet, it is far more

    reasonable to conceive of morality (ethics) as a state of

    mind, a mental state. It entails belief, but not necessarily

    true belief, or justification. As a mental state, morality

    cannot admit the “world” (right and wrong, evidence,

    goals, or results) into its logical formal definition. The

    world is never part of the definition of a mental state.

    Another way of looking at it, though, is that morality

    cannot be defined in terms of goals and results – because

    these goals and results ARE morality itself. Such a

    definition would be tautological.

    There is no guarantee that we know when we are in a

    certain mental state. Morality is no exception.

    An analysis based on the schemata and arguments

    proposed by Timothy Williamson follows.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    Moral Mental State – A Synopsis

    Morality is the mental state that comprises a series of

    attitudes to propositions. There are four classes of moral

    propositions: “It is wrong to…”, “It is right to…”, (You

    should) do this…”, “(You should) not do this…”. The most

    common moral state of mind is: one adheres to p.

    Adhering to p has a non-trivial analysis in the more basic

    terms of (a component of) believing and (a component of)

    knowing, to be conceptually and metaphysically analysed

    later. Its conceptual status is questionable because we

    need to decompose it to obtain the necessary and

    sufficient conditions for its possession (Peacocke, 1992).

    It may be a complex (secondary) concept.

    Adhering to proposition p is not merely believing that p

    and knowing that p but also that something should be so,

    if and only if p (moral law).

    Morality is not a factive attitude. One believes p to be true

    – but knows p to be contingently true (dependent on

    epoch, place, and culture). Since knowing is a factive

    attitude, the truth it relates to is the contingently true

    nature of moral propositions.

    Morality relates objects to moral propositions and it is a

    mental state (for every p, having a moral mental relation

    to p is a mental state).

    Adhering to p entails believing p (involves the mental

    state of belief). In other words, one cannot adhere without

    believing. Being in a moral mental state is both necessary

    and sufficient for adhering to p. Since no “truth” is

    involved – there is no non-mental component of adhering

    to p.

    Adhering to p is a conjunction with each of the conjuncts

    (believing p and knowing p) a necessary condition – and

    the conjunction is necessary and sufficient for adhering to

    p.

    One doesn’t always know if one adheres to p. Many moral

    rules are generated “on the fly”, as a reaction to

    circumstances and moral dilemmas. It is possible to

    adhere to p falsely (and behave differently when faced

    with the harsh test of reality). A sceptic would say that for

    any moral proposition p – one is in the position to know

    that one doesn’t believe p. Admittedly, it is possible for a

    moral agent to adhere to p without being in the position to

    know that one adheres to p, as we illustrated above. One

    can also fail to adhere to p without knowing that one fails

    to adhere to p. As Williamson says “transparency (to be in

    the position to know one’s mental state) is false”.

    Naturally, one knows one’s mental state better than one

    knows other people’s. There is an observational

    asymmetry involved. We have non-observational

    (privileged) access to our mental state and observational

    access to other people’s mental states. Thus, we can say

    that we know our morality non-observationally (directly) –

    while we are only able to observe other people’s morality.

    One believes moral propositions and knows moral

    propositions. Whether the belief itself is rational or not, is

    debatable. But the moral mental state strongly imitates

    rational belief (which relies on reasoning). In other words,

    the moral mental state masquerades as a factive attitude,

    though it is not. The confusion arises from the normative

    nature of knowing and being rational.

    Normative elements exist in belief attributions, too, but,

    for some reason, are considered “outside the realm of

    belief”. Belief, for instance, entails the grasping of mental

    content, its rational processing and manipulation,

    defeasible reaction to new information.

    We will not go here into the distinction offered by

    Williamson between “believing truly” (not a mental state,

    according to him) and “believing”. Suffice it to say that

    adhering to p is a mental state, metaphysically speaking –

    and that “adheres to p” is a (complex or secondary) mental

    concept. The structure of adheres to p is such that the non-

    mental concepts are the content clause of the attitude

    ascription and, thus do not render the concept thus

    expressed non-mental: adheres to (right and wrong,

    evidence, goals, or results).

    Williamson’s Mental State Operator calculus is applied.

    Origin is essential when we strive to fully understand the

    relations between adhering that p and other moral

    concepts (right, wrong, justified, etc.). To be in the moral

    state requires the adoption of specific paths, causes, and

    behaviour modes. Moral justification and moral

    judgement are such paths.

    Knowing, Believing and their Conjunction

    We said above that:

    “Adhering to p is a conjunction with each of the conjuncts

    (believing p and knowing p) a necessary condition – and
    the conjunction is necessary and sufficient for adhering to

    p.”

    Williamson suggests that one believes p if and only if one

    has an attitude to proposition p indiscriminable from

    knowing p. Another idea is that to believe p is to treat p as

    if one knew p. Thus, knowing is central to believing

    though by no means does it account for the entire

    spectrum of belief (example: someone who chooses to

    believe in God even though he doesn’t know if God

    exists). Knowledge does determine what is and is

    not

    appropriate to believe, though (“standard of

    appropriateness”). Evidence helps justify belief.

    But knowing as a mental state is possible without having a

    concept of knowing. One can treat propositions in the

    same way one treats propositions that one knows – even if

    one lacks concept of knowing. It is possible (and

    practical) to rely on a proposition as a premise if one has a

    factive propositional attitude to it. In other words, to treat

    the proposition as though it is known and then to believe

    in it.

    As Williamson says, “believing is a kind of a botched

    knowing”. Knowledge is the aim of belief, its goal.

    Affiliation and Morality

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    Also Read:

    Morality as a Mental State

    Nature, Aesthetics, Pleasure, and Ethics

    What should prevail: the imperative to spare the lives of

    innocent civilians – or the need to safeguard the lives of

    fighter pilots? Precision bombing puts such pilots at great

    risk. Avoiding this risk usually results in civilian

    casualties (“collateral damage”).

    This moral dilemma is often “solved” by applying –

    explicitly or implicitly – the principle of “over-riding

    affiliation”. We find the two facets of this principle in

    Jewish sacred texts: “One is close to oneself” and “Your

    city’s poor denizens come first (with regards to charity)”.

    One’s affiliation (to a community, or a fraternity) is

    determined by one’s position and, more so, perhaps, by

    one’s oppositions.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/moral.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/ethics.html

    One’s sole organic position is the positive statement “I am

    a human being”. All other positions are actually synthetic.

    They are subsets of the single organic positive statement

    “I am a human being”. They are made of couples of

    positive and negative statements. The negative members

    of each couple can be fully derived from (and are entirely

    dependent on) – and thus fully implied by – the positive

    members. Not so the positive members.

    Consider the couple “I am an Israeli” and “I am not an

    Indian”.

    The positive statement “I am an Israeli” implies about 220

    CERTAIN (true) negative statements of the type “I am not

    … (a citizen of country X, which is not Israel)”, including

    the statement “I am not an Indian”. But it cannot be fully

    derived from any single true negative statement, or be

    entirely dependent upon it.

    The relationship, though, is asymmetrical.

    The negative statement “I am not an Indian” implies about

    220 POSSIBLE positive statements of the type “I am … (a

    citizen of country X, which is not India)”, including the

    statement “I am an Israeli”. And it can be fully derived

    from any single (true) positive statement or be entirely

    dependent upon it (the positive statement “I am an Indian”

    being, of course, false).

    Thus, a positive statement about one’s affiliation (“I am an

    Israeli”) immediately generates 220 true and certain

    negative statements (one of which is “I am not an

    Indian”).

    One’s positive self-definition automatically yields

    multiple definitions (by negation) of multiple others.

    Their positive self-definitions, in turn, negate one’s

    positive self-definition.

    It is possible for more than one person to have the same

    positive self-definition. A positive self-definition shared

    by more than one person is what we know as community,

    fraternity, nation, state, religion – or, in short, affiliation.

    One’s moral obligations towards others who share with

    him his positive self-definition (i.e., with whom one is

    affiliated) overrides and supersedes one’s moral

    obligations towards others who don’t. As an Israeli, my

    moral obligation to safeguard the lives of Israeli fighter

    pilots overrides and supersedes (subordinates) my moral

    obligation to save the lives of innocent civilians, however

    numerous, if they are not Israelis.

    The more numerous the positive self-definitions I share

    with someone (i.e., the more affiliations) , the larger and

    more overriding is my moral obligation to him. My moral

    obligation towards other humans is superseded by my

    moral obligation towards other Israelis, which, in turn, is

    superseded by my moral obligation towards the members

    of my family.

    But this raises some difficulties.

    It would appear that the strength of one’s moral

    obligations towards other people is determined by the

    number of positive self-definitions he shares with them

    (i.e., by the number of his affiliations). Moral obligations

    are, therefore, not transcendent – but contingent and

    relative. They are the outcomes of interactions with others

    – but not in the immediate sense, as the personalist

    philosopher Emmanuel Levinas postulated.

    Rather, they are the solutions yielded by a moral calculus

    of shared affiliations. The solutions are best presented as

    matrices with specific moral values and obligations

    attached to the numerical strengths of one’s affiliations.

    Some moral obligations are universal and are related to

    one’s organic position as a human being (the “basic

    affiliation”). These are the “transcendent

    moral values”.

    Other moral values and obligations arise as the number of

    shared affiliations increases. These are the “derivative

    moral values”.

    Yet, moral values and obligations do not accumulate.

    There is a hierarchy of moral values and obligations. The

    universal ones – the ones related to one’s organic position

    as a human being – are the WEAKEST. They are

    overruled by derivative moral values and obligations

    related to one’s affiliations – and are subordinated to them.

    The imperative “thou shall not kill (another human

    being)” is easily over-ruled by the moral obligation to kill

    for one’s country. The imperative “though shall not steal”

    is superseded by one’s moral obligation to spy for one’s

    nation.

    This leads to another startling conclusion:

    There is no such thing as a self-consistent moral system.

    The derivative moral values and obligations often

    contradict each other and almost always conflict with the

    universal moral values

    and obligations.

    In the examples above, killing (for one’s country) and

    stealing (for one’s nation) are moral obligations, the

    outcomes of the application of derivative moral

    values.

    Yet, they contradict the universal moral value of the

    sanctity of life and the universal moral obligation not to

    kill.

    Nature, Aesthetics, Pleasure, and Ethics

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    The distinction often made between emotions and

    judgements gives rise to a host of conflicting accounts of

    morality. Yet, in the same way that the distinction

    “observer-observed” is false, so is the distinction between

    emotions and judgements. Emotions contain judgements

    and judgements are formed by both emotions and the

    ratio. Emotions are responses to sensa (see “The Manifold

    of Sense”) and inevitably incorporate judgements (and

    beliefs) about those sensa. Some of these judgements are

    inherent (the outcome of biological evolution), others

    cultural, some unconscious, others conscious, and the

    result of personal experience. Judgements, on the other

    hand, are not compartmentalized. They vigorously interact

    with our emotions as they form.

    The source of this artificial distinction is the confusion

    between moral and natural laws.

    We differentiate among four kinds of “right” and “good”.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/sense.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/sense.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/sense.html

    THE NATURAL GOOD

    There is “right” in the mathematical, physical, or

    pragmatic sense. It is “right” to do something in a certain

    way. In other words, it is viable, practical, functional, it

    coheres with the world. Similarly, we say that it is “good”

    to do the “right” thing and that we “ought to” do it. It is

    the kind of “right” and “good” that compel us to act

    because we “ought to”. If we adopt a different course, if

    we neglect, omit, or refuse to act in the “right” and “good”

    way, as we “ought to” – we are punished. Nature herself

    penalizes such violations. The immutable laws of nature

    are the source of the “rightness” and “goodness” of these

    courses of action. We are compelled to adopt them –

    because we have no other CHOICE. If we construct a

    bridge in the “right” and “good” way, as we “ought to” – it

    will survive. Otherwise, the laws of nature will make it

    collapse and, thus, punish us. We have no choice in the

    matter. The laws of nature constrain our moral principles

    as well.

    THE MORAL GOOD

    This lack of choice stands in stark contrast to the “good”

    and “right” of morality. The laws of morality cannot be

    compared to the laws of nature – nor are they variants or

    derivatives thereof. The laws of nature leave us no choice.

    The laws of morality rely on our choice.

    Yet, the identical vocabulary and syntax we successfully

    employ in both cases (the pragmatic and the moral) –

    “right action”, “good”, and “ought to” – surely signify a

    deep and hidden connection between our dictated

    reactions to the laws of nature and our chosen reactions to

    the laws of morality (i.e., our reactions to the laws of Man

    or God)? Perhaps the principles and rules of morality

    ARE laws of nature – but with choice added? Modern

    physics incorporates deterministic theories (Newton’s,

    Einstein’s) – and theories involving probability and choice

    (Quantum Mechanics and its interpretations, especially

    the Copenhagen interpretation). Why can’t we conceive of

    moral laws as private cases (involving choice,

    judgements, beliefs, and emotions) of natural laws?

    THE HEDONISTIC GOOD

    If so, how can we account for the third, hedonistic, variant

    of “good”, “right”, and “ought to”? To live the “good” life

    may mean to maximize one’s utility (i.e., happiness, or

    pleasure) – but not necessarily to maximize overall utility.

    In other words, living the good life is not always a moral

    pursuit (if we apply to it Utilitarian or Consequentialist

    yardsticks). Yet, here, too, we use the same syntax and

    vocabulary. We say that we want to live the “good” life

    and to do so, there is a “right action”, which we “ought to”

    pursue. Is hedonism a private case of the Laws of Nature

    as well? This would be going too far. Is it a private case of

    the rules or principles of Morality? It could be – but need

    not be. Still, the principle of utility has place in every

    cogent description of morality.

    THE AESTHETIC GOOD

    A fourth kind of “good” is of the aesthetic brand. The

    language of aesthetic judgement is identical to the

    languages of physics, morality, and hedonism. Aesthetic

    values sound strikingly like moral ones and both

    resemble, structurally, the laws of nature. We say that

    beauty is “right” (symmetric, etc.), that we “ought to”

    maximize beauty – and this leads to the right

    action.

    Replace “beauty” with “good” in any aesthetic statement –

    and one gets a moral statement. Moral, natural, aesthetic,

    and hedonistic statements are all mutually convertible.

    Moreover, an aesthetic experience often leads to moral

    action.

    AN INTERACTIVE FRAMEWORK

    It is safe to say that, when we wish to discuss the nature of

    “good” and “right”, the Laws of Nature serve as the

    privileged frame of reference. They delimit and constrain

    the set of possible states – pragmatic and moral. No moral,

    aesthetic, or hedonistic principle or rule can defy, negate,

    suspend, or ignore the Laws of Nature. They are the

    source of everything that is “good” and “right”. Thus, the

    language we use to describe all instances of “good” and

    “right” is “natural”. Human choice, of course, does not

    exist as far as the Laws of Nature go.

    Nature is beautiful – symmetric, elegant, and

    parsimonious. Aesthetic values and aesthetic judgements

    of “good” (i.e., beautiful) and “right” rely heavily on the

    attributes of Nature. Inevitably, they employ the same

    vocabulary and syntax. Aesthetics is the bridge between

    the functional or correct “good” and “right” – and the

    hedonistic “good” and “right”.

    Aesthetics is the first order of the interaction between the

    WORLD and the MIND. Here, choice is very limited. It is

    not possible to “choose” something to be beautiful. It is

    either beautiful or it is not (regardless of the objective or

    subjective source of the aesthetic judgement).

    The hedonist is primarily concerned with the

    maximization of his happiness and pleasure. But such

    outcomes can be secured only by adhering to aesthetic

    values, by rendering aesthetic judgements, and by

    maintaining aesthetic standards. The hedonist craves

    beauty, pursues perfection, avoids the ugly – in short, the

    hedonist is an aesthete. Hedonism is the application of

    aesthetic rules, principles, values, and judgements in a

    social and cultural setting. Hedonism is aesthetics in

    context – the context of being human in a society of

    humans. The hedonist has a limited, binary, choice –

    between being a hedonist and not being one.

    From here it is one step to morality. The principle of

    individual utility which underlies hedonism can be easily

    generalized to encompass Humanity as a whole. The

    social and cultural context is indispensable – there cannot

    be meaningful morality outside society. A Robinson

    Crusoe – at least until he spotted Friday – is an a-moral

    creature. Thus, morality is generalized hedonism with the

    added (and crucial) feature of free will and (for all

    practical purposes) unrestricted choice. It is what makes

    us really human.

    On Being Human
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
    Also Read:
    The Aborted Contract

    In Our Own Image – Cloning

    Turing Machines and Universes

    Death and the Question of Identity

    The Shattered Identity

    Are we human because of unique traits and attributes not

    shared with either animal or machine? The definition of

    “human” is circular: we are human by virtue of the

    properties that make us human (i.e., distinct from animal

    and machine). It is a definition by negation: that which

    separates us from animal and machine is our “human-

    ness”.

    We are human because we are not animal, nor machine.

    But such thinking has been rendered progressively less

    tenable by the advent of evolutionary and neo-

    evolutionary theories which postulate a continuum in

    nature between animals and Man.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/abort.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cloning.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/turing.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/death.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/identity.html

    Our uniqueness is partly quantitative and partly

    qualitative. Many animals are capable of cognitively

    manipulating symbols and using tools. Few are as adept at

    it as we are. These are easily quantifiable differences –

    two of many.

    Qualitative differences are a lot more difficult to

    substantiate. In the absence of privileged access to the

    animal mind, we cannot and don’t know if animals feel

    guilt, for instance. Do animals love? Do they have a

    concept of sin? What about object permanence, meaning,

    reasoning, self-awareness, critical thinking? Individuality?

    Emotions? Empathy? Is artificial intelligence (AI) an

    oxymoron? A machine that passes the Turing Test may

    well be described as “human”. But is it really? And if it is

    not – why isn’t

    it?

    Literature is full of stories of monsters – Frankenstein, the

    Golem – and androids or anthropoids. Their behavior is

    more “humane” than the humans around them. This,

    perhaps, is what really sets humans apart: their behavioral

    unpredictability. It is yielded by the interaction between

    Mankind’s underlying immutable genetically-determined

    nature – and Man’s kaleidoscopically changing

    environments.

    The Constructivists even claim that Human Nature is a

    mere cultural artefact. Sociobiologists, on the other hand,

    are determinists. They believe that human nature – being

    the inevitable and inexorable outcome of our bestial

    ancestry – cannot be the subject of moral judgment.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/empathy.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/turing.html

    An improved Turing Test would look for baffling and

    erratic patterns of misbehavior to identify humans. Pico

    della Mirandola wrote in “Oration on the Dignity of Man”

    that Man was born without a form and can mould and

    transform – actually, create – himself at will. Existence

    precedes essence, said the Existentialists centuries later.

    The one defining human characteristic may be our

    awareness of our mortality. The automatically triggered,

    “fight or flight”, battle for survival is common to all living

    things (and to appropriately programmed machines). Not

    so the catalytic effects of imminent death. These are

    uniquely human. The appreciation of the fleeting

    translates into aesthetics, the uniqueness of our ephemeral

    life breeds morality, and the scarcity of time gives rise to

    ambition and creativity.

    In an infinite life, everything materializes at one time or

    another, so the concept of choice is spurious. The

    realization of our finiteness forces us to choose among

    alternatives. This act of selection is predicated upon the

    existence of “free will”. Animals and machines are

    thought to be devoid of choice, slaves to their genetic or

    human programming.

    Yet, all these answers to the question: “What does it mean

    to be human” – are lacking.

    The set of attributes we designate as human is subject to

    profound alteration. Drugs, neuroscience, introspection,

    and experience all cause irreversible changes in these

    traits and characteristics. The accumulation of these

    changes can lead, in principle, to the emergence of new

    properties, or to the abolition of old ones.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/death.html

    Animals and machines are not supposed to possess free

    will or exercise it. What, then, about fusions of machines

    and humans (bionics)? At which point does a human turn

    into a machine? And why should we assume that free will

    ceases to exist at that – rather arbitrary – point?

    Introspection – the ability to construct self-referential and

    recursive models of the world – is supposed to be a

    uniquely human quality. What about introspective

    machines? Surely, say the critics, such machines are

    PROGRAMMED to introspect, as opposed to humans. To

    qualify as introspection, it must be WILLED, they

    continue. Yet, if introspection is willed – WHO wills it?

    Self-willed introspection leads to infinite regression and

    formal logical paradoxes.

    Moreover, the notion – if not the formal concept – of

    “human” rests on many hidden assumptions and

    conventions.

    Political correctness notwithstanding – why presume that

    men and women (or different races) are identically

    human? Aristotle thought they were not. A lot separates

    males from females – genetically (both genotype and

    phenotype) and environmentally (culturally). What is

    common to these two sub-species that makes them both

    “human”?

    Can we conceive of a human without body (i.e., a

    Platonian Form, or soul)? Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas

    think not. A soul has no existence separate from the body.

    A machine-supported energy field with mental states

    similar to ours today – would it be considered human?

    What about someone in a state of coma – is he or she (or

    it) fully human?

    Is a new born baby human – or, at least, fully human – and,

    if so, in which sense? What about a future human race –

    whose features would be unrecognizable to us? Machine-

    based intelligence – would it be thought of as human? If

    yes, when would it be considered human?

    In all these deliberations, we may be confusing “human”

    with “person”. The former is a private case of the latter.

    Locke’s person is a moral agent, a being responsible for its

    actions. It is constituted by the continuity of its mental

    states accessible to introspection.

    Locke’s is a functional definition. It readily accommodates

    non-human persons (machines, energy matrices) if the

    functional conditions are satisfied. Thus, an android which

    meets the prescribed requirements is more human than a

    brain dead person.

    Descartes’ objection that one cannot specify conditions of

    singularity and identity over time for disembodied souls is

    right only if we assume that such “souls” possess no

    energy. A bodiless intelligent energy matrix which

    maintains its form and identity over time is conceivable.

    Certain AI and genetic software programs already do it.

    Strawson is Cartesian and Kantian in his definition of a

    “person” as a “primitive”. Both the corporeal predicates

    and those pertaining to mental states apply equally,

    simultaneously, and inseparably to all the individuals of

    that type of entity. Human beings are one such entity.

    Some, like Wiggins, limit the list of possible persons to

    animals – but this is far from rigorously necessary and is

    unduly restrictive.

    The truth is probably in a synthesis:

    A person is any type of fundamental and irreducible entity

    whose typical physical individuals (i.e., members) are

    capable of continuously experiencing a range of states of

    consciousness and permanently having a list of

    psychological attributes.

    This definition allows for non-animal persons and

    recognizes the personhood of a brain damaged human

    (“capable of experiencing”). It also incorporates Locke’s

    view of humans as possessing an ontological status

    similar to “clubs” or “nations” – their personal identity

    consists of a variety of interconnected psychological

    continuities.

    The Encroachment of the Public
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    Also Read

    The Law of Technology and the Technology of Law –

    An Epistolary Dialogue

    The Ghost in the Net – An Epistolary Dialogue

    As Aristotle and John Stuart Mill observed, the private

    sphere sets limits, both normative and empirical, to the

    rights, powers, and obligations of others. The myriad

    forms of undue invasion of the private sphere – such as

    rape, burglary, or eavesdropping – are all crimes. Even the

    state – this monopolist of legal violence – respects these

    boundaries. When it fails to honor the distinction between

    public and private – when it is authoritarian or totalitarian

    – it loses its legitimacy.

    Alas, this vital separation of realms is eroding fast.

    In theory, private life is insulated and shielded from social

    pressures, the ambit of norms and laws, and even the

    strictures of public morality. Reality, though, is different.

    The encroachment of the public is inexorable and,

    probably, irreversible. The individual is forced to share,

    consent to, or merely obey a panoply of laws, norms, and

    regulations not only in his or her relationships with others

    – but also when solitary.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/lawtech.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/lawtech.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/ghost.html

    Failure to comply – and to be seen to be conforming –

    leads to dire consequences. In a morbid twist, public

    morality is now synonymous with social orthodoxy,

    political authority, and the exercise of police powers. The

    quiddity, remit, and attendant rights of the private sphere

    are now determined publicly, by the state.

    In the modern world , privacy – the freedom to withhold

    or divulge information – and autonomy – the liberty to act

    in certain ways when not in public – are illusory in that

    their scope and essence are ever-shifting, reversible, and

    culture-dependent. They both are perceived as public

    concessions – not as the inalienable (though, perhaps, as

    Judith Jarvis Thomson observes, derivative) rights that

    they are.

    The trend from non-intrusiveness to wholesale

    invasiveness is clear:

    Only two hundred years ago, the legal regulation of

    economic relations between consenting adults – a

    quintessentially private matter – would have been

    unthinkable and bitterly resisted. Only a century ago, no

    bureaucrat would have dared intervene in domestic

    affairs. A Man’s home was, indeed, his castle.

    Nowadays, the right – let alone dwindling technological

    ability – to maintain a private sphere is multiply contested

    and challenged. Feminists, such as Catharine MacKinnon,

    regard it as a patriarchal stratagem to perpetuate abusive

    male domination. Conservatives blame it for mounting

    crime and terrorism. Sociologists – and the Church – worry

    about social atomization and alienation.

    Consequently, today, both one’s business and one’s family

    are open books to the authorities, the media, community

    groups, non-governmental organizations, and assorted

    busybodies.

    Which leads us back to privacy, the topic of this essay. It

    is often confused with autonomy. The private sphere

    comprises both. Yet, the former has little to do with the

    latter . Even the acute minds of the Supreme Court of the

    United States keep getting it wrong.

    In 1890, Justice Louise Brandeis (writing with Samuel

    Warren) correctly summed up privacy rights as “the right

    to be left alone” – that is, the right to control information

    about oneself.

    But, nearly a century later, in 1973, in the celebrated case

    of Roe vs. Wade, the U.S. Supreme Court, mixing up

    privacy and autonomy, found some state regulation of

    abortion to be in violation of a woman’s constitutional

    right of privacy, implicit in the liberty guarantee of the

    Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

    But if unrelated to autonomy – what is privacy all about?

    As Julie Inness and many others note, privacy – the

    exclusive access to information – is tightly linked to

    intimacy. The more intimate the act – excretion, ill-health,

    and sex come to mind – the more closely we safeguard its

    secrets. By keeping back such data, we show

    consideration for the sensitivities of other people and we

    enhance our own uniqueness and the special nature of our

    close relationships.

    Privacy is also inextricably linked to personal safety.

    Withholding information makes us less vulnerable to

    abuse and exploitation. Our privileged access to some data

    guarantees our wellbeing, longevity, status, future, and the

    welfare of our family and community. Just consider the

    consequences of giving potentially unscrupulous others

    access to our bank accounts, credit card numbers, PIN

    codes, medical records, industrial and military secrets, or

    investment portfolios.

    Last, but by no way least, the successful defense of one’s

    privacy sustains one’s self-esteem – or what Brandeis and

    Warren called “inviolate personality”. The invasion of

    privacy provokes an upwelling of shame and indignation

    and feelings of indignity, violation, helplessness, a

    diminished sense of self-worth, and the triggering of a

    host of primitive defense mechanisms. Intrusion upon

    one’s private sphere is, as Edward J. Bloustein observes,

    traumatic.

    Incredibly, modern technology has conspired to do just

    that. Reality TV shows, caller ID, electronic monitoring,

    computer viruses (especially worms and Trojans),

    elaborate databases, marketing profiles, Global

    Positioning System (GPS)-enabled cell phones, wireless

    networks, smart cards – are all intrusive and counter-

    privacy.

    Add social policies and trends to the mixture – police

    profiling, mandatory drug-testing, workplace keylogging,

    the nanny (welfare) state, traffic surveillance, biometric

    screening, electronic bracelets – and the long-heralded

    demise of privacy is no longer mere scaremongering.

    As privacy fades – so do intimacy, personal safety, and

    self-esteem (mental health) and with them social

    cohesion. The ills of anomic modernity – alienation,

    violence, and crime, to mention but three – are, therefore,

    directly attributable to diminishing privacy. This is the

    irony: that privacy is increasingly breached in the name of

    added security (counter-terrorism or crime busting). We

    seem to be undermining our societies in order to make

    them safer.

    And Then There Were Too Many
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    The latest census in Ukraine revealed an apocalyptic drop

    of 10% in its population – from 52.5 million a decade ago

    to a mere 47.5 million last year. Demographers predict a

    precipitous decline of one third in Russia’s impoverished,

    inebriated, disillusioned, and ageing citizenry. Births in

    many countries in the rich, industrialized, West are below

    the replacement rate. These bastions of conspicuous

    affluence are shriveling.

    Scholars and decision-makers – once terrified by the

    Malthusian dystopia of a “population bomb” – are more

    sanguine now. Advances in agricultural technology

    eradicated hunger even in teeming places like India and

    China. And then there is the old idea of progress: birth

    rates tend to decline with higher education levels and

    growing incomes. Family planning has had resounding

    successes in places as diverse as Thailand, China, and

    western Africa.

    In the near past, fecundity used to compensate for infant

    mortality. As the latter declined – so did the former.

    Children are means of production in many destitute

    countries.

    Hence the inordinately large families of the past

    – a form of insurance against the economic outcomes of

    the inevitable demise of some of one’s off-spring.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    Yet, despite these trends, the world’s populace is

    augmented by 80 million people annually. All of them are

    born to the younger inhabitants of the more penurious

    corners of the Earth. There were only 1 billion people

    alive in 1804. The number doubled a century later.

    But our last billion – the sixth – required only 12 fertile

    years. The entire population of Germany is added every

    half a decade to both India and China. Clearly, Mankind’s

    growth is out of control, as affirmed in the 1994 Cairo

    International Conference on Population and Development.

    Dozens of millions of people regularly starve – many of

    them to death. In only one corner of the Earth – southern

    Africa – food aid is the sole subsistence of entire

    countries. More than 18 million people in Zambia,

    Malawi, and Angola survived on charitable donations in

    1992. More than 10 million expect the same this year,

    among them the emaciated denizens of erstwhile food

    exporter, Zimbabwe.

    According to Medecins Sans Frontiere, AIDS kills 3

    million people a year, Tuberculosis another 2 million.

    Malaria decimates 2 people every minute. More than 14

    million people fall prey to parasitic and infectious

    diseases every year – 90% of them in the developing

    countries.

    Millions emigrate every year in search of a better life.

    These massive shifts are facilitated by modern modes of

    transportation. But, despite these tectonic relocations – and

    despite famine, disease, and war, the classic Malthusian

    regulatory mechanisms – the depletion of natural resources

    – from arable land to water – is undeniable and gargantuan.

    Our pressing environmental issues – global warming,

    water stress, salinization, desertification, deforestation,

    pollution, loss of biological diversity – and our ominous

    social ills – crime at the forefront – are traceable to one,

    politically incorrect, truth:

    There are too many of us. We are way too numerous. The

    population load is unsustainable. We, the survivors, would

    be better off if others were to perish. Should population

    growth continue unabated – we are all doomed.

    Doomed to what?

    Numerous Cassandras and countless Jeremiads have been

    falsified by history. With proper governance, scientific

    research, education, affordable medicines, effective

    family planning, and economic growth – this planet can

    support even 10-12 billion people. We are not at risk of

    physical extinction and never have been.

    What is hazarded is not our life – but our quality of life.

    As any insurance actuary will attest, we are governed by

    statistical datasets.

    Consider this single fact:

    About 1% of the population suffer from the perniciously

    debilitating and all-pervasive mental health disorder,

    schizophrenia. At the beginning of the 20th century, there

    were 16.5 million schizophrenics – nowadays there are 64

    million. Their impact on friends, family, and colleagues is

    exponential – and incalculable. This is not a merely

    quantitative leap. It is a qualitative phase transition.

    Or this:

    Large populations lead to the emergence of high density

    urban centers. It is inefficient to cultivate ever smaller

    plots of land. Surplus manpower moves to centers of

    industrial production. A second wave of internal migrants

    caters to their needs, thus spawning a service sector.

    Network effects generate excess capital and a virtuous

    cycle of investment, employment, and consumption

    ensues.

    But over-crowding breeds violence (as has been

    demonstrated in experiments with mice). The sheer

    numbers involved serve to magnify and amplify social

    anomies, deviate behaviour, and antisocial traits. In the

    city, there are more criminals, more perverts, more

    victims, more immigrants, and more racists per square

    mile.

    Moreover, only a planned and orderly urbanization is

    desirable. The blights that pass for cities in most third

    world countries are the outgrowth of neither premeditation

    nor method. These mega-cities are infested with non-

    disposed of waste and prone to natural catastrophes and

    epidemics.

    No one can vouchsafe for a “critical mass” of humans, a

    threshold beyond which the species will implode and

    vanish.

    Luckily, the ebb and flow of human numbers is subject to

    three regulatory demographic mechanisms, the combined

    action of which gives hope.

    The Malthusian Mechanism

    Limited resources lead to wars, famine, and diseases and,

    thus, to a decrease in human numbers. Mankind has done

    well to check famine, fend off disease, and staunch war.

    But to have done so without a commensurate policy of

    population control was irresponsible.

    The Assimilative Mechanism

    Mankind is not divorced from nature. Humanity is

    destined to be impacted by its choices and by the

    reverberations of its actions. Damage caused to the

    environment haunts – in a complex feedback loop – the

    perpetrators.

    Examples:

    Immoderate use of antibiotics leads to the eruption of

    drug-resistant strains of pathogens. A myriad types of

    cancer are caused by human pollution. Man is the victim

    of its own destructive excesses.

    The Cognitive Mechanism

    Humans intentionally limit the propagation of their race

    through family planning, abortion, and contraceptives.

    Genetic engineering will likely intermesh with these to

    produce “enhanced” or “designed” progeny to

    specifications.

    We must stop procreating. Or, else, pray for a reduction

    in our numbers.

    This could be achieved benignly, for instance by

    colonizing space, or the ocean depths – both remote and

    technologically unfeasible possibilities.

    Yet, the alternative is cataclysmic. Unintended wars,

    rampant disease, and lethal famines will ultimately trim

    our numbers – no matter how noble our intentions and

    how diligent our efforts to curb them.

    Is this a bad thing?

    Not necessarily. To my mind, even a Malthusian

    resolution is preferable to the alternative of slow decay,

    uniform impecuniosity, and perdition in instalments – an

    alternative made inexorable by our collective

    irresponsibility and denial.

    Racing Down

    Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    “It is clear that modern medicine has created a serious

    dilemma … In the past, there were many children who

    never survived – they succumbed to various diseases …

    But in a sense modern medicine has put natural selection

    out of commission. Something that has helped one

    individual over a serious illness can in the long run

    contribute to weakening the resistance of the whole

    human race to certain diseases. If we pay absolutely no

    attention to what is called hereditary hygiene, we could

    find ourselves facing a degeneration of the human race.

    Mankind’s hereditary potential for resisting serious

    disease will be weakened.”

    (Jostein Gaarder in “Sophie’s World”, a bestselling

    philosophy textbook for adolescents published in Oslo,

    Norway, in 1991 and, afterwards, throughout the world,

    having been translated to dozens of languages)

    The Nazis regarded the murder of the feeble-minded and

    the mentally insane – intended to purify the race and

    maintain hereditary hygiene – as a form of euthanasia.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    German doctors were enthusiastic proponents of an

    eugenics movements rooted in 19th century social

    Darwinism. Luke Gormally writes, in his essay “Walton,

    Davies, and Boyd” (published in “Euthanasia Examined –

    Ethical, Clinical, and Legal Perspectives”, ed. John

    Keown, Cambridge University Press, 1995):

    “When the jurist Karl Binding and the psychiatrist Alfred

    Hoche published their tract The Permission to Destroy

    Life that is Not Worth Living in 1920 … their motive was

    to rid society of the ‘human ballast and enormous

    economic burden’ of care for the mentally ill, the

    handicapped, retarded and deformed children, and the

    incurably ill. But the reason they invoked to justify the

    killing of human beings who fell into these categories was

    that the lives of such human beings were ‘not worth

    living’, were ‘devoid of value'”

    It is this association with the hideous Nazi regime that

    gave eugenics – a term coined by a relative of Charles

    Darwin, Sir Francis Galton, in 1883 – its bad name.

    Richard Lynn, of the University of Ulster of North

    Ireland, thinks that this recoil resulted in “Dysgenics – the

    genetic deterioration of modern (human) population”, as

    the title of his controversial tome puts it.

    The crux of the argument for eugenics is that a host of

    technological, cultural, and social developments conspired

    to give rise to negative selection of the weakest, least

    intelligent, sickest, the habitually criminal, the sexually

    deviant, the mentally-ill, and the least adapted.

    Contraception is more widely used by the affluent and the

    well-educated than by the destitute and dull. Birth control

    as practiced in places like China distorted both the sex

    distribution in the cities – and increased the weight of the

    rural population (rural couples in China are allowed to

    have two children rather than the urban one).

    Modern medicine and the welfare state collaborate in

    sustaining alive individuals – mainly the mentally

    retarded, the mentally ill, the sick, and the genetically

    defective – who would otherwise have been culled by

    natural selection to the betterment of the entire species.

    Eugenics may be based on a literal understanding of

    Darwin’s metaphor.

    The 2002 edition of the Encyclopedia Britannica has this

    to say:

    “Darwin’s description of the process of natural selection as

    the survival of the fittest in the struggle for life is a

    metaphor. “Struggle” does not necessarily mean

    contention, strife, or combat; “survival” does not mean

    that ravages of death are needed to make the selection

    effective; and “fittest” is virtually never a single optimal

    genotype but rather an array of genotypes that collectively

    enhance population survival rather than extinction. All

    these considerations are most apposite to consideration of

    natural selection in humans. Decreasing infant and

    childhood mortality rates do not necessarily mean that

    natural selection in the human species no longer operates.

    Theoretically, natural selection could be very effective if

    all the children born reached maturity.

    http://www.britannica.com/

    Two conditions are needed to make this theoretical

    possibility realized: first, variation in the number of

    children per family and, second, variation correlated with

    the genetic properties of the parents. Neither of these

    conditions is farfetched.”

    The eugenics debate is only the visible extremity of the

    Man vs. Nature conundrum. Have we truly conquered

    nature and extracted ourselves from its determinism?

    Have we graduated from natural to cultural evolution,

    from natural to artificial selection, and from genes to

    memes?

    Does the evolutionary process culminate in a being that

    transcends its genetic baggage, that programs and charts

    its future, and that allows its weakest and sickest to

    survive? Supplanting the imperative of the survival of the

    fittest with a culturally-sensitive principle may be the

    hallmark of a successful evolution, rather than the

    beginning of an inexorable decline.

    The eugenics movement turns this argument on its head.

    They accept the premise that the contribution of natural

    selection to the makeup of future human generations is

    glacial and negligible. But they reject the conclusion that,

    having ridden ourselves of its tyranny, we can now let the

    weak and sick among us survive and multiply. Rather,

    they propose to replace natural selection with eugenics.

    But who, by which authority, and according to what

    guidelines will administer this man-made culling and

    decide who is to live and who is to die, who is to breed

    and who may not? Why select by intelligence and not by

    courtesy or altruism or church-going – or al of them

    together? It is here that eugenics fails miserably.

    Should the criterion be physical, like in ancient Sparta?

    Should it be mental? Should IQ determine one’s fate – or

    social status or wealth? Different answers yield disparate

    eugenic programs and target dissimilar groups in the

    population.

    Aren’t eugenic criteria liable to be unduly influenced by

    fashion and cultural bias? Can we agree on a universal

    eugenic agenda in a world as ethnically and culturally

    diverse as ours? If we do get it wrong – and the chances

    are overwhelming – will we not damage our gene pool

    irreparably and, with it, the future of our species?

    And even if many will avoid a slippery slope leading from

    eugenics to active extermination of “inferior” groups in

    the general population – can we guarantee that everyone

    will? How to prevent eugenics from being appropriated by

    an intrusive, authoritarian, or even murderous state?

    Modern eugenicists distance themselves from the crude

    methods adopted at the beginning of the last century by 29

    countries, including Germany, The United States, Canada,

    Switzerland, Austria, Venezuela, Estonia, Argentina,

    Norway, Denmark, Sweden (until 1976), Brazil, Italy,

    Greece, and Spain.

    They talk about free contraceptives for low-IQ women,

    vasectomies or tubal ligations for criminals, sperm banks

    with contributions from high achievers, and incentives for

    college students to procreate. Modern genetic engineering

    and biotechnology are readily applicable to eugenic

    projects. Cloning can serve to preserve the genes of the

    fittest. Embryo selection and prenatal diagnosis of

    genetically diseased embryos can reduce the number of

    the unfit.

    But even these innocuous variants of eugenics fly in the

    face of liberalism. Inequality, claim the proponents of

    hereditary amelioration, is genetic, not environmental. All

    men are created unequal and as much subject to the

    natural laws of heredity as are cows and bees. Inferior

    people give birth to inferior offspring and, thus, propagate

    their inferiority.

    Even if this were true – which is at best debatable – the

    question is whether the inferior specimen of our species

    possess the inalienable right to reproduce? If society is to

    bear the costs of over-population – social welfare, medical

    care, daycare centers – then society has the right to

    regulate procreation. But does it have the right to act

    discriminately in doing so?

    Another dilemma is whether we have the moral right – let

    alone the necessary knowledge – to interfere with natural

    as well as social and demographic trends. Eugenicists

    counter that contraception and indiscriminate medicine

    already do just that. Yet, studies show that the more

    affluent and educated a population becomes – the less

    fecund it is. Birth rates throughout the world have

    dropped dramatically already.

    Instead of culling the great unwashed and the unworthy –

    wouldn’t it be a better idea to educate them (or their off-

    spring) and provide them with economic opportunities

    (euthenics rather than eugenics)? Human populations

    seem to self-regulate. A gentle and persistent nudge in the

    right direction – of increased affluence and better

    schooling – might achieve more than a hundred eugenic

    programs, voluntary or compulsory.

    That eugenics presents itself not merely as a biological-

    social agenda, but as a panacea, ought to arouse suspicion.

    The typical eugenics text reads more like a catechism than

    a reasoned argument. Previous all-encompassing and

    omnicompetent plans tended to end traumatically –

    especially when they contrasted a human elite with a

    dispensable underclass of persons.

    Above all, eugenics is about human hubris. To presume to

    know better than the lottery of life is haughty. Modern

    medicine largely obviates the need for eugenics in that it

    allows even genetically defective people to lead pretty

    normal lives. Of course, Man himself – being part of

    Nature – may be regarded as nothing more than an agent

    of natural selection. Still, many of the arguments

    advanced in favor of eugenics can be turned against it

    with embarrassing ease.

    Consider sick children. True, they are a burden to society

    and a probable menace to the gene pool of the species.

    But they also inhibit further reproduction in their family

    by consuming the financial and mental resources of the

    parents. Their genes – however flawed – contribute to

    genetic diversity. Even a badly mutated phenotype

    sometimes yields precious scientific knowledge and an

    interesting genotype.

    The implicit Weltbild of eugenics is static – but the real

    world is dynamic. There is no such thing as a “correct”

    genetic makeup towards which we must all strive. A

    combination of genes may be perfectly adaptable to one

    environment – but woefully inadequate in another. It is

    therefore prudent to encourage genetic diversity or

    polymorphism.

    The more rapidly the world changes, the greater the value

    of mutations of all sorts. One never knows whether

    today’s maladaptation will not prove to be tomorrow’s

    winner. Ecosystems are invariably comprised of niches

    and different genes – even mutated ones – may fit different

    niches.

    In the 18th century most peppered moths in Britain were

    silvery gray, indistinguishable from lichen-covered trunks

    of silver birches – their habitat. Darker moths were

    gobbled up by rapacious birds. Their mutated genes

    proved to be lethal. As soot from sprouting factories

    blackened these trunks – the very same genes, hitherto

    fatal, became an unmitigated blessing. The blacker

    specimen survived while their hitherto perfectly adapted

    fairer brethren perished (“industrial melanism”). This

    mode of natural selection is called directional.

    Moreover, “bad” genes are often connected to “desirable

    genes” (pleitropy). Sickle cell anemia protects certain

    African tribes against malaria. This is called “diversifying

    or disruptive natural selection”. Artificial selection can

    thus fast deteriorate into adverse selection due to

    ignorance.

    Modern eugenics relies on statistics. It is no longer

    concerned with causes – but with phenomena and the

    likely effects of intervention. If the adverse traits of off-

    spring and parents are strongly correlated – then

    preventing parents with certain undesirable qualities from

    multiplying will surely reduce the incidence of said

    dispositions in the general population. Yet, correlation

    does not necessarily imply causation. The manipulation of

    one parameter of the correlation does not inevitably alter

    it – or the incidence of the outcome.

    Eugenicists often hark back to wisdom garnered by

    generations of breeders and farmers. But the unequivocal

    lesson of thousands of years of artificial selection is that

    cross-breeding (hybridization) – even of two lines of

    inferior genetic stock – yields valuable genotypes. Inter-

    marriage between races, groups in the population, ethnic

    groups, and clans is thus bound to improve the species’

    chances of survival more than any eugenic scheme.

    The Myth of the Right to Life
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    I. The Right to Life

    Generations of malleable Israeli children are brought up

    on the story of the misnamed Jewish settlement Tel-Hai

    (“Mount of Life”), Israel’s Alamo. There, among the

    picturesque valleys of the Galilee, a one-armed hero

    named Joseph Trumpeldor is said to have died, eight

    decades ago, from an Arab stray bullet, mumbling: “It is

    good to die for our country.” Judaism is dubbed “A

    Teaching of Life” – but it would seem that the sanctity of

    life can and does take a back seat to some overriding

    values.

    The right to life – at least of human beings – is a rarely

    questioned fundamental moral principle. In Western

    cultures, it is assumed to be inalienable and indivisible

    (i.e., monolithic). Yet, it is neither. Even if we accept the

    axiomatic – and therefore arbitrary – source of this right,

    we are still faced with intractable dilemmas. All said, the

    right to life may be nothing more than a cultural construct,

    dependent on social mores, historical contexts, and

    exegetic systems.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    Rights – whether moral or legal – impose obligations or

    duties on third parties towards the right-holder. One has a

    right AGAINST other people and thus can prescribe to

    them certain obligatory behaviors and proscribe certain

    acts or omissions. Rights and duties are two sides of the

    same Janus-like ethical coin.

    This duality confuses people. They often erroneously

    identify rights with their attendant duties or obligations,

    with the morally decent, or even with the morally

    permissible. One’s rights inform other people how they

    MUST behave towards one – not how they SHOULD or

    OUGHT to act morally. Moral behavior is not dependent

    on the existence of a right. Obligations are.

    To complicate matters further, many apparently simple

    and straightforward rights are amalgams of more basic

    moral or legal principles. To treat such rights as unities is

    to mistreat them.

    Take the right to life. It is a compendium of no less than

    eight distinct rights: the right to be brought to life, the

    right to be born, the right to have one’s life maintained,

    the right not to be killed, the right to have one’s life

    saved, the right to save one’s life (wrongly reduced to the

    right to self-defense), the right to terminate one’s life, and

    the right to have one’s life terminated.

    None of these rights is self-evident, or unambiguous, or

    universal, or immutable, or automatically applicable. It is

    safe to say, therefore, that these rights are not primary as

    hitherto believed – but derivative.

    The Right to be Brought to Life

    In most moral systems – including all major religions and

    Western legal methodologies – it is life that gives rise to

    rights. The dead have rights only because of the existence

    of the living. Where there is no life – there are no rights.

    Stones have no rights (though many animists would find

    this statement abhorrent).

    Hence the vitriolic debate about cloning which involves

    denuding an unfertilized egg of its nucleus. Is there life in

    an egg or a sperm cell?

    That something exists, does not necessarily imply that it

    harbors life. Sand exists and it is inanimate. But what

    about things that exist and have the potential to develop

    life?

    No one disputes the existence of eggs and sperms –

    or their capacity to grow alive.

    Is the potential to be alive a legitimate source of rights?

    Does the egg have any rights, or, at the very least, the

    right to be brought to life (the right to become or to be)

    and thus to acquire rights? The much trumpeted right to

    acquire life pertains to an entity which exists but is not

    alive – an egg. It is, therefore, an unprecedented kind of

    right. Had such a right existed, it would have implied an

    obligation or duty to give life to the unborn and the not

    yet conceived.

    Clearly, life manifests, at the earliest, when an egg and a

    sperm unite at the moment of fertilization. Life is not a

    potential – it is a process triggered by an event. An

    unfertilized egg is neither a process – nor an event. It does

    not even possess the potential to become alive unless and

    until it is fertilized.

    The potential to become alive is not the ontological

    equivalent of actually being alive. A potential life cannot

    give rise to rights and obligations. The transition from

    potential to being is not trivial, nor is it automatic, or

    inevitable, or independent of context. Atoms of various

    elements have the potential to become an egg (or, for that

    matter, a human being) – yet no one would claim that they

    ARE an egg (or a human being), or that they should be

    treated as such (i.e., with the same rights

    and obligations).

    The Right to be Born

    While the right to be brought to life deals with potentials –

    the right to be born deals with actualities. When one or

    two adults voluntarily cause an egg to be fertilized by a

    sperm cell with the explicit intent and purpose of creating

    another life – the right to be born crystallizes. The

    voluntary and premeditated action of said adults amounts

    to a contract with the embryo – or rather, with society

    which stands in for the embryo.

    Henceforth, the embryo acquires the entire panoply of

    human rights: the right to be born, to be fed, sheltered, to

    be emotionally nurtured, to get an education, and so on.

    But what if the fertilization was either involuntary (rape)

    or unintentional (“accidental” pregnancy)?

    Is the embryo’s successful acquisition of rights dependent

    upon the nature of the conception? We deny criminals

    their loot as “fruits of the poisoned tree”. Why not deny an

    embryo his life if it is the outcome of a crime?

    The conventional response – that the embryo did not

    commit the crime or conspire in it – is inadequate. We

    would deny the poisoned fruits of crime to innocent

    bystanders as well. Would we allow a passerby to freely

    spend cash thrown out of an escape vehicle following a

    robbery?

    Even if we agree that the embryo has a right to be kept

    alive – this right cannot be held against his violated

    mother. It cannot oblige her to harbor this patently

    unwanted embryo. If it could survive outside the womb,

    this would have solved the moral dilemma. But it is

    dubious – to say the least – that it has a right to go on

    using the mother’s body, or resources, or to burden her in

    any way in order to sustain its own life.

    The Right to Have One’s Life Maintained

    This leads to a more general quandary. To what extent can

    one use other people’s bodies, their property, their time,

    their resources and to deprive them of pleasure, comfort,

    material possessions, income, or any other thing – in order

    to maintain one’s life?

    Even if it were possible in reality, it is indefensible to

    maintain that I have a right to sustain, improve, or prolong

    my life at another’s expense. I cannot demand – though I

    can morally expect – even a trivial and minimal sacrifice

    from another in order to prolong my life. I have no right to

    do so.

    Of course, the existence of an implicit, let alone explicit,

    contract between myself and another party would change

    the picture. The right to demand sacrifices commensurate

    with the provisions of the contract would then crystallize

    and create corresponding duties and obligations.

    No embryo has a right to sustain its life, maintain, or

    prolong it at its mother’s expense. This is true regardless

    of how insignificant the sacrifice required of her is.

    Yet, by knowingly and intentionally conceiving the

    embryo, the mother can be said to have signed a contract

    with it. The contract causes the right of the embryo to

    demand such sacrifices from his mother to crystallize. It

    also creates corresponding duties and obligations of the

    mother towards her embryo.

    We often find ourselves in a situation where we do not

    have a given right against other individuals – but we do

    possess this very same right against society. Society owes

    us what no constituent-individual does.

    Thus, we all have a right to sustain our lives, maintain,

    prolong, or even improve them at society’s expense – no

    matter how major and significant the resources required.

    Public hospitals, state pension schemes, and police forces

    may be needed in order to fulfill society’s obligations to

    prolong, maintain, and improve our lives – but fulfill them

    it must.

    Still, each one of us can sign a contract with society –

    implicitly or explicitly – and abrogate this right. One can

    volunteer to join the army. Such an act constitutes a

    contract in which the individual assumes the duty or

    obligation to give up his or her life.

    The Right not to be Killed

    It is commonly agreed that every person has the right not

    to be killed unjustly. Admittedly, what is just and what is

    unjust is determined by an ethical calculus or a social

    contract – both constantly in flux.

    Still, even if we assume an Archimedean immutable point

    of moral reference – does A’s right not to be killed mean

    that third parties are to refrain from enforcing the rights of

    other people against A? What if the only way to right

    wrongs committed by A against others – was to kill A?

    The moral obligation to right wrongs is about restoring the

    rights of the wronged.

    If the continued existence of A is predicated on the

    repeated and continuous violation of the rights of others –

    and these other people object to it – then A must be killed

    if that is the only way to right the wrong and re-assert the

    rights of A’s victims.

    The Right to have One’s Life Saved

    There is no such right because there is no moral obligation

    or duty to save a life. That people believe otherwise

    demonstrates the muddle between the morally

    commendable, desirable, and decent (“ought”, “should”)

    and the morally obligatory, the result of other people’s

    rights (“must”). In some countries, the obligation to save a

    life is codified in the law of the land. But legal rights and

    obligations do not always correspond to moral rights and

    obligations, or give rise to them.

    The Right to Save One’s Own Life

    One has a right to save one’s life by exercising self-

    defense or otherwise, by taking certain actions or by

    avoiding them. Judaism – as well as other religious, moral,

    and legal systems – accept that one has the right to kill a

    pursuer who knowingly and intentionally is bent on taking

    one’s life. Hunting down Osama bin-Laden in the wilds of

    Afghanistan is, therefore, morally acceptable (though not

    morally mandatory).

    But does one have the right to kill an innocent person who

    unknowingly and unintentionally threatens to take one’s

    life? An embryo sometimes threatens the life of the

    mother. Does she have a right to take its life? What about

    an unwitting carrier of the Ebola virus – do we have a

    right to terminate her life? For that matter, do we have a

    right to terminate her life even if there is nothing she

    could have done about it had she known about her

    condition?

    The Right to Terminate One’s Life

    There are many ways to terminate one’s life: self sacrifice,

    avoidable martyrdom, engaging in life risking activities,

    refusal to prolong one’s life through medical treatment,

    euthanasia, overdosing and self inflicted death that is the

    result of coercion. Like suicide, in all these – bar the last –

    a foreknowledge of the risk of death is present coupled

    with its acceptance. Does one have a right to take one’s

    life?

    The answer is: it depends. Certain cultures and societies

    encourage suicide. Both Japanese kamikaze and Jewish

    martyrs were extolled for their suicidal actions. Certain

    professions are knowingly life-threatening – soldiers,

    firemen, policemen. Certain industries – like the

    manufacture of armaments, cigarettes, and alcohol – boost

    overall mortality rates.

    In general, suicide is commended when it serves social

    ends, enhances the cohesion of the group, upholds its

    values, multiplies its wealth, or defends it from external

    and internal threats. Social structures and human

    collectives – empires, countries, firms, bands, institutions –

    often commit suicide. This is considered to be a healthy

    process.

    Thus, suicide came to be perceived as a social act. The

    flip-side of this perception is that life is communal

    property. Society has appropriated the right to foster

    suicide or to prevent it. It condemns individual suicidal

    entrepreneurship. Suicide, according to Thomas Aquinas,

    is unnatural. It harms the community and violates God’s

    property rights.

    In Judeo-Christian tradition, God is the owner of all souls.

    The soul is on deposit with us. The very right to use it, for

    however short a period, is a divine gift. Suicide, therefore,

    amounts to an abuse of God’s possession. Blackstone, the

    venerable codifier of British Law, concurred. The state,

    according to him, has a right to prevent and to punish

    suicide and attempted suicide. Suicide is self-murder, he

    wrote, and, therefore, a grave felony. In certain

    paternalistic countries, this still is the case.

    The Right to Have One’s Life Terminated

    The right to have one’s life terminated at will (euthanasia),

    is subject to social, ethical, and legal strictures. In some

    countries – such as the Netherlands – it is legal (and

    socially acceptable) to have one’s life terminated with the

    help of third parties given a sufficient deterioration in the

    quality of life and given the imminence of death. One has

    to be of sound mind and will one’s death knowingly,

    intentionally, repeatedly, and forcefully.

    II. Issues in the Calculus of

    Rights

    The Hierarchy of Rights

    The right to life supersedes – in Western moral and legal

    systems – all other rights. It overrules the right to one’s

    body, to comfort, to the avoidance of pain, or to

    ownership of property. Given such lack of equivocation,

    the amount of dilemmas and controversies surrounding

    the right to life is, therefore, surprising.

    When there is a clash between equally potent rights – for

    instance, the conflicting rights to life of two people – we

    can decide among them randomly (by flipping a coin, or

    casting dice). Alternatively, we can add and subtract

    rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic.

    Thus, if the continued life of an embryo or a fetus

    threatens the mother’s life – that is, assuming,

    controversially, that both of them have an equal right to

    life – we can decide to kill the fetus. By adding to the

    mother’s right to life her right to her own body we

    outweigh the fetus’ right to life.

    The Difference between Killing and Letting Die

    Counterintuitively, there is a moral gulf between killing

    (taking a life) and letting die (not saving a life). The right

    not to be killed is undisputed. There is no right to have

    one’s own life saved. Where there is a right – and only

    where there is one – there is an obligation. Thus, while

    there is an obligation not to kill – there is no obligation to

    save a life.

    Killing the Innocent

    The life of a Victim (V) is sometimes threatened by the

    continued existence of an innocent person (IP), a person

    who cannot be held guilty of V’s ultimate death even

    though he caused it. IP is not guilty of dispatching V

    because he hasn’t intended to kill V, nor was he aware that

    V will die due to his actions or continued existence.

    Again, it boils down to ghastly arithmetic. We definitely

    should kill IP to prevent V’s death if IP is going to die

    anyway – and shortly. The remaining life of V, if saved,

    should exceed the remaining life of IP, if not killed. If

    these conditions are not met, the rights of IP and V should

    be weighted and calculated to yield a decision (See

    “Abortion and the Sanctity of Human Life” by Baruch A.

    Brody).

    Utilitarianism – a form of crass moral calculus – calls for

    the maximization of utility (life, happiness, pleasure). The

    lives, happiness, or pleasure of the many outweigh the

    life, happiness, or pleasure of the few. If by killing IP we

    save the lives of two or more people and there is no other

    way to save their lives – it is morally permissible.

    But surely V has right to self defense, regardless of any

    moral calculus of rights? Not so. Taking another’s life to

    save one’s own is rarely justified, though such behavior

    cannot be condemned. Here we have the flip side of the

    confusion we opened with: understandable and perhaps

    inevitable behavior (self defense) is mistaken for a moral

    right.

    If I were V, I would kill IP unhesitatingly. Moreover, I

    would have the understanding and sympathy of everyone.

    But this does not mean that I had a right to kill IP.

    Which brings us to September 11.

    Collateral Damage

    What should prevail: the imperative to spare the lives of
    innocent civilians – or the need to safeguard the lives of
    fighter pilots? Precision bombing puts such pilots at great
    risk. Avoiding this risk usually results in civilian
    casualties (“collateral damage”).
    This moral dilemma is often “solved” by applying –
    explicitly or implicitly – the principle of “over-riding
    affiliation”. We find the two facets of this principle in
    Jewish sacred texts: “One is close to oneself” and “Your
    city’s poor denizens come first (with regards to charity)”.

    Some moral obligations are universal – thou shalt not kill.

    They are related to one’s position as a human being. Other

    moral values and obligations arise from one’s affiliations.

    Yet, there is a hierarchy of moral values and obligations.

    The ones related to one’s position as a human being are,

    actually, the weakest.

    They are overruled by moral values and obligations

    related to one’s affiliations. The imperative “thou shalt not

    kill (another human being)” is easily over-ruled by the

    moral obligation to kill for one’s country. The imperative

    “thou shalt not steal” is superseded by one’s moral

    obligation to spy for one’s nation.

    This leads to another startling conclusion:

    There is no such thing as a self-consistent moral system.

    Moral values and obligations often contradict each other

    and almost always conflict with universal moral values

    and obligations.
    In the examples above, killing (for one’s country) and

    stealing (for one’s nation) are moral obligations. Yet, they

    contradict the universal moral value of the sanctity of life

    and the universal moral obligation not to kill. Far from

    being a fundamental and immutable principle – the right to

    life, it would seem, is merely a convenient implement in

    the hands of society.

    The Argument for Torture

    By: Sam Vaknin

    Also Read:

    The Business of Torture

    I. Practical Considerations

    The problem of the “ticking bomb” – rediscovered after

    September 11 by Alan Dershowitz, a renowned criminal

    defense lawyer in the United States – is old hat. Should

    physical torture be applied – where psychological strain

    has failed – in order to discover the whereabouts of a

    ticking bomb and thus prevent a mass slaughter of the

    innocent? This apparent ethical dilemma has been

    confronted by ethicists and jurists from Great Britain to

    Israel.

    Nor is Dershowitz’s proposal to have the courts issue

    “torture warrants” (Los Angeles Times, November 8,

    2001) unprecedented. In a controversial decision in 1996,

    the Supreme Court of Israel permitted its internal security

    forces to apply “moderate physical pressure” during the

    interrogation of suspects.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/brief-torture01.html

    It has thus fully embraced the recommendation of the

    1987 Landau Commission, presided over by a former

    Supreme Court judge. This blanket absolution was

    repealed in 1999 when widespread abuses against

    Palestinian detainees were unearthed by human rights

    organizations.

    Indeed, this juridical reversal – in the face of growing

    suicidal terrorism – demonstrates how slippery the ethical

    slope can be. What started off as permission to apply mild

    torture in extreme cases avalanched into an all-pervasive

    and pernicious practice. This lesson – that torture is habit-

    forming and metastasizes incontrollably throughout the

    system – is the most powerful – perhaps the only –

    argument against it.

    As Harvey Silverglate argued in his rebuttal of

    Dershowitz’s aforementioned op-ed piece:

    “Institutionalizing torture will give it society‘s

    imprimatur, lending it a degree of respectability. It will

    then be virtually impossible to curb not only the

    increasing frequency with which warrants will be sought

    — and granted — but also the inevitable rise in

    unauthorized use of torture. Unauthorized torture will

    increase not only to extract life-saving information, but

    also to obtain confessions (many of which will then prove

    false). It will also be used to punish real or imagined

    infractions, or for no reason other than human sadism.

    This is a genie we should not let out of the bottle.”

    Alas, these are weak contentions.

    That something has the potential to be widely abused –

    and has been and is being widely misused – should not

    inevitably lead to its utter, universal, and unconditional

    proscription. Guns, cars, knives, and books have always

    been put to vile ends. Nowhere did this lead to their

    complete interdiction.

    Moreover, torture is erroneously perceived by liberals as a

    kind of punishment. Suspects – innocent until proven

    guilty – indeed should not be subject to penalty. But

    torture is merely an interrogation technique. Ethically, it is

    no different to any other pre-trial process: shackling,

    detention, questioning, or bad press. Inevitably, the very

    act of suspecting someone is traumatic and bound to

    inflict pain and suffering – psychological, pecuniary, and

    physical – on the suspect.

    True, torture is bound to yield false confessions and

    wrong information, Seneca claimed that it “forces even

    the innocent to lie”. St. Augustine expounded on the

    moral deplorability of torture

    thus:

    ―If the accused be

    innocent, he will undergo for an uncertain crime a certain

    punishment, and that not for having committed a crime,

    but because it is unknown whether he committed it.”

    But the same can be said about other, less corporeal,

    methods of interrogation. Moreover, the flip side of ill-

    gotten admissions is specious denials of guilt. Criminals

    regularly disown their misdeeds and thus evade their

    penal consequences. The very threat of torture is bound to

    limit this miscarriage of justice. Judges and juries can

    always decide what confessions are involuntary and were

    extracted under duress.

    Thus, if there was a way to ensure that non-lethal torture

    is narrowly defined, applied solely to extract time-critical

    information in accordance with a strict set of rules and

    specifications, determined openly and revised frequently

    by an accountable public body; that abusers are severely

    punished and instantly removed; that the tortured have

    recourse to the judicial system and to medical attention at

    any time – then the procedure would have been ethically

    justified in rare cases if carried out by the authorities.

    This proviso – “if carried out by the authorities” – is

    crucial.

    The sovereign has rights denied the individual, or any

    subset of society. It can judicially kill with impunity. Its

    organs – the police, the military – can exercise violence. It

    is allowed to conceal information, possess illicit or

    dangerous substances, deploy arms, invade one’s bodily

    integrity, or confiscate property. To permit the sovereign

    to torture while forbidding individuals, or organizations

    from doing so would, therefore, not be without precedent,

    or inconsistent.

    Alan Dershowitz expounds:

    “(In the United States) any interrogation technique,

    including the use of truth serum or even torture, is not

    prohibited. All that is prohibited is the introduction into

    evidence of the fruits of such techniques in a criminal trial

    against the person on whom the techniques were used. But

    the evidence could be used against that suspect in a non-

    criminal case – such as a deportation hearing – or against

    someone else.”

    When the unspeakable horrors of the Nazi concentration

    camps were revealed, C.S. Lewis wrote, in quite

    desperation:

    “What was the sense in saying the enemy were in the

    wrong unless Right is a real thing which the Nazis at

    bottom knew as well as we did and ought to have

    practiced? If they had no notion of what we mean by

    Right, then, though we might still have had to fight them,

    we could no more have blamed them for that than for the

    color of their hair.” (C.S. Lewis, Mere Christianity (New

    York: Macmillan, paperback edition, 1952).

    But legal torture should never be directed at innocent

    civilians based on arbitrary criteria such as their race or

    religion. If this principle is observed, torture would not

    reflect on the moral standing of the state. Identical acts are

    considered morally sound when carried out by the realm –

    and condemnable when discharged by individuals.

    Consider the denial of freedom. It is lawful incarceration

    at the hands of the republic – but kidnapping if effected by

    terrorists.

    Nor is torture, as “The Economist” misguidedly claims, a

    taboo.

    According to the 2002 edition of the “Encyclopedia

    Britannica”, taboos are “the prohibition of an action or the

    use of an object based on ritualistic distinctions of them

    either as being sacred and consecrated or as being

    dangerous, unclean, and accursed.” Evidently, none of this

    applies to torture. On the contrary, torture – as opposed,

    for instance, to incest – is a universal, state-sanctioned

    behavior.

    Amnesty International – who should know better –

    professed to have been shocked by the results of their own

    surveys:

    “In preparing for its third international campaign to stop

    torture, Amnesty International conducted a survey of its

    research files on 195 countries and territories. The survey

    covered the period from the beginning of 1997 to mid-

    2000. Information on torture is usually concealed, and

    reports of torture are often hard to document, so the

    figures almost certainly underestimate its extent. The

    statistics are shocking. There were reports of torture or ill-

    treatment by state officials in more than 150 countries. In

    more than 70, they were widespread or persistent. In more

    than 80 countries, people reportedly died as a result.”

    Countries and regimes abstain from torture – or, more

    often, claim to do so – because such overt abstention is

    expedient. It is a form of global political correctness, a

    policy choice intended to demonstrate common values and

    to extract concessions or benefits from others. Giving up

    this efficient weapon in the law enforcement arsenal even

    in Damoclean circumstances is often rewarded with

    foreign direct investment, military aid, and other forms of

    support.

    But such ethical magnanimity is a luxury in times of war,

    or when faced with a threat to innocent life. Even the

    courts of the most liberal societies sanctioned atrocities in

    extraordinary circumstances. Here the law conforms both

    with common sense and with formal, utilitarian, ethics.

    II. Ethical Considerations

    Rights – whether moral or legal – impose obligations or
    duties on third parties towards the right-holder. One has a
    right AGAINST other people and thus can prescribe to
    them certain obligatory behaviors and proscribe certain
    acts or omissions. Rights and duties are two sides of the
    same Janus-like ethical coin.
    This duality confuses people. They often erroneously
    identify rights with their attendant duties or obligations,
    with the morally decent, or even with the morally
    permissible. One’s rights inform other people how they

    MUST behave towards one – not how they SHOULD, or

    OUGHT to act morally. Moral behavior is not dependent
    on the existence of a right. Obligations are.
    To complicate matters further, many apparently simple
    and straightforward rights are amalgams of more basic
    moral or legal principles. To treat such rights as unities is
    to mistreat them.

    Take the right not to be tortured. It is a compendium of

    many distinct rights, among them: the right to bodily and

    mental integrity, the right to avoid self-incrimination, the

    right not to be pained, or killed, the right to save one’s life

    (wrongly reduced merely to the right to self-defense), the

    right to prolong one’s life (e.g., by receiving medical

    attention), and the right not to be forced to lie under

    duress.

    None of these rights is self-evident, or unambiguous, or
    universal, or immutable, or automatically applicable. It is

    safe to say, therefore, that these rights are not primary –

    but derivative, nonessential, or mere “wants”.

    Moreover, the fact that the torturer also has rights whose

    violation may justify torture is often overlooked.

    Consider these two, for instance:

    The Rights of Third Parties against the Tortured

    What is just and what is unjust is determined by an ethical

    calculus, or a social contract – both in constant flux. Still,

    it is commonly agreed that every person has the right not

    to be tortured, or killed unjustly.

    Yet, even if we find an Archimedean immutable point of

    moral reference – does A’s right not to be tortured, let

    alone killed, mean that third parties are to refrain from

    enforcing the rights of other people against A?

    What if the only way to right wrongs committed, or about

    to be committed by A against others – was to torture, or

    kill A? There is a moral obligation to right wrongs by

    restoring, or safeguarding the rights of those wronged, or

    about to be wronged by A.

    If the defiant silence – or even the mere existence – of A

    are predicated on the repeated and continuous violation of

    the rights of others (especially their right to live), and if

    these people object to such violation – then A must be

    tortured, or killed if that is the only way to right the wrong

    and re-assert the rights of A’s victims.

    This, ironically, is the argument used by liberals to justify

    abortion when the fetus (in the role of A) threatens his

    mother’s rights to health and life.

    The Right to Save One’s Own Life
    One has a right to save one’s life by exercising self-

    defense or otherwise, by taking certain actions, or by

    avoiding them. Judaism – as well as other religious, moral,

    and legal systems – accepts that one has the right to kill a

    pursuer who knowingly and intentionally is bent on taking
    one’s life. Hunting down Osama bin-Laden in the wilds of
    Afghanistan is, therefore, morally acceptable (though not

    morally mandatory). So is torturing his minions.

    When there is a clash between equally potent rights – for
    instance, the conflicting rights to life of two people – we
    can decide among them randomly (by flipping a coin, or
    casting dice). Alternatively, we can add and subtract

    rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic. The right to life

    definitely prevails over the right to comfort, bodily

    integrity, absence of pain and so on. Where life is at stake,

    non-lethal torture is justified by any ethical calculus.

    Utilitarianism – a form of crass moral calculus – calls for
    the maximization of utility (life, happiness, pleasure). The
    lives, happiness, or pleasure of the many outweigh the

    life, happiness, or pleasure of the few. If by killing or

    torturing the few we (a) save the lives of the many (b) the

    combined life expectancy of the many is longer than the

    combined life expectancy of the few and (c) there is no

    other way to save the lives of the many – it is morally

    permissible to kill, or torture the few.

    III. The Social Treaty

    There is no way to enforce certain rights without

    infringing on others. The calculus of ethics relies on

    implicit and explicit quantitative and qualitative

    hierarchies. The rights of the many outweigh certain rights

    of the few. Higher-level rights – such as the right to life –

    override rights of a lower order.

    The rights of individuals are not absolute but “prima

    facie”. They are restricted both by the rights of others and

    by the common interest. They are inextricably connected

    to duties towards other individuals in particular and the

    community in general. In other words, though not

    dependent on idiosyncratic cultural and social contexts,

    they are an integral part of a social covenant.

    It can be argued that a suspect has excluded himself from

    the social treaty by refusing to uphold the rights of others

    – for instance, by declining to collaborate with law

    enforcement agencies in forestalling an imminent disaster.

    Such inaction amounts to the abrogation of many of one’s

    rights (for instance, the right to be free). Why not apply

    this abrogation to his or her right not to be tortured?

    The Aborted Contract And the Right to Life

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    The issue of abortion is emotionally loaded and this often

    makes for poor, not thoroughly thought out

    arguments. The questions: “Is abortion immoral” and “Is

    abortion a murder” are often confused. The pregnancy

    (and the resulting fetus) are discussed in terms normally

    reserved to natural catastrophes (force majeure). At times,

    the embryo is compared to cancer, a thief, or an invader:

    after all, they are both growths, clusters of cells. The

    difference, of course, is that no one contracts cancer

    willingly (except, to some extent, smokers -–but, then

    they gamble, not contract).

    When a woman engages in voluntary sex, does not use

    contraceptives and gets pregnant – one can say that she

    signed a contract with her fetus. A contract entails the

    demonstrated existence of a reasonably (and reasonable)

    free will. If the fulfillment of the obligations in a contract

    between individuals could be life-threatening – it is fair

    and safe to assume that no rational free will was involved.

    No reasonable person would sign or enter such a contract

    with another person (though most people would sign such

    contracts with society).

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    Judith Jarvis Thomson argued convincingly (“A Defence

    of Abortion”) that pregnancies that are the result of forced

    sex (rape being a special case) or which are life

    threatening should or could, morally, be terminated. Using

    the transactional language: the contract was not entered to

    willingly or reasonably and, therefore, is null and

    void. Any actions which are intended to terminate it and

    to annul its consequences should be legally and morally

    permissible.

    The same goes for a contract which was entered into

    against the express will of one of the parties and despite

    all the reasonable measures that the unwilling party

    adopted to prevent it. If a mother uses contraceptives in a

    manner intended to prevent pregnancy, it is as good as

    saying: ” I do not want to sign this contract, I am doing

    my reasonable best not to sign it, if it is signed – it is

    contrary to my express will”. There is little legal (or

    moral) doubt that such a contract should be voided.

    Much more serious problems arise when we study the

    other party to these implicit agreements: the embryo. To

    start with, it lacks consciousness (in the sense that is

    needed for signing an enforceable and valid contract). Can

    a contract be valid even if one of the “signatories” lacks

    this sine qua non trait? In the absence of consciousness,

    there is little point in talking about free will (or rights

    which depend on sentience). So, is the contract not a

    contract at all? Does it not reflect the intentions of the

    parties?

    The answer is in the negative. The contract between a

    mother and her fetus is derived from the larger Social

    Contract. Society – through its apparatuses – stands for

    the embryo the same way that it represents minors, the

    mentally retarded, and the insane. Society steps in – and

    has the recognized right and moral obligation to do so –

    whenever the powers of the parties to a contract (implicit

    or explicit) are not balanced. It protects small citizens

    from big monopolies, the physically weak from the thug,

    the tiny opposition from the mighty administration, the

    barely surviving radio station from the claws of the

    devouring state mechanism. It also has the right and

    obligation to intervene, intercede and represent the

    unconscious: this is why euthanasia is absolutely

    forbidden without the consent of the dying person. There

    is not much difference between the embryo and the

    comatose.

    A typical contract states the rights of the parties. It

    assumes the existence of parties which are “moral

    personhoods” or “morally significant persons” – in other

    words, persons who are holders of rights and can demand

    from us to respect these rights. Contracts explicitly

    elaborate some of these rights and leaves others

    unmentioned because of the presumed existence of the

    Social Contract. The typical contract assumes that there is

    a social contract which applies to the parties to the

    contract and which is universally known and, therefore,

    implicitly incorporated in every contract. Thus, an explicit

    contract can deal with the property rights of a certain

    person, while neglecting to mention that person’s rights to

    life, to free speech, to the enjoyment the fruits of his

    lawful property and, in general to a happy life.

    There is little debate that the Mother is a morally

    significant person and that she is a rights-holder. All born

    humans are and, more so, all adults above a certain age.

    But what about the unborn fetus?

    One approach is that the embryo has no rights until certain

    conditions are met and only upon their fulfillment is he

    transformed into a morally significant person (“moral

    agent”). Opinions differ as to what are the conditions.

    Rationality, or a morally meaningful and valued life are

    some of the oft cited criteria. The fallaciousness of this

    argument is easy to demonstrate: children are irrational –

    is this a licence to commit infanticide?

    A second approach says that a person has the right to life

    because it desires it.

    But then what about chronic depressives who wish to die

    – do we have the right to terminate their miserable lives?

    The good part of life (and, therefore, the differential and

    meaningful test) is in the experience itself – not in the

    desire to experience.

    Another variant says that a person has the right to life

    because once his life is terminated – his experiences

    cease. So, how should we judge the right to life of

    someone who constantly endures bad experiences (and, as

    a result, harbors a death wish)? Should he better be

    “terminated”?

    Having reviewed the above arguments and counter-

    arguments, Don Marquis goes on (in “Why Abortion is

    Immoral”, 1989) to offer a sharper and more

    comprehensive criterion: terminating a life is morally

    wrong because a person has a future filled with value and

    meaning, similar to ours.

    But the whole debate is unnecessary. There is no conflict

    between the rights of the mother and those of her fetus

    because there is never a conflict between parties to an

    agreement. By signing an agreement, the mother gave up

    some of her rights and limited the others. This is normal

    practice in contracts: they represent compromises, the

    optimization (and not the maximization) of the parties’

    rights and wishes. The rights of the fetus are an

    inseparable part of the contract which the mother signed

    voluntarily and reasonably. They are derived from the

    mother’s behaviour. Getting willingly pregnant (or

    assuming the risk of getting pregnant by not using

    contraceptives reasonably) – is the behaviour which

    validates and ratifies a contract between her and the

    fetus. Many contracts are by behaviour, rather than by a

    signed piece of paper. Numerous contracts are verbal or

    behavioural. These contracts, though implicit, are as

    binding as any of their written, more explicit,

    brethren. Legally (and morally) the situation is crystal

    clear: the mother signed some of her rights away in this

    contract. Even if she regrets it – she cannot claim her

    rights back by annulling the contract unilaterally. No

    contract can be annulled this way – the consent of both

    parties is required. Many times we realize that we have

    entered a bad contract, but there is nothing much that we

    can do about it. These are the rules of the game.

    Thus the two remaining questions: (a) can this specific

    contract (pregnancy) be annulled and, if so (b) in which

    circumstances – can be easily settled using modern

    contract law. Yes, a contract can be annulled and voided if

    signed under duress, involuntarily, by incompetent

    persons (e.g., the insane), or if one of the parties made a

    reasonable and full scale attempt to prevent its signature,

    thus expressing its clear will not to sign the contract. It is

    also terminated or voided if it would be unreasonable to

    expect one of the parties to see it through. Rape,

    contraception failure, life threatening situations are all

    such cases.

    This could be argued against by saying that, in the case of

    economic hardship, f or instance, the damage to the

    mother’s future is certain. True, her value- filled,

    meaningful future is granted – but so is the detrimental

    effect that the fetus will have on it, once born. This

    certainty cannot be balanced by the UNCERTAIN value-

    filled future life of the embryo. Always, preferring an

    uncertain good to a certain evil is morally wrong. But

    surely this is a quantitative matter – not a qualitative one.

    Certain, limited aspects of the rest of the mother’s life will

    be adversely effected (and can be ameliorated by society’s

    helping hand and intervention) if she does have the

    baby. The decision not to have it is both qualitatively and

    qualitatively different. It is to deprive the unborn of all the

    aspects of all his future life – in which he might well have

    experienced happiness, values, and meaning.

    The questions whether the fetus is a Being or a growth of

    cells, conscious in any manner, or utterly unconscious,

    able to value his life and to want them – are all but

    irrelevant. He has the potential to lead a happy,

    meaningful, value-filled life, similar to ours, very much as

    a one minute old baby does. The contract between him

    and his mother is a service provision contract. She

    provides him with goods and services that he requires in

    order to materialize his potential. It sounds very much like

    many other human contracts. And this contract continue

    well after pregnancy has ended and birth given.

    Consider education: children do not appreciate its

    importance or value its potential – still, it is enforced upon

    them because we, who are capable of those feats, want

    them to have the tools that they will need in order to

    develop their potential. In this and many other respects,

    the human pregnancy continues well into the fourth year

    of life (physiologically it continues in to the second year

    of life – see “Born Alien”). Should the location of the

    pregnancy (in uterus, in vivo) determine its future? If a

    mother has the right to abort at will, why should the

    mother be denied her right to terminate the ” pregnancy”

    AFTER the fetus emerges and the pregnancy continues

    OUTSIDE her womb? Even after birth, the woman’s body

    is the main source of food to the baby and, in any case,

    she has to endure physical hardship to raise the

    child. Why not extend the woman’s ownership of her body

    and right to it further in time and space to the post-natal

    period?

    http://samvak.tripod.com/alien.html

    Contracts to provide goods and services (always at a

    personal cost to the provider) are the commonest of

    contracts. We open a business. We sell a software

    application, we publish a book – we engage in helping

    others to materialize their potential. We should always do

    so willingly and reasonably – otherwise the contracts that

    we sign will be null and void. But to deny anyone his

    capacity to materialize his potential and the goods and

    services that he needs to do so – after a valid contract was

    entered into – is

    immoral.

    To refuse to provide a service or

    to condition it provision (Mother: ” I will provide the

    goods and services that I agreed to provide to this fetus

    under this contract only if and when I benefit from such

    provision”) is a violation of the contract and should be

    penalized. Admittedly, at times we have a right to choose

    to do the immoral (because it has not been codified as

    illegal) – but that does not turn it into moral.

    Still, not every immoral act involving the termination of

    life can be classified as murder. Phenomenology is

    deceiving: the acts look the same (cessation of life

    functions, the prevention of a future). But murder is the

    intentional termination of the life of a human who

    possesses, at the moment of death, a consciousness (and,

    in most cases, a free will, especially the will not to

    die). Abortion is the intentional termination of a life

    which has the potential to develop into a person with

    consciousness and free will. Philosophically, no identity

    can be established between potential and actuality. The

    destruction of paints and cloth is not tantamount (not to

    say identical) to the destruction of a painting by Van

    Gogh, made up of these very elements. Paints and cloth

    are converted to a painting through the intermediacy and

    agency of the Painter. A cluster of cells a human makes

    only through the agency of Nature.

    Surely, the destruction of the painting materials

    constitutes an offence against the Painter. In the same

    way, the destruction of the fetus constitutes an offence

    against Nature. But there is no denying that in both cases,

    no finished product was eliminated. Naturally, this

    becomes less and less so (the severity of the terminating

    act increases) as the process of creation advances.

    Classifying an abortion as murder poses numerous and

    insurmountable philosophical problems.

    No one disputes the now common view that the main

    crime committed in aborting a pregnancy – is a crime

    against potentialities. If so, what is the philosophical

    difference between aborting a fetus and destroying a

    sperm and an egg? These two contain all the information

    (=all the potential) and their destruction is philosophically

    no less grave than the destruction of a fetus. The

    destruction of an egg and a sperm is even more serious

    philosophically: the creation of a fetus limits the set of all

    potentials embedded in the genetic material to the one

    fetus created. The egg and sperm can be compared to the

    famous wave function (state vector) in quantum

    mechanics – the represent millions of potential final states

    (=millions of potential embryos and lives). The fetus is

    the collapse of the wave function: it represents a much

    more limited set of potentials. If killing an embryo is

    murder because of the elimination of potentials – how

    should we consider the intentional elimination of many

    more potentials through masturbation and contraception?

    The argument that it is difficult to say which sperm cell

    will impregnate the egg is not serious. Biologically, it

    does not matter – they all carry the same genetic

    content. Moreover, would this counter-argument still hold

    if, in future, we were be able to identify the chosen one

    and eliminate only it? In many religions (Catholicism)

    contraception is murder. In Judaism, masturbation is “the

    corruption of the seed” and such a serious offence that it is

    punishable by the strongest religious penalty: eternal ex-

    communication (“Karet”).

    If abortion is indeed murder how should we resolve the

    following moral dilemmas and questions (some of them

    patently absurd):

    Is a natural abortion the equivalent of manslaughter

    (through negligence)?

    Do habits like smoking, drug addiction, vegetarianism –

    infringe upon the right to life of the embryo? Do they

    constitute a violation of the contract?

    Reductio ad absurdum: if, in the far future, research will

    unequivocally prove that listening to a certain kind of

    music or entertaining certain thoughts seriously hampers

    the embryonic development – should we apply censorship

    to the Mother?

    Should force majeure clauses be introduced to the

    Mother-Embryo pregnancy contract? Will they give the

    mother the right to cancel the contract? Will the embryo

    have a right to terminate the contract? Should the

    asymmetry persist: the Mother will have no right to

    terminate – but the embryo will, or vice versa?

    Being a rights holder, can the embryo (=the State) litigate

    against his Mother or Third Parties (the doctor that

    aborted him, someone who hit his mother and brought

    about a natural abortion) even after he died?

    Should anyone who knows about an abortion be

    considered an accomplice to murder?

    If abortion is murder – why punish it so mildly? Why is

    there a debate regarding this question? “Thou shalt not

    kill” is a natural law, it appears in virtually every legal

    system. It is easily and immediately identifiable. The fact

    that abortion does not “enjoy” the same legal and moral

    treatment says a lot.

    In Our Own Image

    The Debate about Cloning
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    There are two types of cloning. One involves harvesting

    stem cells from embryos (“therapeutic cloning”). These

    are the biological equivalent of a template. They can

    develop into any kind of mature functional cell and thus

    help cure many degenerative and auto-immune diseases.

    The other kind of cloning is much derided in popular

    culture – and elsewhere – as the harbinger of a Brave, New

    World. A nucleus from any cell of a donor is embedded in

    an egg whose own nucleus has been removed. The egg is

    then implanted in a woman’s womb and a cloned baby is

    born nine months later. Biologically, the cloned infant is a

    replica of the donor.

    Cloning is often confused with other advances in bio-

    medicine and bio-engineering – such as genetic selection.

    It cannot – in itself – be used to produce “perfect humans”

    or select sex or other traits. Hence, some of the arguments

    against cloning are either specious or fuelled by

    ignorance.

    It is true, though, that cloning, used in conjunction with

    other bio-technologies, raises serious bio-ethical

    questions.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    Scare scenarios of humans cultivated in sinister labs as

    sources of spare body parts, “designer babies”, “master

    races”, or “genetic sex slaves” – formerly the preserve of B

    sci-fi movies – have invaded mainstream discourse.

    Still, cloning touches upon Mankind’s most basic fears

    and hopes. It invokes the most intractable ethical and

    moral dilemmas. As an inevitable result, the debate is

    often more passionate than informed.

    Right to Life Arguments

    According to cloning’s detractors, the nucleus removed

    from the egg could otherwise have developed into a

    human being. Thus, removing the nucleus amounts to

    murder.

    It is a fundamental principle of most moral theories that

    all human beings have a right to life. The existence of a

    right implies obligations or duties of third parties towards

    the right-holder. One has a right AGAINST other people.

    The fact that one possesses a certain right – prescribes to

    others certain obligatory behaviours and proscribes certain

    acts or omissions. This Janus-like nature of rights and

    duties as two sides of the same ethical coin – creates great

    confusion. People often and easily confuse rights and their

    attendant duties or obligations with the morally decent, or

    even with the morally permissible. What one MUST do as

    a result of another’s right – should never be confused with

    one SHOULD or OUGHT to do morally (in the absence

    of a right).

    But is the egg – alive?

    This question is NOT equivalent to the ancient quandary

    of “when does life begin”. Life crystallizes, at the earliest,

    when an egg and a sperm unite (i.e., at the moment of

    fertilization). Life is not a potential – it is a process

    triggered by an event. An unfertilized egg is neither a

    process – nor an event. It does not even possess the

    potential to become alive unless and until it merges with a

    sperm. Should such merger not occur – it will never

    develop life.

    The potential to become X is not the ontological

    equivalent of actually being X, nor does it spawn moral

    and ethical rights and obligations pertaining to X. The

    transition from potential to being is not trivial, nor is it

    automatic, or inevitable, or independent of context. Atoms

    of various elements have the potential to become an egg

    (or, for that matter, a human being) – yet no one would

    claim that they ARE an egg (or a human being), or that

    they should be treated as one (i.e., with the same rights

    and obligations).

    Moreover, it is the donor nucleus embedded in the egg

    that endows it with life – the life of the cloned baby. Yet,

    the nucleus is usually extracted from a muscle or the skin.

    Should we treat a muscle or a skin cell with the same

    reverence the critics of cloning wish to accord an

    unfertilized egg?

    Is this the main concern?

    The main concern is that cloning – even the therapeutic

    kind – will produce piles of embryos. Many of them –

    close to 95% with current biotechnology – will die. Others

    can be surreptitiously and illegally implanted in the

    wombs of “surrogate mothers”.

    It is patently immoral, goes the precautionary argument,

    to kill so many embryos. Cloning is such a novel

    technique that its success rate is still unacceptably low.

    There are alternative ways to harvest stem cells – less

    costly in terms of human life. If we accept that life begins

    at the moment of fertilization, this argument is valid. But

    it also implies that – once cloning becomes safer and

    scientists more adept – cloning itself should be permitted.

    This is anathema to those who fear a slippery slope. They

    abhor the very notion of “unnatural” conception. To them,

    cloning is a narcissistic act and an ignorant and dangerous

    interference in nature’s sagacious ways. They would ban

    procreative cloning, regardless of how safe it is.

    Therapeutic cloning – with its mounds of discarded fetuses

    – will allow rogue scientists to cross the boundary between

    permissible (curative cloning) and illegal (baby cloning).

    Why should Baby Cloning be Illegal?

    Cloning’s opponents object to procreative cloning because

    it can be abused to design babies, skew natural selection,

    unbalance nature, produce masters and slaves and so on.

    The “argument from abuse” has been raised with every

    scientific advance – from in vitro fertilization to space

    travel.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/npdglance.html

    Every technology can be potentially abused. Television

    can be either a wonderful educational tool – or an

    addictive and mind numbing pastime. Nuclear fission is a

    process that yields both nuclear weapons and atomic

    energy. To claim, as many do, that cloning touches upon

    the “heart” of our existence, the “kernel” of our being, the

    very “essence” of our nature – and thus threatens life itself

    – would be incorrect.

    There is no “privileged” form of technological abuse and

    no hierarchy of potentially abusive technologies. Nuclear

    fission tackles natural processes as fundamental as life.

    Nuclear weapons threaten life no less than cloning. The

    potential for abuse is not a sufficient reason to arrest

    scientific research and progress – though it is a necessary

    condition.

    Some fear that cloning will further the government’s

    enmeshment in the healthcare system and in scientific

    research. Power corrupts and it is not inconceivable that

    governments will ultimately abuse and misuse cloning and

    other biotechnologies. Nazi Germany had a state-

    sponsored and state-mandated eugenics program in the

    1930’s.

    Yet, this is another variant of the argument from abuse.

    That a technology can be abused by governments does not

    imply that it should be avoided or remain undeveloped.

    This is because all technologies – without a single

    exception – can and are abused routinely – by governments

    and others. This is human nature.

    Fukuyama raised the possibility of a multi-tiered

    humanity in which “natural” and “genetically modified”

    people enjoy different rights and privileges. But why is

    this inevitable? Surely this can easily by tackled by

    proper, prophylactic, legislation?

    All humans, regardless of their pre-natal history, should

    be treated equally. Are children currently conceived in

    vitro treated any differently to children conceived in

    utero? They

    are not.

    There is no reason that cloned or

    genetically-modified children should belong to distinct

    legal classes.

    Unbalancing Nature

    It is very anthropocentric to argue that the proliferation of

    genetically enhanced or genetically selected children will

    somehow unbalance nature and destabilize the precarious

    equilibrium it maintains. After all, humans have been

    modifying, enhancing, and eliminating hundreds of

    thousands of species for well over 10,000 years now.

    Genetic modification and bio-engineering are as natural as

    agriculture. Human beings are a part of nature and its

    manifestation. By definition, everything they do is natural.

    Why would the genetic alteration or enhancement of one

    more species – homo sapiens – be of any consequence? In

    what way are humans “more important” to nature, or

    “more crucial” to its proper functioning? In our short

    history on this planet, we have genetically modified and

    enhanced wheat and rice, dogs and cows, tulips and

    orchids, oranges and potatoes. Why would interfering

    with the genetic legacy of the human species be any

    different?

    Effects on Society

    Cloning – like the Internet, the television, the car,

    electricity, the telegraph, and the wheel before it – is

    bound to have great social consequences. It may foster

    “embryo industries”. It may lead to the exploitation of

    women – either willingly (“egg prostitution”) or

    unwillingly (“womb slavery”). Charles Krauthammer, a

    columnist and psychiatrist, quoted in “The Economist”,

    says:

    “(Cloning) means the routinisation, the

    commercialisation, the commodification of the human

    embryo”.

    Exploiting anyone unwillingly is a crime, whether it

    involves cloning or white slavery. But why would egg

    donations and surrogate motherhood be considered

    problems? If we accept that life begins at the moment of

    fertilization and that a woman owns her body and

    everything within it – why should she not be allowed to

    sell her eggs or to host another’s baby and how would

    these voluntary acts be morally repugnant? In any case,

    human eggs are already being bought and sold and the

    supply far exceeds the demand.

    Moreover, full-fledged humans are routinely “routinised,

    commercialized, and commodified” by governments,

    corporations, religions, and other social institutions.

    Consider war, for instance – or commercial advertising.

    How is the “routinisation, commercialization, and

    commodification” of embryos more reprehensible that the

    “routinisation, commercialization, and commodification”

    of fully formed human beings?

    Curing and Saving Life

    Cell therapy based on stem cells often leads to tissue

    rejection and necessitates costly and potentially dangerous

    immunosuppressive therapy. But when the stem cells are

    harvested from the patient himself and cloned, these

    problems are averted. Therapeutic cloning has vast

    untapped – though at this stage still remote – potential to

    improve the lives of hundreds of millions.

    As far as “designer babies” go, pre-natal cloning and

    genetic engineering can be used to prevent disease or cure

    it, to suppress unwanted traits, and to enhance desired

    ones. It is the moral right of a parent to make sure that his

    progeny suffers less, enjoys life more, and attains the

    maximal level of welfare throughout his or her life.

    That such technologies can be abused by over-zealous, or

    mentally unhealthy parents in collaboration with

    avaricious or unscrupulous doctors – should not prevent

    the vast majority of stable, caring, and sane parents from

    gaining access to them.

    Ethical Relativism and Absolute Taboos
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    I. Taboos

    II. Incest

    III. Suicide

    IV. Race

    V. Moral Relativism

    I. Taboos

    Taboos regulate our sexual conduct, race relations,

    political institutions, and economic mechanisms – virtually

    every realm of our life. According to the 2002 edition of

    the “Encyclopedia Britannica”, they are “the prohibition

    of an action or the use of an object based on ritualistic

    distinctions of them either as being sacred and

    consecrated or as being dangerous, unclean, and

    accursed.”

    Jews are instructed to ritually cleanse themselves after

    having been in contact with a Torah scroll – or a corpse.

    This association of the sacred with the accursed and the

    holy with the depraved is the key to the guilt and sense of

    danger which accompany the violation of a taboo.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#taboo

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#incest

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#suicide

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#race

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#relativism

    In Polynesia, where the term originated, “taboos could

    include prohibitions on fishing or picking fruit at certain

    seasons; food taboos that restrict the diet of pregnant

    women; prohibitions on talking to or touching chiefs or

    members of other high social classes; taboos on walking

    or traveling in certain areas, such as forests; and various

    taboos that function during important life events such as

    birth, marriage, and death.”

    Political correctness is a particularly pernicious kind of

    taboo enforcement. It entails an all-pervasive self-

    censorship coupled with social sanctions. Consider the

    treatment of the right to life, incest, suicide, and race.

    II. Incest

    In contemporary thought, incest is invariably associated

    with child abuse and its horrific, long-lasting, and often

    irreversible consequences. But incest is far from being the

    clear-cut or monolithic issue that millennia of taboo

    imply. Incest with minors is a private – and particularly

    egregious – case of pedophilia or statutory rape. It should

    be dealt with forcefully. But incest covers much more

    besides these criminal

    acts.

    Incest is the ethical and legal prohibition to have sex with

    a related person or to marry him or her – even if the people

    involved are consenting and fully informed adults.

    Contrary to popular mythology, banning incest has little to

    do with the fear of genetic diseases. Even genetically

    unrelated parties (a stepfather and a stepdaughter) can

    commit incest.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#incest

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#suicide

    ../../../Upload%20Tripod/taboo.html#race

    Incest is also forbidden between fictive kin or

    classificatory kin (that belong to the same matriline or

    patriline). In certain societies (certain Native American

    tribes, or the Chinese) it is sufficient to carry the same

    family name (i.e., to belong to the same clan) to render a

    relationship incestuous. Clearly, eugenic considerations

    have little to do with incest.

    Moreover, the use of contraceptives means that incest

    does not need to result in pregnancy and the transmission

    of genetic material. Inbreeding (endogamous) or

    straightforward incest is the norm in many life forms,

    even among primates (e.g., chimpanzees). It was also

    quite common until recently in certain human societies –

    the Hindus, for instance, or many Native American tribes,

    and royal families everywhere.

    Nor is the taboo universal. In some societies, incest is

    mandatory or prohibited, according to one’s social class

    (Bali). In others, the Royal House started a tradition of

    incestuous marriages, later emulated by the lower classes

    (Ancient Egypt). The list is long and it serves to

    demonstrate the diversity of attitudes towards this most

    universal practice.

    The more primitive and aggressive the society, the more

    strict and elaborate the set of incest prohibitions and the

    fiercer the penalties for their violation. The reason may be

    economic. Incest interferes with rigid algorithms of

    inheritance in conditions of extreme scarcity (for instance,

    of land and water) and consequently leads to survival-

    threatening internecine disputes.

    Freud said that incest provokes horror because it touches

    upon our forbidden, ambivalent sexual cravings and

    aggression towards members of our close family.

    Westermark held that “familiarity breeds repulsion” and

    that the incest taboo – rather than counter inbred instincts –

    simply reflects emotional reality. Both ignored the fact

    that the incest taboo is learned – not inherent.

    We can easily imagine a society where incest is extolled,

    taught, and practiced – and out-breeding is regarded with

    horror and revulsion. The incestuous marriages among

    members of the royal households of Europe were intended

    to preserve the familial property and expand the clan’s

    territory. They were normative, not aberrant. Marrying an

    outsider was considered abhorrent.

    III. Suicide

    Self-sacrifice, avoidable martyrdom, engaging in life

    risking activities, refusal to prolong one’s life through

    medical treatment, euthanasia, overdosing, and self-

    destruction that is the result of coercion – are all closely

    related to suicide. They all involve a deliberately self-

    inflicted death.

    But while suicide is chiefly intended to terminate a life –

    the other acts are aimed at perpetuating, strengthening,

    and defending values or other people. Many are appalled

    by the choice implied in suicide – of death over life. They

    feel that it demeans life – i.e., abnegates its meaning.

    Life’s meaning – the outcome of active selection by the

    individual – is either external (i.e., God’s plan) or internal

    (i.e., the outcome of an arbitrary frame of reference).

    Our life is rendered meaningful only by integrating into an

    eternal thing, process, design, or being. Suicide makes life

    trivial because the act is not natural – not part of the

    eternal framework, the undying process, the timeless cycle

    of birth and death. Suicide is a break with eternity.

    Sidgwick said that only conscious (i.e., intelligent) beings

    can appreciate values and meanings. So, life is significant

    to conscious, intelligent, though finite, beings – because it

    is a part of some eternal goal, plan, process, thing, design,

    or being. Suicide flies in the face of Sidgwick’s dictum. It

    is a statement by an intelligent and conscious being about

    the meaninglessness of life.

    If suicide is a statement, than society, in this case, is

    against the freedom of expression. In the case of suicide,

    free speech dissonantly clashes with the sanctity of a

    meaningful life. To rid itself of the anxiety brought on by

    this conflict, society cast suicide as a depraved or even

    criminal act and its perpetrators are much castigated.

    The suicide violates not only the social contract – but,

    many will add, covenants with God or nature. Thomas

    Aquinas said that – since organisms strive to survive –

    suicide is an unnatural act. Moreover, it adversely affects

    the community and violates the property rights of God,

    the imputed owner of one’s spirit. Christianity regards the

    immortal soul as a gift and, in Jewish writings, it is a

    deposit. Suicide amounts to the abuse or misuse of God’s

    possessions, temporarily lodged in a corporeal mansion.

    This paternalism was propagated, centuries later, by

    Blackstone, the codifier of British Law. Suicide – being

    self-murder – is a grave felony, which the state has a right

    to prevent and to punish for.

    In certain countries this still is the case. In Israel, for

    instance, a soldier is considered to be “military property”

    and an attempted suicide is severely punished as “a

    corruption of a army chattel”.

    Paternalism, a malignant mutation of benevolence, is

    about objectifying people and treating them as

    possessions. Even fully-informed and consenting adults

    are not granted full, unmitigated autonomy, freedom, and

    privacy. This tends to breed “victimless crimes”. The

    “culprits” – gamblers, homosexuals, communists, suicides,

    drug addicts, alcoholics, prostitutes – are “protected from

    themselves” by an intrusive nanny state.

    The possession of a right creates a corresponding

    obligation not to act to frustrate its exercise. Suicide is

    often the choice of a mentally and legally competent

    adult. Life is such a basic and deep set phenomenon that

    even the incompetents – the mentally retarded or mentally

    insane or minors – can fully gauge its significance and

    make “informed” decisions, in my view.

    The paternalists claim counterfactually that no competent

    adult “in his right mind” will ever decide to commit

    suicide. They cite the cases of suicides who survived and

    felt very happy that they have – as a compelling reason to

    intervene. But we all make irreversible decisions for

    which, sometimes, we are sorry. It gives no one the right

    to interfere.

    Paternalism is a slippery slope. Should the state be

    allowed to prevent the birth of a genetically defective

    child or forbid his parents to marry in the first place?

    Should unhealthy adults be forced to abstain from

    smoking, or steer clear from alcohol? Should they be

    coerced to exercise?

    Suicide is subject to a double moral standard. People are

    permitted – nay, encouraged – to sacrifice their life only in

    certain, socially sanctioned, ways. To die on the

    battlefield or in defense of one’s religion is commendable.

    This hypocrisy reveals how power structures – the state,

    institutional religion, political parties, national movements

    – aim to monopolize the lives of citizens and adherents to

    do with as they see fit. Suicide threatens this monopoly.

    Hence the taboo.

    IV. Race

    Social Darwinism, sociobiology, and, nowadays,

    evolutionary psychology are all derided and disparaged

    because they try to prove that nature – more specifically,

    our genes – determine our traits, our accomplishments, our

    behavior patterns, our social status, and, in many ways,

    our destiny. Our upbringing and our environment change

    little. They simply select from ingrained libraries

    embedded in our brain.

    Moreover, the discussion of race and race relations is

    tainted by a history of recurrent ethnocide and genocide

    and thwarted by the dogma of egalitarianism. The

    (legitimate) question “are all races equal” thus becomes a

    private case of the (no less legitimate) “are all men equal”.

    To ask “can races co-exist peacefully” is thus to embark

    on the slippery slope to slavery and Auschwitz. These

    historical echoes and the overweening imposition of

    political correctness prevent any meaningful – let alone

    scientific – discourse.

    The irony is that “race” – or at least race as determined by

    skin color – is a distinctly unscientific concept, concerned

    more with appearances (i.e., the color of one’s skin, the

    shape of one’s head or hair), common history, and social

    politics – than with heredity. Most human classificatory

    traits are not concordant. Different taxonomic criteria

    conjure up different “races”. IQ is a similarly contentious

    construct, although it is stable and does predict academic

    achievement effectively.

    Thus, racist-sounding claims are as unfounded as claims

    about racial equality. Still, while the former are treated as

    an abomination – the latter are accorded academic

    respectability and scientific scrutiny.

    Consider these two hypotheses:

    I. That the IQ (or any other measurable trait) of a given

    race or ethnic group is hereditarily determined (i.e., that

    skin color and IQ – or another measurable trait – are

    concordant) and is strongly correlated with certain types

    of behavior, life accomplishments, and social status.

    II. That the IQ (or any other quantifiable trait) of a given

    race or “ethnic group” is the outcome of social and

    economic circumstances and even if strongly correlated

    with behavior patterns, academic or other achievements,

    and social status – which is disputable – is amenable to

    “social engineering”.

    Both theories are falsifiable and both deserve serious,

    unbiased, study. That we choose to ignore the first and

    substantiate the second demonstrates the pernicious and

    corrupting effect of political correctness.

    Claims of the type “trait A and trait B are concordant”

    should be investigated by scientists, regardless of how

    politically incorrect they are. Not so claims of the type

    “people with trait A are …” or “people with trait A do …”.

    These should be decried as racist tripe.

    Thus the statement “The traits of being an Ashkenazi Jew

    (A) and suffering from Tay-Sachs induced idiocy (B) are

    concordant” is true 1 of every 2500 times.

    The statements “people who are Jews (i.e., with trait A)

    are (narcissists)”, or “people who are Jews (i.e., with trait

    A) do this: they drink the blood of innocent Christian

    children during the Passover rites” – are vile racist and

    paranoid statements.

    People are not created equal. Human diversity – a taboo

    topic – is a cause for celebration. It is important to study

    and ascertain what are the respective contributions of

    nature and nurture to the way people – individuals and

    groups – grow, develop, and mature. In the pursuit of this

    invaluable and essential knowledge, taboos are

    dangerously counter-productive.

    V. Moral Relativism

    Protagoras, the Greek Sophist, was the first to notice that

    ethical codes are culture-dependent and vary in different

    societies, economies, and geographies. The pragmatist

    believe that what is right is merely what society thinks is

    right at any given moment. Good and evil are not

    immutable. No moral principle – and taboos are moral

    principles – is universally and eternally true and valid.

    Morality applies within cultures but not across them.

    But ethical or cultural relativism and the various schools

    of pragmatism ignore the fact that certain ethical percepts

    – probably grounded in human nature – do appear to be

    universal and ancient, if not eternal. Fairness, veracity,

    keeping promises, moral hierarchy – permeate all the

    cultures we have come to know. Nor can certain moral

    tenets be explained away as mere expressions of emotions

    or behavioral prescriptions – devoid of cognitive content,

    logic, and a relatedness to certain facts.

    Still, it is easy to prove that most taboos are, indeed,

    relative. Incest, suicide, feticide, infanticide, parricide,

    ethnocide, genocide, genital mutilation, social castes, and

    adultery are normative in certain cultures – and strictly

    proscribed in others. Taboos are pragmatic moral

    principles. They derive their validity from their efficacy.

    They are observed because they work, because they yield

    solutions and provide results. They disappear or are

    transformed when no longer useful.

    Incest is likely to be tolerated in a world with limited

    possibilities for procreation. Suicide is bound to be

    encouraged in a society suffering from extreme scarcity of

    resources and over-population. Ethnocentrism, racism and

    xenophobia will inevitably rear their ugly heads again in

    anomic circumstances. None of these taboos is

    unassailable.

    None of them reflects some objective truth, independent

    of culture and circumstances. They are convenient

    conventions, workable principles, and regulatory

    mechanisms – nothing more. That scholars are frantically

    trying to convince us otherwise – or to exclude such a

    discussion altogether – is a sign of the growing

    disintegration of our weakening society.

    The Merits of Stereotypes
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
    Also Read:

    The Science of Superstitions

    The trouble with people is not that they don’t know but

    that they know so much that ain’t so.

    — Henry Wheeler Shaw

    Do stereotypes usefully represent real knowledge or

    merely reflect counter-productive prejudice?

    Stereotypes invariably refer in a generalized manner to –

    often arbitrary – groups of people, usually minorities.

    Stereotypes need not necessarily be derogatory or

    cautionary, though most of them are. The “noble savage”

    and the “wild savage” are both stereotypes. Indians in

    movies, note Ralph and Natasha Friar in their work titled

    “The Only Good Indian – The Hollywood Gospel” (1972)

    are overwhelmingly drunken, treacherous, unreliable, and

    childlike. Still, some of them are as portrayed as

    unrealistically “good”.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/supers.html

    But alcoholism among Native Americans – especially

    those crammed into reservations – is, indeed, more

    prevalent than among the general population. The

    stereotype conveys true and useful information about

    inebriation among Indians. Could its other descriptors be

    equally accurate?

    It is hard to unambiguously define, let alone quantify,

    traits. At which point does self-centerdness become

    egotism or the pursuit of self-interest – treachery? What

    precisely constitutes childlike behavior? Some types of

    research cannot even be attempted due to the stifling

    censorship of political correctness. Endeavoring to answer

    a simple question like: “Do blacks in America really

    possess lower IQ’s and, if so, is this deficiency

    hereditary?” has landed many an American academic

    beyond the pale.

    The two most castigated aspects of stereotypes are their

    generality and their prejudice. Implied in both criticisms is

    a lack of veracity and rigor of stereotypes. Yet, there is

    nothing wrong with generalizations per se. Science is

    constructed on such abstractions from private case to

    general rule. In historiography we discuss “the Romans”

    or “ancient Greeks” and characterize them as a group.

    “Nazi Germany”, “Communist Russia”, and

    “Revolutionary France” are all forms of groupspeak.

    In an essay titled “Helping Students Understand

    Stereotyping” and published in the April 2001 issue of

    “Education Digest”, Carlos Cortes suggest three

    differences between “group generalizations” and

    “stereotypes”:

    “Group generalizations are flexible and permeable to new,

    countervailing, knowledge – ideas, interpretations, and

    information that challenge or undermine current beliefs.

    Stereotypes are rigid and resistant to change even in the

    face of compelling new evidence.

    Second, group generalizations incorporate intragroup

    heterogeneity while stereotypes foster intragroup

    homogeneity. Group generalizations embrace diversity –

    “there are many kinds of Jews, tall and short, mean and

    generous, clever and stupid, black and white, rich and

    poor”. Stereotypes cast certain individuals as exceptions

    or deviants – “though you are Jewish, you don’t behave as

    a Jew would, you are different”.

    Finally, while generalizations provide mere clues about

    group culture and behavior – stereotypes purport to proffer

    immutable rules applicable to all the members of the

    group. “Stereotypes develop easily, rigidify

    surreptitiously, and operate reflexively, providing simple,

    comfortable, convenient bases for making personal sense

    of the world. Because generalizations require greater

    attention, content flexibility, and nuance in application,

    they do not provide a stereotype’s security blanket of

    permanent, inviolate, all-encompassing, perfectly reliable

    group knowledge.”

    It is commonly believed that stereotypes form the core of

    racism, sexism, homophobia, and other forms of

    xenophobia. Stereotypes, goes the refrain, determine the

    content and thrust of prejudices and propel their advocates

    to take action against minorities. There is a direct lineage,

    it is commonly held, between typecasting and lynching.

    It is also claimed that pigeonholing reduces the quality of

    life, lowers the expectations, and curbs the

    accomplishments of its victims. The glass ceiling and the

    brass ceiling are pernicious phenomena engendered by

    stereotypes. The fate of many social policy issues – such

    as affirmative action, immigration quotas, police profiling,

    and gay service in the military – is determined by

    stereotypes rather than through informed opinion.

    USA Today Magazine reported the findings of a survey of

    1000 girls in grades three to twelve conducted by Harris

    Interactive for “Girls”. Roughly half the respondents

    thought that boys and girls have the same abilities –

    compared to less than one third of boys. A small majority

    of the girls felt that “people think we are only interested in

    love and romance”.

    Somewhat less than two thirds of the girls were told not to

    brag about things they do well and were expected to spend

    the bulk of their time on housework and taking care of

    younger children. Stereotypical thinking had a practical

    effect: girls who believe that they are as able as boys and

    face the same opportunities are way more likely to plan to

    go to college.

    But do boys and girls have the same abilities? Absolutely

    not. Boys are better at spatial orientation and math. Girls

    are better at emotions and relationships. And do girls face

    the same opportunities as boys? It would be perplexing if

    they did, taking into account physiological, cognitive,

    emotional, and reproductive disparities – not to mention

    historical and cultural handicaps. It boils down to this

    politically incorrect statement: girls are not boys and

    never will be.

    Still, there is a long stretch from “girls are not boys” to

    “girls are inferior to boys” and thence to “girls should be

    discriminated against or confined”. Much separates

    stereotypes and generalizations from discriminatory

    practice.

    Discrimination prevails against races, genders, religions,

    people with alternative lifestyles or sexual preferences,

    ethnic groups, the poor, the rich, professionals, and any

    other conceivable minority. It has little to do with

    stereotypes and a lot to do with societal and economic

    power matrices. Granted, most racists typecast blacks and

    Indians, Jews and Latinos. But typecasting in itself does

    not amount to racism, nor does it inevitably lead to

    discriminatory conduct.

    In a multi-annual study titled “Economic Insecurity,

    Prejudicial Stereotypes, and Public Opinion on

    Immigration Policy”, published by the Political Science

    Quarterly, the authors Peter Burns and James Gimpel

    substantiated the hypothesis that “economic self-interest

    and symbolic prejudice have often been treated as rival

    explanations for attitudes on a wide variety of issues, but

    it is plausible that they are complementary on an issue

    such as immigration. This would be the case if prejudice

    were caused, at least partly, by economic insecurity.”

    A long list of scholarly papers demonstrate how racism –

    especially among the dispossessed, dislocated, and low-

    skilled – surges during times of economic hardship or

    social transition. Often there is a confluence of long-

    established racial and ethnic stereotypes with a growing

    sense of economic insecurity and social dislocation.

    “Social Identity Theory” tells us that stereotypical

    prejudice is a form of compensatory narcissism. The acts

    of berating, demeaning, denigrating, and debasing others

    serve to enhance the perpetrators’ self-esteem and regulate

    their labile sense of self-worth. It is vicarious “pride by

    proxy” – belonging to an “elite” group bestows superiority

    on all its members. Not surprisingly, education has some

    positive influence on racist attitudes and political

    ideology.

    Having been entangled – sometimes unjustly – with

    bigotry and intolerance, the merits of stereotypes have

    often been overlooked.

    In an age of information overload, “nutshell” stereotypes

    encapsulate information compactly and efficiently and

    thus possess an undeniable survival value. Admittedly,

    many stereotypes are self-reinforcing, self-fulfilling

    prophecies. A young black man confronted by a white

    supremacist may well respond violently and an Hispanic,

    unable to find a job, may end up is a street gang.

    But this recursiveness does not detract from the usefulness

    of stereotypes as “reality tests” and serviceable

    prognosticators. Blacks do commit crimes over and above

    their proportion in the general population. Though

    stereotypical in the extreme, it is a useful fact to know and

    act upon. Hence racial profiling.

    Stereotypes – like fables – are often constructed around

    middle class morality and are prescriptive. They split the

    world into the irredeemably bad – the other, blacks, Jews,

    http://samvak.tripod.com/14.html

    Hispanics, women, gay – and the flawlessly good, we, the

    purveyors of the stereotype. While expressly unrealistic,

    the stereotype teaches “what not to be” and “how not to

    behave”. A by-product of this primitive rendition is

    segregation.

    A large body of scholarship shows that proximity and

    familiarity actually polarize rather than ameliorate inter-

    ethnic and inter-racial tensions. Stereotypes minimize

    friction and violence by keeping minorities and the

    majority apart. Venting and vaunting substitute for

    vandalizing and worse. In time, as erstwhile minorities are

    gradually assimilated and new ones emerge, conflict is

    averted.

    Moreover, though they frequently reflect underlying

    deleterious emotions – such as rage or envy – not all

    stereotypes are negative. Blacks are supposed to have

    superior musical and athletic skills. Jews are thought to be

    brainier in science and shrewder in business. Hispanics

    uphold family values and ethnic cohesion. Gays are

    sensitive and compassionate. And negative stereotypes are

    attached even to positive social roles – athletes are dumb

    and violent, soldiers inflexible and programmed.

    Stereotypes are selective filters. Supporting data is

    hoarded and information to the contrary is ignored. One

    way to shape stereotypes into effective coping strategies is

    to bombard their devotees with “exceptions”, contexts,

    and alternative reasoning.

    Blacks are good athletes because sports is one of the few

    egalitarian career paths open to them. Jews, historically

    excluded from all professions, crowded into science and

    business and specialized. If gays are indeed more sensitive

    or caring than the average perhaps it is because they have

    been repressed and persecuted for so long. Athletes are

    not prone to violence – violent athletes simply end up on

    TV more often. And soldiers have to act reflexively to

    survive in battle.

    There is nothing wrong with stereotypes if they are

    embedded in reality and promote the understanding of

    social and historical processes. Western, multi-ethnic,

    pluralistic civilization celebrates diversity and the

    uniqueness and distinctiveness of its components.

    Stereotypes merely acknowledge this variety.

    USA Today Magazine reported in January a survey of 800

    adults, conducted last year by social psychology

    professors Amanda Diekman of Purdue University and

    Alice Eagly of Northwestern University. They found that

    far from being rigid and biased, stereotypes regarding the

    personality traits of men and women have changed

    dramatically to accurately reflect evolving gender roles.

    Diekman noted that “women are perceived as having

    become much more assertive, independent, and

    competitive over the years … Our respondents – whether

    they were old enough to have witnessed it or not –

    recognized the role change that occurred when women

    began working outside the home in large numbers and the

    necessity of adopting characteristics that equip them to be

    breadwinners.”

    The Happiness of Others

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    Is there any necessary connection between our actions and

    the happiness of others? Disregarding for a moment the

    murkiness of the definitions of “actions” in philosophical

    literature – two types of answers were hitherto provided.

    Sentient Beings (referred to, in this essay, as “Humans” or

    “persons”) seem either to limit each other – or to enhance

    each other’s actions. Mutual limitation is, for instance,

    evident in game theory. It deals with decision outcomes

    when all the rational “players” are fully aware of both the

    outcomes of their actions and of what they prefer these

    outcomes to be. They are also fully informed about the

    other players: they know that they are rational, too, for

    instance. This, of course, is a very farfetched idealization.

    A state of unbounded information is nowhere and never to

    be found. Still, in most cases, the players settle down to

    one of the Nash equilibria solutions. Their actions are

    constrained by the existence of the others.

    The “Hidden Hand” of Adam Smith (which, among other

    things, benignly and optimally regulates the market and

    the price mechanisms) – is also a “mutually limiting”

    model. Numerous single participants strive to maximize

    their (economic and financial) outcomes – and end up

    merely optimizing them.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    The reason lies in the existence of others within the

    “market”. Again, they are constrained by other people‘s

    motivations, priorities ands, above all, actions.

    All the consequentialist theories of ethics deal with

    mutual enhancement. This is especially true of the

    Utilitarian variety. Acts (whether judged individually or in

    conformity to a set of rules) are moral, if their outcome

    increases utility (also known as happiness or pleasure).

    They are morally obligatory if they maximize utility and

    no alternative course of action can do so. Other versions

    talk about an “increase” in utility rather than its

    maximization. Still, the principle is simple: for an act to

    be judged “moral, ethical, virtuous, or good” – it must

    influence others in a way which will “enhance” and

    increase their happiness.

    The flaws in all the above answers are evident and have

    been explored at length in the literature. The assumptions

    are dubious (fully informed participants, rationality in

    decision making and in prioritizing the outcomes, etc.).

    All the answers are instrumental and quantitative: they

    strive to offer a moral measuring rod. An “increase”

    entails the measurement of two states: before and after the

    act. Moreover, it demands full knowledge of the world

    and a type of knowledge so intimate, so private – that it is

    not even sure that the players themselves have conscious

    access to it. Who goes around equipped with an

    exhaustive list of his priorities and another list of all the

    possible outcomes of all the acts that he may commit?

    But there is another, basic flaw: these answers are

    descriptive, observational, phenomenological in the

    restrictive sense of these words. The motives, the drives,

    the urges, the whole psychological landscape behind the

    act are deemed irrelevant. The only thing relevant is the

    increase in utility/happiness. If the latter is achieved – the

    former might as well not have existed. A computer, which

    increases happiness is morally equivalent to a person who

    achieves a quantitatively similar effect. Even worse: two

    persons acting out of different motives (one malicious and

    one benevolent) will be judged to be morally equivalent if

    their acts were to increase happiness similarly.

    But, in life, an increase in utility or happiness or pleasure

    is CONDITIONED upon, is the RESULT of the motives

    behind the acts that led to it. Put differently: the utility

    functions of two acts depend decisively on the motivation,

    drive, or urge behind them. The process, which leads to

    the act is an inseparable part of the act and of its

    outcomes, including the outcomes in terms of the

    subsequent increase in utility or happiness. We can safely

    distinguish the “utility contaminated” act from the “utility

    pure (or ideal)” act.

    If a person does something which is supposed to increase

    the overall utility – but does so in order to increase his

    own utility more than the expected average utility increase

    – the resulting increase will be lower. The maximum

    utility increase is achieved overall when the actor forgoes

    all increase in his personal utility. It seems that there is a

    constant of utility increase and a conservation law

    pertaining to it.

    So that a disproportionate increase in one’s personal utility

    translates into a decrease in the overall average utility. It

    is not a zero sum game because of the infiniteness of the

    potential increase – but the rules of distribution of the

    utility added after the act, seem to dictate an averaging of

    the increase in order to maximize the result.

    The same pitfalls await these observations as did the

    previous ones. The players must be in the possession of

    full information at least regarding the motivation of the

    other players. “Why is he doing this?” and “why did he do

    what he did?” are not questions confined to the criminal

    courts. We all want to understand the “why’s” of actions

    long before we engage in utilitarian calculations of

    increased utility. This also seems to be the source of many

    an emotional reaction concerning human actions. We are

    envious because we think that the utility increase was

    unevenly divided (when adjusted for efforts invested and

    for the prevailing cultural mores). We suspect outcomes

    that are “too good to be true”. Actually, this very sentence

    proves my point: that even if something produces an

    increase in overall happiness it will be considered morally

    dubious if the motivation behind it remains unclear or

    seems to be irrational or culturally deviant.

    Two types of information are, therefore, always needed:

    one (discussed above) concerns the motives of the main

    protagonists, the act-ors. The second type relates to the

    world. Full knowledge about the world is also a necessity:

    the causal chains (actions lead to outcomes), what

    increases the overall utility or happiness and for whom,

    etc.

    To assume that all the participants in an interaction

    possess this tremendous amount of information is an

    idealization (used also in modern theories of economy),

    should be regarded as such and not be confused with

    reality in which people approximate, estimate, extrapolate

    and evaluate based on a much more limited knowledge.

    Two examples come to mind:

    Aristotle described the “Great Soul”. It is a virtuous agent

    (actor, player) that judges himself to be possessed of a

    great soul (in a self-referential evaluative disposition). He

    has the right measure of his worth and he courts the

    appreciation of his peers (but not of his inferiors) which

    he believes that he deserves by virtue of being virtuous.

    He has a dignity of demeanour, which is also very self-

    conscious. He is, in short, magnanimous (for instance, he

    forgives his enemies their offences). He seems to be the

    classical case of a happiness-increasing agent – but he is

    not. And the reason that he fails in qualifying as such is

    that his motives are suspect. Does he refrain from

    assaulting his enemies because of charity and generosity

    of spirit – or because it is likely to dent his pomposity? It

    is sufficient that a POSSIBLE different motive exist – to

    ruin the utilitarian outcome.

    Adam Smith, on the other hand, adopted the spectator

    theory of his teacher Francis Hutcheson. The morally

    good is a euphemism. It is really the name provided to the

    pleasure, which a spectator derives from seeing a virtue in

    action. Smith added that the reason for this emotion is the

    similarity between the virtue observed in the agent and the

    virtue possessed by the observer.

    It is of a moral nature because of the object involved: the

    agent tries to consciously conform to standards of

    behaviour which will not harm the innocent, while,

    simultaneously benefiting himself, his family and his

    friends. This, in turn, will benefit society as a whole. Such

    a person is likely to be grateful to his benefactors and

    sustain the chain of virtue by reciprocating. The chain of

    good will, thus, endlessly multiply.

    Even here, we see that the question of motive and

    psychology is of utmost importance. WHY is the agent

    doing what he is doing? Does he really conform to

    society’s standards INTERNALLY? Is he GRATEFUL to

    his benefactors? Does he WISH to benefit his friends?

    These are all questions answerable only in the realm of

    the mind. Really, they are not answerable at all.

    The Egotistic Friend

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    What are friends for and how can a friendship be tested?

    By behaving altruistically, would be the most common

    answer and by sacrificing one’s interests in favour of one’s

    friends. Friendship implies the converse of egoism, both

    psychologically and ethically. But then we say that the

    dog is “man’s best friend”. After all, it is characterized by

    unconditional love, by unselfish behaviour, by sacrifice,

    when necessary. Isn’t this the epitome of friendship?

    Apparently not. On the one hand, the dog’s friendship

    seems to be unaffected by long term calculations of

    personal benefit. But that is not to say that it is not

    affected by calculations of a short-term nature. The

    owner, after all, looks after the dog and is the source of its

    subsistence and security. People – and dogs – have been

    known to have sacrificed their lives for less. The dog is

    selfish – it clings and protects what it regards to be its

    territory and its property (including – and especially so –

    the owner). Thus, the first condition, seemingly not

    satisfied by canine attachment is that it be reasonably

    unselfish.

    There are, however, more important conditions:

    a. For a real friendship to exist – at least one of the
    friends must be a conscious and intelligent entity,

    possessed of mental states. It can be an individual,

    or a collective of individuals, but in both cases this

    requirement will similarly apply.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    b. There must be a minimal level of identical mental
    states between the terms of the equation of

    friendship. A human being cannot be friends with

    a tree (at least not in the fullest sense of the word).

    c. The behaviour must not be deterministic, lest it be
    interpreted as instinct driven. A conscious choice

    must be involved. This is a very surprising

    conclusion: the more “reliable”, the more

    “predictable” – the less appreciated. Someone who

    reacts identically to similar situations, without

    dedicating a first, let alone a second thought to it –

    his acts would be depreciated as “automatic

    responses”.

    For a pattern of behaviour to be described as “friendship”,

    these four conditions must be met: diminished egoism,

    conscious and intelligent agents, identical mental states

    (allowing for the communication of the friendship) and

    non-deterministic behaviour, the result of constant

    decision making.

    A friendship can be – and often is – tested in view of these

    criteria. There is a paradox underlying the very notion of

    testing a friendship. A real friend would never test his

    friend’s commitment and allegiance. Anyone who puts his

    friend to a test (deliberately) would hardly qualify as a

    friend himself. But circumstances can put ALL the

    members of a friendship, all the individuals (two or more)

    in the “collective” to a test of friendship. Financial

    hardship encountered by someone would surely oblige his

    friends to assist him – even if he himself did not take the

    initiative and explicitly asked them to do so. It is life that

    tests the resilience and strength and depth of true

    friendships – not the friends themselves.

    In all the discussions of egoism versus altruism –

    confusion between self-interest and self-welfare prevails.

    A person may be urged on to act by his self-interest,

    which might be detrimental to his (long-term) self-

    welfare. Some behaviours and actions can satisfy short-

    term desires, urges, wishes (in short: self-interest) – and

    yet be self- destructive or otherwise adversely effect the

    individual’s future welfare. (Psychological) Egoism

    should, therefore, be re-defined as the active pursuit of

    self- welfare, not of self-interest. Only when the person

    caters, in a balanced manner, to both his present (self-

    interest) and his future (self-welfare) interests – can we

    call him an egoist. Otherwise, if he caters only to his

    immediate self-interest, seeks to fulfil his desires and

    disregards the future costs of his behaviour – he is an

    animal, not an egoist.

    Joseph Butler separated the main (motivating) desire from

    the desire that is self- interest. The latter cannot exist

    without the former. A person is hungry and this is his

    desire. His self-interest is, therefore, to eat. But the hunger

    is directed at eating – not at fulfilling self-interests. Thus,

    hunger generates self-interest (to eat) but its object is

    eating. Self-interest is a second order desire that aims to

    satisfy first order desires (which can also motivate us

    directly).

    This subtle distinction can be applied to disinterested

    behaviours, acts, which seem to lack a clear self-interest

    or even a first order desire. Consider why do people

    contribute to humanitarian causes? There is no self-

    interest here, even if we account for the global picture

    (with every possible future event in the life of the

    contributor).

    No rich American is likely to find himself starving in

    Somalia, the target of one such humanitarian aid mission.

    But even here the Butler model can be validated. The first

    order desire of the donator is to avoid anxiety feelings

    generated by a cognitive dissonance. In the process of

    socialization we are all exposed to altruistic messages.

    They are internalized by us (some even to the extent of

    forming part of the almighty superego, the conscience). In

    parallel, we assimilate the punishment inflicted upon

    members of society who are not “social” enough,

    unwilling to contribute beyond that which is required to

    satisfy their self interest, selfish or egoistic, non-

    conformist, “too” individualistic, “too” idiosyncratic or

    eccentric, etc. Completely not being altruistic is “bad” and

    as such calls for “punishment”. This no longer is an

    outside judgement, on a case by case basis, with the

    penalty inflicted by an external moral authority. This

    comes from the inside: the opprobrium and reproach, the

    guilt, the punishment (read Kafka). Such impending

    punishment generates anxiety whenever the person judges

    himself not to have been altruistically “sufficient”. It is to

    avoid this anxiety or to quell it that a person engages in

    altruistic acts, the result of his social conditioning. To use

    the Butler scheme: the first-degree desire is to avoid the

    agonies of cognitive dissonance and the resulting anxiety.

    This can be achieved by committing acts of altruism. The

    second-degree desire is the self-interest to commit

    altruistic acts in order to satisfy the first-degree desire. No

    one engages in contributing to the poor because he wants

    them to be less poor or in famine relief because he does

    not want others to starve. People do these apparently

    selfless activities because they do not want to experience

    that tormenting inner voice and to suffer the acute anxiety,

    which accompanies it.

    Altruism is the name that we give to successful

    indoctrination. The stronger the process of socialization,

    the stricter the education, the more severely brought up

    the individual, the grimmer and more constraining his

    superego – the more of an altruist he is likely to be.

    Independent people who really feel comfortable with their

    selves are less likely to exhibit these behaviours.

    This is the self-interest of society: altruism enhances the

    overall level of welfare. It redistributes resources more

    equitably, it tackles market failures more or less

    efficiently (progressive tax systems are altruistic), it

    reduces social pressures and stabilizes both individuals

    and society. Clearly, the self-interest of society is to make

    its members limit the pursuit of their own self-interest?

    There are many opinions and theories. They can be

    grouped into:

    a. Those who see an inverse relation between the
    two: the more satisfied the self interests of the

    individuals comprising a society – the worse off

    that society will end up. What is meant by “better

    off” is a different issue but at least the

    commonsense, intuitive, meaning is clear and begs

    no explanation. Many religions and strands of

    moral absolutism espouse this view.

    b. Those who believe that the more satisfied the self-
    interests of the individuals comprising a society –

    the better off this society will end up. These are

    the “hidden hand” theories. Individuals, which

    strive merely to maximize their utility, their

    happiness, their returns (profits) – find themselves

    inadvertently engaged in a colossal endeavour to

    better their society.

    This is mostly achieved through the dual mechanisms

    of market and price. Adam Smith is an example (and

    other schools of the dismal science).

    c. Those who believe that a delicate balance must
    exist between the two types of self-interest: the

    private and the public. While most individuals will

    be unable to obtain the full satisfaction of their

    self-interest – it is still conceivable that they will

    attain most of it. On the other hand, society must

    not fully tread on individuals’ rights to self-

    fulfilment, wealth accumulation and the pursuit of

    happiness. So, it must accept less than maximum

    satisfaction of its self-interest. The optimal mix

    exists and is, probably, of the minimax type. This

    is not a zero sum game and society and the

    individuals comprising it can maximize their worst

    outcomes.

    The French have a saying: “Good bookkeeping – makes

    for a good friendship”. Self-interest, altruism and the

    interest of society at large are not necessarily

    incompatible.

    The Distributive Justice of the Market

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    Also published by United Press International (UPI)

    Also Read

    The Principal-Agent Conundrum

    The Green-Eyed Capitalist

    The Misconception of Scarcity

    The public outcry against executive pay and compensation

    followed disclosures of insider trading, double dealing,

    and outright fraud. But even honest and productive

    entrepreneurs often earn more money in one year than

    Albert Einstein did in his entire life. This strikes many –

    especially academics – as unfair. Surely Einstein’s

    contributions to human knowledge and welfare far exceed

    anything ever accomplished by sundry businessmen?

    Fortunately, this discrepancy is cause for constructive

    jealousy, emulation, and imitation. It can, however, lead

    to an orgy of destructive and self-ruinous envy.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://www.upi.com/view.cfm?StoryID=20020814-111702-4527r

    http://samvak.tripod.com/pp165.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/pp168.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/scarcity.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/pp167.html

    Entrepreneurs recombine natural and human resources in

    novel ways. They do so to respond to forecasts of future

    needs, or to observations of failures and shortcomings of

    current products or services. Entrepreneurs are

    professional – though usually intuitive – futurologists. This

    is a valuable service and it is financed by systematic risk

    takers, such as venture capitalists. Surely they all deserve

    compensation for their efforts and the hazards they

    assume?

    Exclusive ownership is the most ancient type of such

    remuneration. First movers, entrepreneurs, risk takers,

    owners of the wealth they generated, exploiters of

    resources – are allowed to exclude others from owning or

    exploiting the same things. Mineral concessions, patents,

    copyright, trademarks – are all forms of monopoly

    ownership. What moral right to exclude others is gained

    from being the first?

    Nozick advanced Locke’s Proviso. An exclusive

    ownership of property is just only if “enough and as good

    is left in common for others”. If it does not worsen other

    people’s lot, exclusivity is morally permissible. It can be

    argued, though, that all modes of exclusive ownership

    aggravate other people’s situation. As far as everyone, bar

    the entrepreneur, are concerned, exclusivity also prevents

    a more advantageous distribution of income and wealth.

    Exclusive ownership reflects real-life irreversibility. A

    first mover has the advantage of excess information and of

    irreversibly invested work, time, and effort. Economic

    enterprise is subject to information asymmetry: we know

    nothing about the future and everything about the past.

    This asymmetry is known as “investment risk”. Society

    compensates the entrepreneur with one type of asymmetry

    – exclusive ownership – for assuming another, the

    investment risk.

    One way of looking at it is that all others are worse off by

    the amount of profits and rents accruing to owner-

    entrepreneurs. Profits and rents reflect an intrinsic

    inefficiency. Another is to recall that ownership is the

    result of adding value to the world. It is only reasonable to

    expect it to yield to the entrepreneur at least this value

    added now and in the future.

    In a “Theory of Justice” (published 1971, p. 302), John

    Rawls described an ideal society thus:

    “(1) Each person is to have an equal right to the most

    extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible

    with a similar system of liberty for all. (2) Social and

    economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are

    both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged,

    consistent with the just savings principle, and (b) attached

    to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair

    equality of opportunity. ”

    It all harks back to scarcity of resources – land, money,

    raw materials, manpower, creative brains. Those who can

    afford to do so, hoard resources to offset anxiety

    regarding future uncertainty. Others wallow in paucity.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/scarcity.html

    The distribution of means is thus skewed. “Distributive

    justice” deals with the just allocation of scarce resources.

    Yet, even the basic terminology is somewhat fuzzy. What

    constitutes a resource? what is meant by allocation? Who

    should allocate resources – Adam Smith’s “invisible

    hand”, the government, the consumer, or business? Should

    it reflect differences in power, in intelligence, in

    knowledge, or in heredity? Should resource allocation be

    subject to a principle of entitlement? Is it reasonable to

    demand that it be just – or merely efficient? Are justice

    and efficiency antonyms?

    Justice is concerned with equal access to opportunities.

    Equal access does not guarantee equal outcomes,

    invariably determined by idiosyncrasies and differences

    between people. Access leveraged by the application of

    natural or acquired capacities – translates into accrued

    wealth. Disparities in these capacities lead to

    discrepancies in accrued wealth.

    The doctrine of equal access is founded on the

    equivalence of Men. That all men are created equal and

    deserve the same respect and, therefore, equal treatment is

    not self evident. European aristocracy well into this

    century would have probably found this notion abhorrent.

    Jose Ortega Y Gasset, writing in the 1930’s, preached that

    access to educational and economic opportunities should

    be premised on one’s lineage, up bringing, wealth, and

    social responsibilities.

    A succession of societies and cultures discriminated

    against the ignorant, criminals, atheists, females,

    homosexuals, members of ethnic, religious, or racial

    groups, the old, the immigrant, and the poor. Communism

    – ostensibly a strict egalitarian idea – foundered because it

    failed to reconcile strict equality with economic and

    psychological realities within an impatient timetable.

    Philosophers tried to specify a “bundle” or “package” of

    goods, services, and intangibles (like information, or

    skills, or knowledge). Justice – though not necessarily

    happiness – is when everyone possesses an identical

    bundle. Happiness – though not necessarily justice – is

    when each one of us possesses a “bundle” which reflects

    his or her preferences, priorities, and predilections. None

    of us will be too happy with a standardized bundle,

    selected by a committee of philosophers – or bureaucrats,

    as was the case under communism.

    The market allows for the exchange of goods and services

    between holders of identical bundles. If I seek books, but

    detest oranges – I can swap them with someone in return

    for his books. That way both of us are rendered better off

    than under the strict egalitarian version.

    Still, there is no guarantee that I will find my exact match

    – a person who is interested in swapping his books for my

    oranges. Illiquid, small, or imperfect markets thus inhibit

    the scope of these exchanges. Additionally, exchange

    participants have to agree on an index: how many books

    for how many oranges? This is the price of oranges in

    terms of books.

    Money – the obvious “index” – does not solve this

    problem, merely simplifies it and facilitates exchanges. It

    does not eliminate the necessity to negotiate an “exchange

    rate”. It does not prevent market failures. In other words:

    money is not an index. It is merely a medium of exchange

    and a store of value. The index – as expressed in terms of

    money – is the underlying agreement regarding the values

    of resources in terms of other resources (i.e., their relative

    values).

    The market – and the price mechanism – increase

    happiness and welfare by allowing people to alter the

    composition of their bundles. The invisible hand is just

    and benevolent. But money is imperfect. The

    aforementioned Rawles demonstrated (1971), that we

    need to combine money with other measures in order to

    place a value on intangibles.

    The prevailing market theories postulate that everyone has

    the same resources at some initial point (the “starting

    gate”). It is up to them to deploy these endowments and,

    thus, to ravage or increase their wealth. While the initial

    distribution is equal – the end distribution depends on how

    wisely – or imprudently – the initial distribution was used.

    Egalitarian thinkers proposed to equate everyone’s income

    in each time frame (e.g., annually). But identical incomes

    do not automatically yield the same accrued wealth. The

    latter depends on how the income is used – saved,

    invested, or squandered. Relative disparities of wealth are

    bound to emerge, regardless of the nature of income

    distribution.

    Some say that excess wealth should be confiscated and

    redistributed. Progressive taxation and the welfare

    state

    aim to secure this outcome. Redistributive mechanisms

    reset the “wealth clock” periodically (at the end of every

    month, or fiscal year). In many countries, the law dictates

    which portion of one’s income must be saved and, by

    implication, how much can be consumed. This conflicts

    with basic rights like the freedom to make economic

    choices.

    The legalized expropriation of income (i.e., taxes) is

    morally dubious. Anti-tax movements have sprung all

    over the world and their philosophy permeates the

    ideology of political parties in many countries, not least

    the USA. Taxes are punitive: they penalize enterprise,

    success, entrepreneurship, foresight, and risk assumption.

    Welfare, on the other hand, rewards dependence and

    parasitism.

    According to Rawles’ Difference Principle, all tenets of

    justice are either redistributive or retributive. This ignores

    non-economic activities and human inherent variance.

    Moreover, conflict and inequality are the engines of

    growth and innovation – which mostly benefit the least

    advantaged in the long run. Experience shows that

    unmitigated equality results in atrophy, corruption and

    stagnation. Thermodynamics teaches us that life and

    motion are engendered by an irregular distribution of

    energy. Entropy – an even distribution of energy – equals

    death and stasis.

    What about the disadvantaged and challenged – the

    mentally retarded, the mentally insane, the paralyzed, the

    chronically ill? For that matter, what about the less

    talented, less skilled, less daring? Dworkin (1981)

    proposed a compensation scheme. He suggested a model

    of fair distribution in which every person is given the

    same purchasing power and uses it to bid, in a fair

    auction, for resources that best fit that person’s life plan,

    goals and preferences.

    Having thus acquired these resources, we are then

    permitted to use them as we see fit. Obviously, we end up

    with disparate economic results. But we cannot complain –

    we were given the same purchasing power and the

    freedom to bid for a bundle of our choice.

    Dworkin assumes that prior to the hypothetical auction,

    people are unaware of their own natural endowments but

    are willing and able to insure against being naturally

    disadvantaged. Their payments create an insurance pool to

    compensate the less fortunate for their misfortune.

    This, of course, is highly unrealistic. We are usually very

    much aware of natural endowments and liabilities – both

    ours and others’. Therefore, the demand for such insurance

    is not universal, nor uniform. Some of us badly need and

    want it – others not at all. It is morally acceptable to let

    willing buyers and sellers to trade in such coverage (e.g.,

    by offering charity or alms) – but may be immoral to make

    it compulsory.

    Most of the modern welfare programs are involuntary

    Dworkin schemes. Worse yet, they often measure

    differences in natural endowments arbitrarily, compensate

    for lack of acquired skills, and discriminate between types

    of endowments in accordance with cultural biases and

    fads.

    Libertarians limit themselves to ensuring a level playing

    field of just exchanges, where just actions always result in

    just outcomes. Justice is not dependent on a particular

    distribution pattern, whether as a starting point, or as an

    outcome. Robert Nozick “Entitlement Theory” proposed

    in 1974 is based on this approach.

    That the market is wiser than any of its participants is a

    pillar of the philosophy of capitalism. In its pure form, the

    theory claims that markets yield patterns of merited

    distribution – i.e., reward and punish justly. Capitalism

    generate just deserts. Market failures – for instance, in the

    provision of public goods – should be tackled by

    governments. But a just distribution of income and wealth

    does not constitute a market failure and, therefore, should

    not be tampered with.

    The Agent-Principal Conundrum

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    Also published by United Press International (UPI

    In the catechism of capitalism, shares represent the part-

    ownership of an economic enterprise, usually a firm. The

    value of shares is determined by the replacement value of

    the assets of the firm, including intangibles such as

    goodwill. The price of the share is determined by

    transactions among arm’s length buyers and sellers in an

    efficient and liquid market. The price reflects expectations

    regarding the future value of the firm and the stock’s

    future stream of income – i.e., dividends.

    Alas, none of these oft-recited dogmas bears any

    resemblance to reality. Shares rarely represent ownership.

    The float – the number of shares available to the public – is

    frequently marginal. Shareholders meet once a year to

    vent and disperse. Boards of directors are appointed by

    management – as are auditors. Shareholders are not

    represented in any decision making process – small or big.

    The dismal truth is that shares reify the expectation to find

    future buyers at a higher price and thus incur capital gains.

    In the Ponzi scheme known as the stock exchange, this

    expectation is proportional to liquidity – new suckers – and

    volatility. Thus, the price of any given stock reflects

    merely the consensus as to how easy it would be to

    offload one’s holdings and at what price.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://www.upi.com/view.cfm?StoryID=20020725-113250-6845r

    Another myth has to do with the role of managers. They

    are supposed to generate higher returns to shareholders by

    increasing the value of the firm’s assets and, therefore, of

    the firm. If they fail to do so, goes the moral tale, they are

    booted out mercilessly. This is one manifestation of the

    “Principal-Agent Problem”. It is defined thus by the

    Oxford Dictionary of Economics:

    “The problem of how a person A can motivate person B to

    act for A’s benefit rather than following (his) self-

    interest.”

    The obvious answer is that A can never motivate B not to

    follow B’s self-interest – never mind what the incentives

    are. That economists pretend otherwise – in “optimal

    contracting theory” – just serves to demonstrate how

    divorced economics is from human psychology and, thus,

    from reality.

    Managers will always rob blind the companies they run.

    They will always manipulate boards to collude in their

    shenanigans. They will always bribe auditors to bend the

    rules. In other words, they will always act in their self-

    interest. In their defense, they can say that the damage

    from such actions to each shareholder is minuscule while

    the benefits to the manager are enormous. In other words,

    this is the rational, self-interested, thing to do.

    But why do shareholders cooperate with such corporate

    brigandage? In an important Chicago Law Review article

    whose preprint was posted to the Web a few weeks ago –

    titled “Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the

    Design of Executive Compensation” – the authors

    demonstrate how the typical stock option granted to

    managers as part of their remuneration rewards mediocrity

    rather than encourages excellence.

    But everything falls into place if we realize that

    shareholders and managers are allied against the firm – not

    pitted against each other. The paramount interest of both

    shareholders and managers is to increase the value of the

    stock – regardless of the true value of the firm. Both are

    concerned with the performance of the share – rather than

    the performance of the firm. Both are preoccupied with

    boosting the share’s price – rather than the company’s

    business.

    Hence the inflationary executive pay packets.

    Shareholders hire stock manipulators – euphemistically

    known as “managers” – to generate expectations regarding

    the future prices of their shares. These snake oil salesmen

    and snake charmers – the corporate executives – are

    allowed by shareholders to loot the company providing

    they generate consistent capital gains to their masters by

    provoking persistent interest and excitement around the

    business. Shareholders, in other words, do not behave as

    owners of the firm – they behave as free-riders.

    The Principal-Agent Problem arises in other social

    interactions and is equally misunderstood there. Consider

    taxpayers and their government. Contrary to conservative

    lore, the former want the government to tax them

    providing they share in the spoils.

    They tolerate corruption in high places, cronyism,

    nepotism, inaptitude and worse – on condition that the

    government and the legislature redistribute the wealth

    they confiscate. Such redistribution often comes in the

    form of pork barrel projects and benefits to the middle-

    class.

    This is why the tax burden and the government’s share of

    GDP have been soaring inexorably with the consent of the

    citizenry. People adore government spending precisely

    because it is inefficient and distorts the proper allocation

    of economic resources. The vast majority of people are

    rent-seekers. Witness the mass demonstrations that erupt

    whenever governments try to slash expenditures,

    privatize, and eliminate their gaping deficits. This is one

    reason the IMF with its austerity measures is universally

    unpopular.

    Employers and employees, producers and consumers –

    these are all instances of the Principal-Agent Problem.

    Economists would do well to discard their models and go

    back to basics. They could start by asking:

    Why do shareholders acquiesce with executive

    malfeasance as long as share prices are rising?

    Why do citizens protest against a smaller government –

    even though it means lower taxes?

    Could it mean that the interests of shareholders and

    managers are identical? Does it imply that people prefer

    tax-and-spend governments and pork barrel politics to the

    Thatcherite alternative?

    Nothing happens by accident or by coercion. Shareholders

    aided and abetted the current crop of corporate executives

    enthusiastically. They knew well what was happening.

    They may not have been aware of the exact nature and

    extent of the rot – but they witnessed approvingly the

    public relations antics, insider trading, stock option

    resetting , unwinding, and unloading, share price

    manipulation, opaque transactions, and outlandish pay

    packages. Investors remained mum throughout the

    corruption of corporate America. It is time for the

    hangover.

    Legalizing Crime
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
    Also Read:

    Narcissists, Ethnic or Religious Affiliation, and

    Terrorists

    The state has a monopoly on behavior usually deemed

    criminal. It murders, kidnaps, and locks up people.

    Sovereignty has come to be identified with the unbridled –

    and exclusive – exercise of violence. The emergence of

    modern international law has narrowed the field of

    permissible conduct. A sovereign can no longer commit

    genocide or ethnic cleansing with impunity, for instance.

    Many acts – such as the waging of aggressive war, the

    mistreatment of minorities, the suppression of the freedom

    of association – hitherto sovereign privilege, have

    thankfully been criminalized. Many politicians, hitherto

    immune to international prosecution, are no longer so.

    Consider Yugoslavia’s Milosevic and Chile’s Pinochet.

    But, the irony is that a similar trend of criminalization –

    within national legal systems – allows governments to

    oppress their citizenry to an extent previously unknown.

    Hitherto civil torts, permissible acts, and common

    behavior patterns are routinely criminalized by legislators

    and regulators. Precious few are decriminalized.

    http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/cv.html

    http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/12.html

    http://www.geocities.com/vaksam/12.html

    Consider, for instance, the criminalization in the

    Economic Espionage Act (1996) of the misappropriation

    of trade secrets and the criminalization of the violation of

    copyrights in the Digital Millennium Copyright Act

    (2000) – both in the USA. These used to be civil torts.

    They still are in many countries. Drug use, common

    behavior in England only 50 years ago – is now criminal.

    The list goes on.

    Criminal laws pertaining to property have malignantly

    proliferated and pervaded every economic and private

    interaction. The result is a bewildering multitude of laws,

    regulations statutes, and acts.

    The average Babylonian could have memorizes and

    assimilated the Hammurabic code 37 centuries ago – it

    was short, simple, and intuitively just.

    English criminal law – partly applicable in many of its

    former colonies, such as India, Pakistan, Canada, and

    Australia – is a mishmash of overlapping and

    contradictory statutes – some of these hundreds of years

    old – and court decisions, collectively known as “case

    law”.

    Despite the publishing of a Model Penal Code in 1962 by

    the American Law Institute, the criminal provisions of

    various states within the USA often conflict. The typical

    American can’t hope to get acquainted with even a

    negligible fraction of his country’s fiendishly complex and

    hopelessly brobdignagian criminal code. Such inevitable

    ignorance breeds criminal behavior – sometimes

    inadvertently – and transforms many upright citizens into

    delinquents.

    In the land of the free – the USA – close to 2 million adults

    are behind bars and another 4.5 million are on probation,

    most of them on drug charges. The costs of

    criminalization – both financial and social – are mind

    boggling. According to “The Economist”, America’s

    prison system cost it $54 billion a year – disregarding the

    price tag of law enforcement, the judiciary, lost product,

    and

    rehabilitation.

    What constitutes a crime? A clear and consistent

    definition has yet to transpire.

    There are five types of criminal behavior: crimes against

    oneself, or “victimless crimes” (such as suicide, abortion,

    and the consumption of drugs), crimes against others

    (such as murder or mugging), crimes among consenting

    adults (such as incest, and in certain countries,

    homosexuality and euthanasia), crimes against collectives

    (such as treason, genocide, or ethnic cleansing), and

    crimes against the international community and world

    order (such as executing prisoners of war). The last two

    categories often overlap.

    The Encyclopedia Britannica provides this definition of a

    crime:

    “The intentional commission of an act usually deemed

    socially harmful or dangerous and specifically defined,

    prohibited, and punishable under the criminal law.”

    But who decides what is socially harmful? What about

    acts committed unintentionally (known as “strict liability

    offenses” in the parlance)? How can we establish intention

    – “mens rea”, or the “guilty mind” – beyond a reasonable

    doubt?

    A much tighter definition would be: “The commission of

    an act punishable under the criminal law.” A crime is

    what the law – state law, kinship law, religious law, or any

    other widely accepted law – says is a crime. Legal systems

    and texts often conflict.

    Murderous blood feuds are legitimate according to the

    15th century “Qanoon”, still applicable in large parts of

    Albania. Killing one’s infant daughters and old relatives is

    socially condoned – though illegal – in India, China,

    Alaska, and parts of Africa. Genocide may have been

    legally sanctioned in Germany and Rwanda – but is

    strictly forbidden under international law.

    Laws being the outcomes of compromises and power

    plays, there is only a tenuous connection between justice

    and morality. Some “crimes” are categorical imperatives.

    Helping the Jews in Nazi Germany was a criminal act –

    yet a highly moral one.

    The ethical nature of some crimes depends on

    circumstances, timing, and cultural context. Murder is a

    vile deed – but assassinating Saddam Hussein may be

    morally commendable. Killing an embryo is a crime in

    some countries – but not so killing a fetus. A “status

    offense” is not a criminal act if committed by an adult.

    Mutilating the body of a live baby is heinous – but this is

    the essence of Jewish circumcision. In some societies,

    criminal guilt is collective. All Americans are held

    blameworthy by the Arab street for the choices and

    actions of their leaders. All Jews are accomplices in the

    “crimes” of the “Zionists”.

    In all societies, crime is a growth industry. Millions of

    professionals – judges, police officers, criminologists,

    psychologists, journalists, publishers, prosecutors,

    lawyers, social workers, probation officers, wardens,

    sociologists, non-governmental-organizations, weapons

    manufacturers, laboratory technicians, graphologists, and

    private detectives – derive their livelihood, parasitically,

    from crime. They often perpetuate models of punishment

    and retribution that lead to recidivism rather than to to the

    reintegration of criminals in society and their

    rehabilitation.

    Organized in vocal interest groups and lobbies, they harp

    on the insecurities and phobias of the alienated urbanites.

    They consume ever growing budgets and rejoice with

    every new behavior criminalized by exasperated

    lawmakers. In the majority of countries, the justice system

    is a dismal failure and law enforcement agencies are part

    of the problem, not its solution.

    The sad truth is that many types of crime are considered

    by people to be normative and common behaviors and,

    thus, go unreported. Victim surveys and self-report studies

    conducted by criminologists reveal that most crimes go

    unreported. The protracted fad of criminalization has

    rendered criminal many perfectly acceptable and recurring

    behaviors and acts. Homosexuality, abortion, gambling,

    prostitution, pornography, and suicide have all been

    criminal offenses at one time or another.

    But the quintessential example of over-criminalization is

    drug abuse.

    There is scant medical evidence that soft drugs such as

    cannabis or MDMA (“Ecstasy”) – and even cocaine – have

    an irreversible effect on brain chemistry or functioning.

    Last month an almighty row erupted in Britain when Jon

    Cole, an addiction researcher at Liverpool University,

    claimed, to quote “The Economist” quoting the

    “Psychologist”, that:

    “Experimental evidence suggesting a link between

    Ecstasy use and problems such as nerve damage and brain

    impairment is flawed … using this ill-substantiated cause-

    and-effect to tell the ‘chemical generation’ that they are

    brain damaged when they are not creates public health

    problems of its own.”

    Moreover, it is commonly accepted that alcohol abuse and

    nicotine abuse can be at least as harmful as the abuse of

    marijuana, for instance. Yet, though somewhat curbed,

    alcohol consumption and cigarette smoking are legal. In

    contrast, users of cocaine – only a century ago

    recommended by doctors as tranquilizer – face life in jail

    in many countries, death in others. Almost everywhere pot

    smokers are confronted with prison terms.

    The “war on drugs” – one of the most expensive and

    protracted in history – has failed abysmally. Drugs are

    more abundant and cheaper than ever. The social costs

    have been staggering: the emergence of violent crime

    where none existed before, the destabilization of drug-

    producing countries, the collusion of drug traffickers with

    terrorists, and the death of millions – law enforcement

    agents, criminals, and users.

    Few doubt that legalizing most drugs would have a

    beneficial effect. Crime empires would crumble

    overnight, users would be assured of the quality of the

    products they consume, and the addicted few would not

    be incarcerated or stigmatized – but rather treated and

    rehabilitated.

    That soft, largely harmless, drugs continue to be illicit is

    the outcome of compounded political and economic

    pressures by lobby and interest groups of manufacturers

    of legal drugs, law enforcement agencies, the judicial

    system, and the aforementioned long list of those who

    benefit from the status quo.

    Only a popular movement can lead to the

    decriminalization of the more innocuous drugs. But such a

    crusade should be part of a larger campaign to reverse the

    overall tide of criminalization. Many “crimes” should

    revert to their erstwhile status as civil torts. Others should

    be wiped off the statute books altogether. Hundreds of

    thousands should be pardoned and allowed to reintegrate

    in society, unencumbered by a past of transgressions

    against an inane and inflationary penal code.

    This, admittedly, will reduce the leverage the state has

    today against its citizens and its ability to intrude on their

    lives, preferences, privacy, and leisure. Bureaucrats and

    politicians may find this abhorrent. Freedom loving

    people should rejoice.

    The Insanity of the Defense

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin
    Also Read

    On Disease

    Althusser, Competing Interpellations and the Third Text

    The Use and Abuse of Differential Diagnoses

    The Myth of Mental Illness

    “You can know the name of a bird in all the languages

    of the world, but when you’re finished, you’ll know

    absolutely nothing whatever about the bird… So let’s

    look at the bird and see what it’s doing – that’s what

    counts. I learned very early the difference between

    knowing the name of something and knowing

    something.”

    Richard Feynman, Physicist and 1965 Nobel Prize

    laureate (1918-1988)

    “You have all I dare say heard of the animal spirits and

    how they are transfused from father to son etcetera

    etcetera – well you may take my word that nine parts in

    ten of a man’s sense or his nonsense, his successes and

    miscarriages in this world depend on their motions and

    activities, and the different tracks and trains you put

    them into, so that when they are once set a-going,

    whether right or wrong, away they go cluttering like hey-

    go-mad.”

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/disease.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/13.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/mentalillness.html

    Lawrence Sterne (1713-1758), “The Life and Opinions of

    Tristram Shandy, Gentleman” (1759)

    I. The Insanity Defense

    II. The Concept of Mental Disease – An Overview

    III. Personality Disorders

    IV. The Biochemistry and Genetics of Mental Health

    V. The Variance of Mental Disease

    VI. Mental Disorders and the Social Order

    VII. Mental Ailment as a Useful Metaphor

    I. The Insanity Defense

    “It is an ill thing to knock against a deaf-mute, an

    imbecile, or a minor. He that wounds them is culpable,

    but if they wound him they are not culpable.” (Mishna,

    Babylonian Talmud)

    If mental illness is culture-dependent and mostly serves as

    an organizing social principle – what should we make of

    the insanity defense (NGRI- Not Guilty by Reason of

    Insanity)?

    A person is held not responsible for his criminal actions if

    s/he cannot tell right from wrong (“lacks substantial

    capacity either to appreciate the criminality

    (wrongfulness) of his conduct” – diminished capacity), did

    not intend to act the way he did (absent “mens rea”)

    and/or could not control his behavior (“irresistible

    impulse”). These handicaps are often associated with

    “mental disease or defect” or “mental retardation”.

    Mental health professionals prefer to talk about an

    impairment of a “person’s perception or understanding of

    reality”. They hold a “guilty but mentally ill” verdict to be

    contradiction in terms. All “mentally-ill” people operate

    within a (usually coherent) worldview, with consistent

    internal logic, and rules of right and wrong (ethics). Yet,

    these rarely conform to the way most people perceive the

    world. The mentally-ill, therefore, cannot be guilty

    because s/he has a tenuous grasp on reality.

    Yet, experience teaches us that a criminal maybe mentally

    ill even as s/he maintains a perfect reality test and thus is

    held criminally responsible (Jeffrey Dahmer comes to

    mind). The “perception and understanding of reality”, in

    other words, can and does co-exist even with the severest

    forms of mental illness.

    This makes it even more difficult to comprehend what is

    meant by “mental disease”. If some mentally ill maintain a

    grasp on reality, know right from wrong, can anticipate

    the outcomes of their actions, are not subject to irresistible

    impulses (the official position of the American Psychiatric

    Association) – in what way do they differ from us,

    “normal” folks?

    http://www.psych.org/public_info/insanity.cfm

    http://www.psych.org/public_info/insanity.cfm

    http://www.psych.org/public_info/insanity.cfm

    This is why the insanity defense often sits ill with mental

    health pathologies deemed socially “acceptable” and

    “normal” – such as religion or love.

    Consider the following case:

    A mother bashes the skulls of her three sons. Two of them

    die. She claims to have acted on instructions she had

    received from God. She is found not guilty by reason of

    insanity. The jury determined that she “did not know right

    from wrong during the killings.”

    But why exactly was she judged insane?

    Her belief in the existence of God – a being with

    inordinate and inhuman attributes – may be irrational.

    But it does not constitute insanity in the strictest sense

    because it conforms to social and cultural creeds and

    codes of conduct in her milieu. Billions of people

    faithfully subscribe to the same ideas, adhere to the same

    transcendental rules, observe the same mystical rituals,

    and claim to go through the same experiences. This shared

    psychosis is so widespread that it can no longer be

    deemed pathological, statistically speaking.

    She claimed that God has spoken to her.

    As do numerous other people. Behavior that is considered

    psychotic (paranoid-schizophrenic) in other contexts is

    lauded and admired in religious circles. Hearing voices

    and seeing visions – auditory and visual delusions – are

    considered rank manifestations of righteousness and

    sanctity.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/lovepathology.html

    http://story.news.yahoo.com/news?tmpl=story&cid=519&ncid=716&e=3&u=/ap/20040404/ap_on_re_us/children_slain

    http://story.news.yahoo.com/news?tmpl=story&cid=519&ncid=716&e=3&u=/ap/20040404/ap_on_re_us/children_slain

    http://story.news.yahoo.com/news?tmpl=story&cid=519&ncid=716&e=3&u=/ap/20040404/ap_on_re_us/children_slain

    Perhaps it was the content of her hallucinations that

    proved her insane?

    She claimed that God had instructed her to kill her boys.

    Surely, God would not ordain such evil?

    Alas, the Old and New Testaments both contain examples

    of God’s appetite for human sacrifice. Abraham was

    ordered by God to sacrifice Isaac, his beloved son (though

    this savage command was rescinded at the last moment).

    Jesus, the son of God himself, was crucified to atone for

    the sins of humanity.

    A divine injunction to slay one’s offspring would sit well

    with the Holy Scriptures and the Apocrypha as well as

    with millennia-old Judeo-Christian traditions of

    martyrdom and sacrifice.

    Her actions were wrong and incommensurate with both

    human and divine (or natural) laws.

    Yes, but they were perfectly in accord with a literal

    interpretation of certain divinely-inspired texts, millennial

    scriptures, apocalyptic thought systems, and

    fundamentalist religious ideologies (such as the ones

    espousing the imminence of “rapture”). Unless one

    declares these doctrines and writings insane, her actions

    are not.

    We are forced to the conclusion that the murderous

    mother is perfectly sane. Her frame of reference is

    different to ours. Hence, her definitions of right and

    wrong are idiosyncratic. To her, killing her babies was the

    right thing to do and in conformity with valued teachings

    and her own epiphany. Her grasp of reality – the

    immediate and later consequences of her actions – was

    never impaired.

    It would seem that sanity and insanity are relative terms,

    dependent on frames of cultural and social reference, and

    statistically defined. There isn’t – and, in principle, can

    never emerge – an “objective”, medical, scientific test to

    determine mental health or disease unequivocally.

    II. The Concept of Mental Disease – An Overview

    Someone is considered mentally “ill” if:

    1. His conduct rigidly and consistently deviates from
    the typical, average behaviour of all other people

    in his culture and society that fit his profile

    (whether this conventional behaviour is moral or

    rational is immaterial), or

    2. His judgment and grasp of objective, physical
    reality is impaired, and

    3. His conduct is not a matter of choice but is innate
    and irresistible, and

    4. His behavior causes him or others discomfort, and
    is

    5. Dysfunctional, self-defeating, and self-destructive
    even by his own yardsticks.

    Descriptive criteria aside, what is the essence of mental

    disorders? Are they merely physiological disorders of the

    brain, or, more precisely of its chemistry? If so, can they

    be cured by restoring the balance of substances and

    secretions in that mysterious organ? And, once

    equilibrium is reinstated – is the illness “gone” or is it still

    lurking there, “under wraps”, waiting to erupt? Are

    psychiatric problems inherited, rooted in faulty genes

    (though amplified by environmental factors) – or brought

    on by abusive or wrong nurturance?

    These questions are the domain of the “medical” school of

    mental health.

    Others cling to the spiritual view of the human psyche.

    They believe that mental ailments amount to the

    metaphysical discomposure of an unknown medium – the

    soul. Theirs is a holistic approach, taking in the patient in

    his or her entirety, as well as his milieu.

    The members of the functional school regard mental

    health disorders as perturbations in the proper, statistically

    “normal”, behaviours and manifestations of “healthy”

    individuals, or as dysfunctions. The “sick” individual – ill

    at ease with himself (ego-dystonic) or making others

    unhappy (deviant) – is “mended” when rendered

    functional again by the prevailing standards of his social

    and cultural frame of reference.

    In a way, the three schools are akin to the trio of blind

    men who render disparate descriptions of the very same

    elephant. Still, they share not only their subject matter –

    but, to a counter intuitively large degree, a faulty

    methodology.

    As the renowned anti-psychiatrist, Thomas Szasz, of the

    State University of New York, notes in his article “The

    Lying Truths of Psychiatry”, mental health scholars,

    regardless of academic predilection, infer the etiology of

    mental disorders from the success or failure of treatment

    modalities.

    This form of “reverse engineering” of scientific models is

    not unknown in other fields of science, nor is it

    unacceptable if the experiments meet the criteria of the

    scientific method. The theory must be all-inclusive

    (anamnetic), consistent, falsifiable, logically compatible,

    monovalent, and parsimonious. Psychological “theories” –

    even the “medical” ones (the role of serotonin and

    dopamine in mood disorders, for instance) – are usually

    none of these things.

    The outcome is a bewildering array of ever-shifting

    mental health “diagnoses” expressly centred around

    Western civilisation and its standards (example: the

    ethical objection to suicide). Neurosis, a historically

    fundamental “condition” vanished after 1980.

    Homosexuality, according to the American Psychiatric

    Association, was a pathology prior to 1973. Seven years

    later, narcissism was declared a “personality disorder”,

    almost seven decades after it was first described by Freud.

    III. Personality Disorders

    Indeed, personality disorders are an excellent example of

    the kaleidoscopic landscape of “objective” psychiatry.

    The classification of Axis II personality disorders –

    deeply ingrained, maladaptive, lifelong behavior patterns

    – in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual, fourth edition,

    text revision [American Psychiatric Association. DSM-

    IV-TR, Washington, 2000] – or the DSM-IV-TR for short

    – has come under sustained and serious criticism from its

    inception in 1952, in the first edition of the DSM.

    The DSM IV-TR adopts a categorical approach,

    postulating that personality disorders are “qualitatively

    distinct clinical syndromes” (p. 689). This is widely

    doubted. Even the distinction made between “normal” and

    “disordered” personalities is increasingly being rejected.

    The “diagnostic thresholds” between normal and

    abnormal are either absent or weakly supported.

    The polythetic form of the DSM’s Diagnostic Criteria –

    only a subset of the criteria is adequate grounds for a

    diagnosis – generates unacceptable diagnostic

    heterogeneity. In other words, people diagnosed with the

    same personality disorder may share only one criterion or

    none.

    The DSM fails to clarify the exact relationship between

    Axis II and Axis I disorders and the way chronic

    childhood and developmental problems interact with

    personality

    disorders.

    The differential diagnoses are vague and the personality

    disorders are insufficiently demarcated. The result is

    excessive co-morbidity (multiple Axis II diagnoses).

    The DSM contains little discussion of what

    distinguishes normal character (personality), personality

    traits, or personality style (Millon) – from personality

    disorders.

    A dearth of documented clinical experience regarding

    both the disorders themselves and the utility of various

    treatment modalities.

    Numerous personality disorders are “not otherwise

    specified” – a catchall, basket “category”.

    Cultural bias is evident in certain disorders (such as the

    Antisocial and the Schizotypal).

    The emergence of dimensional alternatives to the

    categorical approach is acknowledged in the DSM-IV-TR

    itself:

    “An alternative to the categorical approach is the

    dimensional perspective that Personality Disorders

    represent maladaptive variants of personality traits that

    merge imperceptibly into normality and into one

    another” (p.689)

    The following issues – long neglected in the DSM – are

    likely to be tackled in future editions as well as in current

    research. But their omission from official discourse

    hitherto is both startling and telling:

    The longitudinal course of the disorder(s) and their

    temporal stability from early childhood onwards;

    The genetic and biological underpinnings of

    personality disorder(s);

    The development of personality psychopathology

    during childhood and its emergence in

    adolescence;

    The interactions between physical health and

    disease and personality disorders;

    The effectiveness of various treatments – talk

    therapies as well as psychopharmacology.

    IV. The Biochemistry and Genetics of Mental Health

    Certain mental health afflictions are either correlated with

    a statistically abnormal biochemical activity in the brain –

    or are ameliorated with medication. Yet the two facts are

    not ineludibly facets of the same underlying phenomenon.

    In other words, that a given medicine reduces or abolishes

    certain symptoms does not necessarily mean they were

    caused by the processes or substances affected by the

    drug administered. Causation is only one of many possible

    connections and chains of events.

    To designate a pattern of behaviour as a mental health

    disorder is a value judgment, or at best a statistical

    observation. Such designation is effected regardless of the

    facts of brain science. Moreover, correlation is not

    causation. Deviant brain or body biochemistry (once

    called “polluted animal spirits”) do exist – but are they

    truly the roots of mental perversion? Nor is it clear which

    triggers what: do the aberrant neurochemistry or

    biochemistry cause mental illness – or the other way

    around?

    That psychoactive medication alters behaviour and mood

    is indisputable. So do illicit and legal drugs, certain foods,

    and all interpersonal interactions. That the changes

    brought about by prescription are desirable – is debatable

    and involves tautological thinking. If a certain pattern of

    behaviour is described as (socially) “dysfunctional” or

    (psychologically) “sick” – clearly, every change would be

    welcomed as “healing” and every agent of transformation

    would be called a “cure”.

    The same applies to the alleged heredity of mental illness.

    Single genes or gene complexes are frequently

    “associated” with mental health diagnoses, personality

    traits, or behaviour patterns. But too little is known to

    establish irrefutable sequences of causes-and-effects.

    Even less is proven about the interaction of nature and

    nurture, genotype and phenotype, the plasticity of the

    brain and the psychological impact of trauma, abuse,

    upbringing, role models, peers, and other environmental

    elements.

    Nor is the distinction between psychotropic substances

    and talk therapy that clear-cut. Words and the interaction

    with the therapist also affect the brain, its processes and

    chemistry – albeit more slowly and, perhaps, more

    profoundly and irreversibly. Medicines – as David Kaiser

    reminds us in “Against Biologic Psychiatry” (Psychiatric

    Times, Volume XIII, Issue 12, December 1996) – treat

    symptoms, not the underlying processes that yield them.

    V. The Variance of Mental Disease

    If mental illnesses are bodily and empirical, they should

    be invariant both temporally and spatially, across cultures

    and societies. This, to some degree, is, indeed, the case.

    Psychological diseases are not context dependent – but the

    pathologizing of certain behaviours is. Suicide, substance

    abuse, narcissism, eating disorders, antisocial ways,

    schizotypal symptoms, depression, even psychosis are

    considered sick by some cultures – and utterly normative

    or advantageous in others.

    This was to be expected. The human mind and its

    dysfunctions are alike around the world. But values differ

    from time to time and from one place to another. Hence,

    disagreements about the propriety and desirability of

    human actions and inaction are bound to arise in a

    symptom-based diagnostic system.

    As long as the pseudo-medical definitions of mental

    health disorders continue to rely exclusively on signs and

    symptoms – i.e., mostly on observed or reported

    behaviours – they remain vulnerable to such discord and

    devoid of much-sought universality and rigor.

    VI. Mental Disorders and the Social Order

    The mentally sick receive the same treatment as carriers

    of AIDS or SARS or the Ebola virus or smallpox. They

    are sometimes quarantined against their will and coerced

    into involuntary treatment by medication, psychosurgery,

    or electroconvulsive therapy. This is done in the name of

    the greater good, largely as a preventive policy.

    Conspiracy theories notwithstanding, it is impossible to

    ignore the enormous interests vested in psychiatry and

    psychopharmacology. The multibillion dollar industries

    involving drug companies, hospitals, managed healthcare,

    private clinics, academic departments, and law

    enforcement agencies rely, for their continued and

    exponential growth, on the propagation of the concept of

    “mental illness” and its corollaries: treatment and

    research.

    VII. Mental Ailment as a Useful Metaphor

    Abstract concepts form the core of all branches of human

    knowledge. No one has ever seen a quark, or untangled a

    chemical bond, or surfed an electromagnetic wave, or

    visited the unconscious. These are useful metaphors,

    theoretical entities with explanatory or descriptive power.

    “Mental health disorders” are no different. They are

    shorthand for capturing the unsettling quiddity of “the

    Other”. Useful as taxonomies, they are also tools of social

    coercion and conformity, as Michel Foucault and Louis

    Althusser observed. Relegating both the dangerous and

    the idiosyncratic to the collective fringes is a vital

    technique of social engineering.

    The aim is progress through social cohesion and the

    regulation of innovation and creative destruction.

    Psychiatry, therefore, is reifies society’s preference of

    evolution to revolution, or, worse still, to mayhem. As is

    often the case with human endeavour, it is a noble cause,

    unscrupulously and dogmatically pursued.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/althusser.html

    AC/DC – a Deliberation Regarding the Impeachment

    of the President of the United States of America

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    Review the Responses of US Senators

    In the hallways of the Smithsonian, two moralists are

    debating the impeachment of the President of the United

    States of America, Mr. William Jefferson Clinton. One is

    clearly Anti-Clinton (AC) the other, a Democrat (DC), is

    not so much for him as he is for the rational and pragmatic

    application of moral principles.

    AC (expectedly): “The President should be impeached”.

    DC (no less expectedly): “But, surely, even you are not

    trying to imply that he has committed high crimes and

    misdemeanours, as the Constitution demands as grounds

    for the impeachment of a sitting President!”

    AC: “But I do. Perjury is such a high crime because it

    undermines the very fabric of trust between fellow

    citizens and between the citizen and the system of justice,

    the courts.”

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/senator.html

    DC: “A person is innocent until proven guilty. No sound

    proof of perjurious conduct on behalf of the President has

    been provided as yet. Perjurious statements have to be

    deliberate and material. Even if the President deliberately

    lied under oath – his lies were not material to a case,

    which was later dismissed on the grounds of a lack of

    legal merit. Legal hairsplitting and jousting are an

    integral part of the defence in most court cases, civil and

    criminal. It is a legitimate – and legal – component of any

    legal battle, especially one involving interpretations,

    ambiguous terminology and the substantiation of

    intentions. The President should not be denied the

    procedural and substantive rights available to all the

    other citizens of his country. Nor should he be subjected

    to a pre-judgment of his presumed guilt.”

    AC: “This, precisely, is why an impeachment trial by the

    Senate is called for. It is only there that the President can

    credibly and rigorously establish his innocence. All I am

    saying is that IF the President is found by the Senate to

    have committed perjury – he should be impeached.

    Wherever legal hairsplitting and jousting is permissible as

    a legal tactic – it should and will be made available to the

    President. As to the pre-judgment by the Press – I agree

    with you, there is no place for it but, then, in this the

    President has been treated no differently than others. The

    pertinent fact is that perjury is a high misdemeanour, in

    the least, that is, an impeachable offence.”

    DC: “It was clearly not the intention of the Fathers of our

    Constitution to include perjury in the list of impeachable

    offences. Treason is more like it. Moreover, to say that the

    President will receive a fair trial from the hands of his

    peers in the Senate – is to lie. The Senate and its

    committees is a political body, heavily tilted, currently,

    against the President. No justice can be had where politics

    rears its ugly head. Bias and prejudice will rule this mock

    trial.”

    AC: “Man is a political animal, said the Greek

    philosophers of antiquity. Where can you find an

    assembly of people free of politics? What is this discourse

    that we are having if not a political one? Is not the

    Supreme Court of the land a politically appointed entity?

    The Senate is no better and no worse, it is but a mirror, a

    reflection of the combined will of the people. Moreover,

    in pursuing the procedures of impeachment – the Senate

    will have proved its non-political mettle in this case. The

    nation, in all opinion polls, wants this matter dropped. If it

    is not – it is a proof of foresight and civil courage, of

    leadership and refusal to succumb to passing fads.”

    DC: “And what about my first argument – that perjury,

    even once proven, was not considered by the authors of

    the Constitution to have been an impeachable offence?”

    AC: “The rules of the land – even the Constitution – are

    nothing but an agreement between those who subscribe to

    it and for as long as they do. It is a social contract, a pact.

    Men – even the authors of the Constitution – being mortal,

    relegated the right to amend it and to interpret it to future

    generations. The Constitution is a vessel, each generation

    fills it as it sees fit. It is up to us to say what current

    meaning this document harbours. We are not to be

    constrained by the original intentions of the authors.

    These intentions are meaningless as circumstances

    change. It is what we read into the Constitution that forms

    its specific contents. With changing mores and values and

    with the passage of events – each generation generates its

    own version of this otherwise immortal set of principles.”

    DC: “I find it hard to accept that there is no limit to this

    creative deconstruction. Surely it is limited by common

    sense, confined to logic, subordinate to universal human

    principles. One can stretch the meanings of words only

    thus far. It takes a lot of legal hairsplitting to bring perjury

    – not proven yet – under one roof with

    treason.”

    AC: “Let us ignore the legal issues and leave them to their

    professionals. Let us talk about what really bothers us all,

    including you, I hope and trust. This President has lied.

    He may have lied under oath, but he definitely lied on

    television and in the spacious rooms of the White House.

    He lied to his family, to his aides, to the nation, to

    Congress…”

    DC: “For what purpose do you enumerate them?”

    AC: “Because it is one thing to lie to your family and

    another thing to lie to Congress. A lie told to the nation, is

    of a different magnitude altogether. To lie to your closest

    aides and soi dissant confidantes – again is a separate

    matter…”

    DC: “So you agree that there are lies and there are lies?

    That lying is not a monolithic offence? That some lies

    are worse than others, some are permissible, some even

    ethically mandatory?”

    AC: “No, I do not. To lie is to do a morally objectionable

    thing, no matter what the circumstances. It is better to shut

    up. Why didn’t the President invoke the Fifth

    Amendment, the right not to incriminate himself by his

    own lips?”

    DC: “Because as much information is contained in

    abstaining to do something as in doing it and because if he

    did so, he would have provoked riotous rumours.

    Rumours are always worse than the truth. Rumours are

    always worse than the most defiled lie. It is better to lie

    than to provoke rumours.”

    AC: “Unless your lies are so clearly lies that you provoke

    rumours regarding what is true, thus inflicting a double

    blow upon the public peace that you were mandated to

    and undertook to preserve…”

    DC: “Again, you make distinctions between types of lies

    – this time, by their efficacy. I am not sure this is

    progress. Let me give you examples of the three cases:

    where one would do morally well to tell the truth, where

    one would achieve morally commendable outcomes only

    by lying and the case where lying is as morally

    permissible as telling the truth. Imagine a young sick

    adult. Her life is at peril but can be saved if she were to

    agree to consume a certain medicine. This medicament,

    however, will render her sterile. Surely, she must be told

    the truth. It should be entirely her decision how to

    continue his life: in person or through her progeny. Now,

    imagine that this young woman, having suffered greatly

    already, informed her doctor that should she learn that her

    condition is terminal and that she needs to consume

    medicines with grave side effects in order to prolong it or

    even to save it altogether – she is determined to take her

    life and has already procured the means to do so. Surely, it

    is mandatory to lie to this young woman in order to save

    her life. Imagine now the third situation: that she also

    made a statement that having a child is her only,

    predominant, all pervasive, wish in life. Faced with two

    conflicting statements, some may choose to reveal the

    truth to her – others, to withhold it, and with the same

    amount of moral justification.”

    AC: “And what are we to learn from this?”

    DC: “That the moral life is a chain of dilemmas, almost

    none of which is solvable. The President may have lied in

    order to preserve his family, to protect his only child, to

    shield his aides from embarrassing legal scrutiny, even to

    protect his nation from what he perceived to have been the

    destructive zeal of the special prosecutor. Some of his lies

    should be considered at least common, if not morally

    permissible.”

    AC: “This is a slippery slope. There is no end to this

    moral relativism. It is a tautology. You say that in some

    cases there are morally permissible reasons to lie. When I

    ask you how come – you say to me that people lie only

    when they have good reasons to lie. But this the crux of

    your mistake: good reasons are not always sufficient,

    morally permissible, or even necessary reasons. Put more

    plainly: no one lies without a reason. Does the fact that a

    liar has a reason to lie – absolve him?”

    DC: “Depends what is the reason. This is what I tried to

    establish in my little sad example above. To lie about a

    sexual liaison – even under oath – may be morally

    permissible if the intention is to shield other meaningful

    individuals from harm, or in order to buttress the

    conditions, which will allow one to fulfil one’s side of a

    contract. The President has a contract with the American

    people, sealed in two elections. He has to perform. It is his

    duty no less than he has a duty to tell the truth. Conflict

    arises only when two equally powerful principles clash.

    The very fact that there is a controversy in the public

    demonstrates the moral ambiguity of this situation.

    The dysfunction of the American presidency has already

    cost trillions of dollars in a collapsing global economy.

    Who knows how many people died and will die in the

    pursuit of the high principle of vincit omnia veritas (the

    truth always prevails)? If I could prove to you that one

    person – just one person – committed suicide as a result of

    the financial turmoil engendered by the Clinton affair,

    would you still stick to your lofty ideals?”

    AC: “You inadvertently, I am sure, broached the heart of

    this matter. The President is in breach of his contracts.

    Not one contract – but many. As all of us do – he has a

    contract with other fellow beings, he is a signatory to a

    Social Treaty. One of the articles of this treaty calls to

    respect the Law by not lying under oath. Another calls for

    striving to maintain a generally truthful conduct towards

    the other signatories. The President has a contract with

    his wife, which he clearly violated, by committing

    adultery. Professing to be a believing man, he is also in

    breach of his contract with his God as set forth in the

    Holy Scriptures. But the President has another, very

    powerful and highly specific contract with the American

    people. It is this contract that has been violated savagely

    and expressly by the President.”

    DC: “The American people does not seem to think so, but,

    prey, continue…”

    AC: “Before I do, allow me just to repeat. To me, there is

    no moral difference between one lie and another. All lies

    are loathsome and lead, in the long run, to hell whatever

    the good intentions, which paved the way there. As far as

    I am concerned, President Clinton is a condemned man on

    these grounds only. But the lies one chooses and the

    victims he chooses to expose to his misbehaviour – reflect

    his personality, his inner world, what type of human

    being he is. It is the only allowance I make. All lies are

    prohibited as all murders are. But there are murders most

    foul and there are lies most abominable and obnoxious.

    What are we to learn about the President from his choice

    of arms and adversaries? That he is a paranoid, a

    narcissist, lacks empathy, immature, unable to postpone

    his satisfactions, to plan ahead, to foresee the outcomes of

    his actions. He has a sense of special, unwarranted

    entitlement, he judges his environment and the world, at

    large, erroneously. In short: he is dangerously wrong for

    the job that he has acquired through deception.”

    DC: “Through elections…”

    AC: “Nay, through deception brought about by elections.

    He lied to the American people about who he is and what

    he stands for. He did not frankly expose or discuss his

    weaknesses and limitations. He sold his voters on an

    invented, imaginary image, the product of spin-doctors

    and opinion polls, which had no common denominator

    with reality. This is gross deception.”

    DC: “But now that the American people know everything

    – they still prefer him over others, approve of his

    performance and applaud his professional

    achievements…”

    AC: “This is the power of incumbency. It was the same

    with Nixon until one month before his resignation. Or, do

    you sanction his actions as well?”

    DC: “Frankly, I will compare President Clinton to

    President Andrew Johnson rather than to President

    Nixon. The shattering discovery about Nixon was that he

    was an uncommon criminal. The shattering discovery

    about Clinton is that he is human. Congress chastises him

    not for having done what he did – in this he has many

    illustrious precedents. No, he is accused of being

    indiscreet, of failing to hide the truth, to evade the facts.

    He is reproached for his lack of efficiency at

    concealment. He is criticized, therefore, both for being

    evasive and for not being sufficiently protective of his

    secrets. It is hard to win such a case, I tell you. It is also

    hypocritical in the extreme.”

    AC: “Do you agree that the President of the United States

    is party to a contract with the American People?”

    DC: “Absolutely.”

    AC: “Would you say that he is enjoined by this contract to

    uphold the dignity of his office?’

    DC:”I think that most people would agree to this.”

    AC: “And do you agree with me that fornicating in the

    White House would tend to diminish rather than uphold

    this dignity – and, therefore, constitute a violation of this

    contract? That it shows utter disregard and disrespect to

    the institutions of this country and to their standing?”

    DC: “I assume that you mean to say fornication in

    general, not only in the White House. To answer you, I

    must analyse this complex issue into its components.

    First, I assume that you agree with me that sex between

    consenting adults is almost always legally allowed and,

    depending on the circumstances and the culture, it is,

    usually, morally acceptable. The President’s relationship

    with Miss Lewinsky did not involve sexual harassment or

    coercion and, therefore, was sex between consenting

    adults. Legally, there could be nothing against it. The

    problem, therefore, is cast in moral terms. Would you care

    to define it?”

    AC: “The President has engaged in sexual acts – some

    highly unusual -with a woman much younger than he,

    in a building belonging to the American public and put

    at his disposal solely for the performance of his duties.

    Moreover, his acts constituted adultery, which is a

    morally reprehensible act. He acted secretly and tried to

    conceal the facts using expressly illegal and immoral

    means – namely by lying.”

    DC: “I took the pains of noting down everything you said.

    You said that the President has engaged in sexual acts and

    there can be no dispute between us that this does not

    constitute a problem. You said that some of them were

    highly unusual. This is a value judgement, so dependent

    on period and culture, that it is rendered meaningless by

    its derivative nature. What to one is repulsive is to the

    other a delightful stimulus. Of course, this applies only to

    consenting adults and when life itself is not jeopardized.

    Then you mentioned the age disparity between the

    President and his liaison. This is sheer bigotry. I am

    inclined to think that this statement is motivated more by

    envy than by moral judgement…”

    AC: “I beg to differ! His advantages in both position and

    age do raise the spectre of exploitation, even of abuse! He

    took advantage of her, capitalized on her lack of

    experience and innocence, used her as a sex slave, an

    object, there just to fulfil his desires and realize his

    fantasies.”

    DC: “Then there is no meaning to the word consent, nor

    to the legal age of consent. The line must be drawn

    somewhere. The President did not make explicit promises

    and then did not own up to them. Expectations and

    anticipation can develop in total vacuum, in a manner

    unsubstantiated, not supported by any observable

    behaviour. It is an open question who was using who in

    this lurid tale – at least, who was hoping to use who. The

    President, naturally, had much more to offer to Miss

    Lewinsky than she could conceivably have offered to him.

    Qui bono is a useful guide in reality as well as in mystery

    books.”

    AC: “This is again the same Presidential pattern of deceit,

    half truths and plain lies. The President may not have

    promised anything explicitly – but he sure did implicitly,

    otherwise why would Miss Lewinsky have availed herself

    sexually? Even if we adopt your more benevolent version

    of events and assume that Miss Lewinsky approached this

    avowed and professional womanizer with the intention of

    taking advantage of him – clearly, a deal must have been

    struck. ”

    DC: “Yes, but we don’t know its nature and its

    parameters. It is therefore useless to talk about this empty,

    hypothetical entity. You also said that he committed these

    acts of lust in a building belonging to the American public

    and put at his disposal solely for the performance of his

    duties. This is half-true, of course. This is also the home

    of the President, his castle. He has to endure a lot in order

    to occupy this mansion and the separation between private

    and public life is only on paper. Presidents have no private

    lives but only public ones. Why should we reproach them

    for mixing the public with the private? This is a double

    standard: when it suits our predatory instincts, our

    hypocrisy and our search for a scapegoat – we disallow

    the private life of a President. When these same low

    drives can be satisfied by making this distinction – we

    trumpet it. We must make up our minds: either Presidents

    are not allowed to have private lives and then they should

    be perfectly allowed to engage in all manner of normally

    private behaviour in public and on public property (and

    even at the public’s expense). Or the distinction is relevant

    – in which case we should adopt the “European model”

    and not pry into the lives of our Presidents, not expose

    them, and not demand their public flagellation for very

    private sins.”

    AC: “This is a gross misrepresentation of the process that

    led to the current sorry state of affairs. The President got

    himself embroiled in numerous other legal difficulties

    long before the Monika Lewinsky story erupted. The

    special prosecutor was appointed to investigate

    Whitewater and other matters long before the President’s

    sexual shenanigans hit the courts. The President lied under

    oath in connection with a private, civil lawsuit brought

    against him by Paula Jones. It is all the President’s doing.

    Decapitating the messenger – the special prosecutor – is

    an old and defunct Roman habit.”

    DC: “Then you proceeded to accuse the President of

    adultery. Technically, there can be no disagreement. The

    President’s actions – however sexual acts are defined –

    constitute unequivocal adultery. But the legal and

    operational definitions of adultery are divorced from the

    emotional and moral discourse of the same phenomenon.

    We must not forget that you stated that the adulterous acts

    committed by the President have adversely affected the

    dignity of his office and this is what seems to have

    bothered you…”

    AC: “Absolutely misrepresented. I do have a problem

    with adultery in general and I wholeheartedly disagree

    with it…”

    DC: “I apologize. So, let us accord these two rather

    different questions – the separate treatment that they

    deserve. First, surely you agree with me that there can be

    no dignity where there is no truth, for you said so

    yourself. A marital relationship that fails abysmally to

    provide the parties with sexual or emotional gratification

    and is maintained in the teeth of such failure – is a lie. It is

    a lie because it gives observers false information

    regarding the state of things. What is better – to continue a

    marriage of appearances and mutual hell – or to find

    emotional and sexual fulfilment elsewhere? When the

    pursuit of happiness is coupled with the refusal to pretend,

    to pose, in other words, to lie, isn’t this commendable?

    President Clinton admitted to marital problems and there

    seems to be an incompatibility, which reaches to the roots

    of this bond between himself and his wife.

    Sometimes marriages start as one thing – passion, perhaps

    or self delusion – and end up as another: mutual

    acceptance, a warm habit, companionship. Many

    marriages withstand marital infidelity precisely because

    they are not conventional, or ideal marriages. By forgoing

    sex, a partnership is sometimes strengthened and a true,

    disinterested friendship is formed. I say that by insisting

    on being true to himself, by refusing to accept social

    norms of hypocrisy, conventions of make-belief and

    camouflage, by exposing the lacunas in his marriage, by,

    thus, redefining it and by pursuing his own sexual and

    emotional happiness – the President has acted honestly.

    He did not compromise the dignity of his office.”

    AC: “Dysfunctional partnerships should be dissolved.

    The President should have divorced prior to indulging his

    sexual appetite. Sexual exclusivity is an integral –

    possibly the most important – section of the marriage

    contract. The President ignored his vows, dishonoured his

    word, breached his contract with the First Lady.”

    DC: “People stay together only if they feel that the

    foundation upon which they based their relationship is

    still sound. Mr. Clinton and Mrs. Clinton redefined their

    marriage to exclude sexual exclusivity, an impossibility

    under the circumstances. But they did not exclude

    companionship and friendship. It is here that the President

    may have sinned, in lying to his best friend, his wife.

    Adultery is committed only when a party strays out of the

    confines of the marital contract. I postulate that the

    President was well within his agreement with Mrs.

    Clinton when he sought sexual gratification elsewhere.”

    AC: “Adultery is a sin not only against the partner. The

    marriage contract is signed by three parties: the man, the

    woman and God between them. The President sinned

    against God. This cannot be ameliorated by any human

    approval or permission. Whether his wife accepted him as

    he is and disregarded his actions – is irrelevant. And if

    you are agnostic or an atheist, still you can replace the

    word ‗God’ by the words „Social Order’. President

    Clinton’s behaviour undermines the foundations of our

    social order. The family is the basic functional unit and its

    proper functioning is guaranteed by the security of sexual

    and emotional exclusivity. To be adulterous is to rebel

    against civilization. It is an act of high social and moral

    treason.”

    DC: “While I may share your nostalgia – I am compelled

    to inform you that even nostalgia is not what it used to be.

    There is no such thing as ‗The Family’. There are a few

    competing models, some of them involving only a single

    person and his or her offspring. There is nothing to

    undermine. The social order is in such a flux that it is

    impossible to follow, let alone define or capture. Adultery

    is common. This could be a sign of the times – or the

    victory of honesty and openness over pretension and

    hypocrisy. No one can cast a stone at President Clinton in

    this day and age.”

    AC: “But that’s precisely it! The President is not a mirror,

    a reflection of the popular will. Our President is a leader

    with awesome powers. These powers were given to him to

    enable him to set example, to bear a standard – to be a

    standard. I do demand of my President to be morally

    superior to me – and this is no hypocrisy. This is a job

    description. To lead, a leader needs to inspire shame and

    guilt through his model. People must look up to him, wish

    they were like him, hope, dream, aspire and conspire to be

    like him. A true leader provokes inner tumult,

    psychological conflicts, strong emotions – because he

    demands the impossible through the instance of his

    personality. A true leader moves people to sacrifice

    because he is worthy of their sacrifice, because he

    deserves it. He definitely does not set an example of moral

    disintegration, recklessness, short-sightedness and

    immaturity. The President is given unique power, status

    and privileges – only because he has been recognized as a

    unique and powerful and privileged individual. Whether

    such recognition has been warranted or not is what

    determines the quality of the presidency.”

    DC: “Not being a leader, or having been misjudged by the

    voters to be one – do not constitute impeachable offences.

    I reject your view of the presidency. It is too fascist for

    me, it echoes with the despicable Fuhrerprinzip. A leader

    is no different from the people that elected him. A leader

    has strong convictions shared by the majority of his

    compatriots. A leader also has the energy to implement

    the solutions that he proposes and the willingness to

    sacrifice certain aspects of his life (like his privacy) to do

    so. If a leader is a symbol of his people – then he must, in

    many ways, be like them.

    He cannot be as alien as you make him out to be. But

    then, if he is alien by virtue of being superior or by virtue

    of being possessed of superhuman qualities – how can we,

    mere mortals, judge him? This is the logical fallacy in

    your argument: if the President is a symbol, then he must

    be very much similar to us and we should not subject him

    to a judgement more severe than the one meted to

    ourselves. If the President is omnipotent, omniscient,

    omnipresent, or otherwise, superhuman – then he is above

    our ability to judge. And if the President is a standard

    against whom we should calibrate our lives and actions –

    then he must reflect the mores of his times, the

    kaleidoscopic nature of the society that bred him, the flux

    of norms, conventions, paradigms and doctrines which

    formed the society which chose him. A standard too

    remote, too alien, too detached – will not do. People will

    ignore it and revert to other behavioural benchmarks and

    normative yardsticks. The President should, therefore, be

    allowed to be “normal”, he should be forgiven. After all

    forgiveness is as prominent a value as being truthful.

    AC: “This allowance, alas, cannot be made. Even if I

    were to accept your thesis about ‗The President as a

    regular Human Being’ – still his circumstances are not

    regular. The decisions that he faces – and very frequently

    – affect the lives of billions. The conflicting pressures that

    he is under, the gigantic amounts of information that he

    must digest, the enormity of the tasks facing him and the

    strains and stresses that are surely the results of these – all

    call for a special human alloy. If cracks are found in this

    alloy in room temperature – it raises doubts regarding its

    ability to withstand harsher conditions. If the President

    lies concerning a personal matter, no matter how

    significant – who will guarantee veracity rather than

    prevarication in matters more significant to us?

    If he is afraid of a court of law – how is he likely to

    command our armies in a time of war? If he is evasive in

    his answers to the Grand Jury – how can we rely on his

    resolve and determination when confronting world leaders

    and when faced with extreme situations? If he loses his

    temper over petty matters – who will guarantee his

    coolheadedness when it is really required? If criminal in

    small, household matters – why not in the international

    arena?”

    DC: “Because this continuum is false. There is little

    correlation between reactive patterns in the personal

    realms – and their far relatives in the public domain.

    Implication by generalization is a logical fallacy. The

    most adulterous, querulous, and otherwise despicable

    people have been superb, far sighted statesmen. The most

    generous, benevolent, easygoing ones have become

    veritable political catastrophes. The public realm is not

    the personal realm writ large. It is true that the leader’s

    personality interacts with his circumstances to yield policy

    choices. But the relevance of his sexual predilections in

    this context is dubious indeed. It is true that his morals

    and general conformity to a certain value system will

    influence his actions and inactions – influence, but not

    determine them. It is true that his beliefs, experience,

    personality, character and temperament will colour the

    way he does things – but rarely what he does and rarely

    more than colour. Paradoxically, in times of crisis, there is

    a tendency to overlook the moral vices of a leader (or, for

    that matter, his moral virtues). If a proof was needed that

    moral and personal conduct are less relevant to proper

    leadership – this is it. When it really matters, we ignore

    these luxuries of righteousness and get on with the

    business of selecting a leader.

    Not a symbol, not a standard bearer, not a superman.

    Simply a human being – with all the flaws and

    weaknesses of one – who can chart the water and navigate

    to safety flying in the face of adverse circumstances.”

    AC: “Like everything else in life, electing a leader is a

    process of compromise, a negotiation between the ideal

    and the real. I just happen to believe that a good leader is

    the one who is closer to the ideal. You believe that one

    has to be realistic, not to dream, not to expect. To me, this

    is mental death. My criticism is a cry of the pain of

    disillusionment. But if I have to choose between deluding

    myself again and standing firmly on a corrupt and

    degenerate ground – I prefer, and always will, the levity of

    dreams.”

    The Rights of Animals

    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    ―Animal rights‖ is a catchphrase akin to ―human rights‖.

    It involves, however, a few pitfalls. First, animals exist

    only as a concept. Otherwise, they are cuddly cats, curly

    dogs, cute monkeys. A rat and a puppy are both animals

    but our emotional reaction to them is so different that we

    cannot really lump them together. Moreover: what rights

    are we talking about? The right to life? The right to be

    free of pain? The right to food? Except the right to free

    speech – all other rights could be applied to animals.

    Law professor Steven Wise, argues in his book, “Drawing

    the Line: Science and the Case for Animal Rights”, for the

    extension to animals of legal rights accorded to infants.

    Many animal species exhibit awareness, cognizance and

    communication skills typical of human toddlers and of

    humans with arrested development. Yet, the latter enjoy

    rights denied the former.

    According to Wise, there are four categories of practical

    autonomy – a legal standard for granting “personhood”

    and the rights it entails. Practical autonomy involves the

    ability to be desirous, to intend to fulfill and pursue one’s

    desires, a sense of self-awareness, and self-sufficiency.

    Most animals, says Wise, qualify. This may be going too

    far. It is easier to justify the moral rights of animals than

    their legal rights.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    But when we say “animals”, what we really mean is non-

    human organisms. This is such a wide definition that it

    easily pertains to extraterrestrial aliens. Will we witness

    an Alien Rights movement soon? Unlikely. Thus, we are

    forced to narrow our field of enquiry to non-human

    organisms reminiscent of humans, the ones that provoke

    in us empathy.

    Even this is way too fuzzy. Many people love snakes, for

    instance, and deeply empathize with them. Could we

    accept the assertion (avidly propounded by these people)

    that snakes ought to have rights – or should we consider

    only organisms with extremities and the ability to feel

    pain?

    Historically, philosophers like Kant (and Descartes,

    Malebranche, and Aquinas) rejected the idea of animal

    rights. They regarded animals as the organic equivalents

    of machines, driven by coarse instincts, unable to

    experience pain (though their behavior sometimes

    deceives us into erroneously believing that they do).

    Thus, any ethical obligation that we have towards animals

    is a derivative of our primary obligation towards our

    fellow humans (the only ones possessed of moral

    significance). These are called the theories of indirect

    moral obligations. Thus, it is wrong to torture animals

    only because it desensitizes us to human suffering and

    makes us more prone to using violence on humans.

    Malebranche augmented this line of thinking by “proving”

    that animals cannot suffer pain because they are not

    descended from Adam. Pain and suffering, as we all

    know, are the exclusive outcomes of Adam’s sins.

    Kant and Malebranche may have been wrong. Animals

    may be able to suffer and agonize. But how can we tell

    whether another Being is truly suffering pain or not?

    Through empathy. We postulate that – since that Being

    resembles us – it must have the same experiences and,

    therefore, it deserves our pity.

    Yet, the principle of resemblance has many drawbacks.

    One, it leads to moral relativism.

    Consider this maxim from the Jewish Talmud: “Do not do

    unto thy friend that which you hate”. An analysis of this

    sentence renders it less altruistic than it appears. We are

    encouraged to refrain from doing only those things that

    WE find hateful. This is the quiddity of moral relativism.

    The saying implies that it is the individual who is the

    source of moral authority. Each and every one of us is

    allowed to spin his own moral system, independent of

    others. The Talmudic dictum establishes a privileged

    moral club (very similar to later day social

    contractarianism) comprised of oneself and one’s

    friend(s). One is encouraged not to visit evil upon one’s

    friends, all others seemingly excluded. Even the broadest

    interpretation of the word “friend” could only read:

    “someone like you” and substantially excludes strangers.

    Two, similarity is a structural, not an essential, trait.

    Empathy as a differentiating principle is structural: if X

    looks like me and behaves like me – then he is privileged.

    Moreover, similarity is not necessarily identity. Monkeys,

    dogs and dolphins are very much like us, both structurally

    and behaviorally. Even according to Wise, it is quantity

    (the degree of observed resemblance), not quality

    (identity, essence), that is used in determining whether an

    animal is worthy of holding rights, whether is it a morally

    significant person. The degree of figurative and functional

    likenesses decide whether one deserves to live, pain-free

    and happy.

    The quantitative test includes the ability to communicate

    (manipulate vocal-verbal-written symbols within

    structured symbol systems). Yet, we ignore the fact that

    using the same symbols does not guarantee that we attach

    to them the same cognitive interpretations and the same

    emotional resonance (‘private languages”). The same

    words, or symbols, often have different meanings.

    Meaning is dependent upon historical, cultural, and

    personal contexts. There is no telling whether two people

    mean the same things when they say “red”, or “sad”, or

    “I”, or “love”. That another organism looks like us,

    behaves like us and communicates like us is no guarantee

    that it is – in its essence – like us. This is the subject of the

    famous Turing Test: there is no effective way to

    distinguish a machine from a human when we rely

    exclusively on symbol manipulation.

    Consider pain once more.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/turing.html

    To say that something does not experience pain cannot be

    rigorously defended. Pain is a subjective experience.

    There is no way to prove or to disprove that someone is or

    is not in pain. Here, we can rely only on the subject’s

    reports. Moreover, even if we were to have an

    analgometer (pain gauge), there would have been no way

    to show that the phenomenon that activates the meter is

    one and the same for all subjects, SUBJECTIVELY, i.e.,

    that it is experienced in the same way by all the subjects

    examined.

    Even more basic questions regarding pain are impossible

    to answer: What is the connection between the piercing

    needle and the pain REPORTED and between these two

    and electrochemical patterns of activity in the brain? A

    correlation between these three phenomena can be

    established – but not their identity or the existence of a

    causative process. We cannot prove that the waves in the

    subject’s brain when he reports pain – ARE that pain. Nor

    can we show that they CAUSED the pain, or that the pain

    caused them.

    It is also not clear whether our moral percepts are

    conditioned on the objective existence of pain, on the

    reported existence of pain, on the purported existence of

    pain (whether experienced or not, whether reported or

    not), or on some independent laws.

    If it were painless, would it be moral to torture someone?

    Is the very act of sticking needles into someone immoral –

    or is it immoral because of the pain it causes, or supposed

    to inflict? Are all three components (needle sticking, a

    sensation of pain, brain activity) morally equivalent? If so,

    is it as immoral to merely generate the same patterns of

    brain activity, without inducing any sensation of pain and

    without sticking needles in the subject?

    If these three phenomena are not morally equivalent –

    why aren’t they? They are, after all, different facets of the

    very same pain – shouldn’t we condemn all of them

    equally? Or should one aspect of pain (the subject’s report

    of pain) be accorded a privileged treatment and status?

    Yet, the subject’s report is the weakest proof of pain! It

    cannot be verified. And if we cling to this descriptive-

    behavioral-phenomenological definition of pain than

    animals qualify as well. They also exhibit all the

    behaviors normally ascribed to humans in pain and they

    report feeling pain (though they do tend to use a more

    limited and non-verbal vocabulary).

    Pain is, therefore, a value judgment and the reaction to it

    is culturally dependent. In some cases, pain is perceived

    as positive and is sought. In the Aztec cultures, being

    chosen to be sacrificed to the Gods was a high honor.

    How would we judge animal rights in such historical and

    cultural contexts? Are there any “universal” values or does

    it all really depend on interpretation?

    If we, humans, cannot separate the objective from the

    subjective and the cultural – what gives us the right or

    ability to decide for other organisms? We have no way of

    knowing whether pigs suffer pain.

    We cannot decide right and wrong, good and evil for

    those with whom we can communicate, let alone for

    organisms with which we fail to do even this.

    Is it GENERALLY immoral to kill, to torture, to pain?

    The answer seems obvious and it automatically applies to

    animals. Is it generally immoral to destroy? Yes, it is and

    this answer applies to the inanimate as well. There are

    exceptions: it is permissible to kill and to inflict pain in

    order to prevent a (quantitatively or qualitatively) greater

    evil, to protect life, and when no reasonable and feasible

    alternative is available.

    The chain of food in nature is morally neutral and so are

    death and disease. Any act which is intended to sustain

    life of a higher order (and a higher order in life) – is

    morally positive or, at least neutral. Nature decreed so.

    Animals do it to other animals – though, admittedly, they

    optimize their consumption and avoid waste and

    unnecessary pain. Waste and pain are morally wrong. This

    is not a question of hierarchy of more or less important

    Beings (an outcome of the fallacy of

    anthropomorphesizing Nature).

    The distinction between what is (essentially) US – and

    what just looks and behaves like us (but is NOT us) is

    false, superfluous and superficial. Sociobiology is already

    blurring these lines. Quantum Mechanics has taught us

    that we can say nothing about what the world really IS. If

    things look the same and behave the same, we better

    assume that they are the same.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html

    The attempt to claim that moral responsibility is reserved

    to the human species is self defeating. If it is so, then we

    definitely have a moral obligation towards the weaker and

    meeker. If it isn’t, what right do we have to decide who

    shall live and who shall die (in pain)?

    The increasingly shaky “fact” that species do not

    interbreed “proves” that species are distinct, say some.

    But who can deny that we share most of our genetic

    material with the fly and the mouse? We are not as

    dissimilar as we wish we were. And ever-escalating

    cruelty towards other species will not establish our genetic

    supremacy – merely our moral inferiority.

    Just War or a Just War?
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    In an age of terrorism, guerilla and total warfare the

    medieval doctrine of Just War needs to be re-defined.

    Moreover, issues of legitimacy, efficacy and morality

    should not be confused. Legitimacy is conferred by

    institutions. Not all morally justified wars are, therefore,

    automatically legitimate. Frequently the efficient

    execution of a battle plan involves immoral or even illegal

    acts.

    As international law evolves beyond the ancient percepts

    of sovereignty, it should incorporate new thinking about

    pre-emptive strikes, human rights violations as casus belli

    and the role and standing of international organizations,

    insurgents and liberation movements.

    Yet, inevitably, what constitutes “justice” depends heavily

    on the cultural and societal contexts, narratives, mores,

    and values of the disputants. Thus, one cannot answer the

    deceivingly simple question: “Is this war a just war?” –

    without first asking: “According to whom? In which

    context? By which criteria? Based on what values? In

    which period in history and where?”

    Being members of Western Civilization, whether by

    choice or by default, our understanding of what

    constitutes a just war is crucially founded on our shifting

    perceptions of the West.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    Imagine a village of 220 inhabitants. It has one heavily

    armed police constable flanked by two lightly equipped

    assistants. The hamlet is beset by a bunch of ruffians who

    molest their own families and, at times, violently lash out

    at their neighbors. These delinquents mock the authorities

    and ignore their decisions and decrees.

    Yet, the village council – the source of legitimacy – refuses

    to authorize the constable to apprehend the villains and

    dispose of them, by force of arms if need be. The elders

    see no imminent or present danger to their charges and are

    afraid of potential escalation whose evil outcomes could

    far outweigh anything the felons can achieve.

    Incensed by this laxity, the constable – backed only by

    some of the inhabitants – breaks into the home of one of

    the more egregious thugs and expels or kills him. He

    claims to have acted preemptively and in self-defense, as

    the criminal, long in defiance of the law, was planning to

    attack its representatives.

    Was the constable right in acting the way he did?

    On the one hand, he may have saved lives and prevented a

    conflagration whose consequences no one could predict.

    On the other hand, by ignoring the edicts of the village

    council and the expressed will of many of the denizens, he

    has placed himself above the law, as its absolute

    interpreter and enforcer.

    What is the greater danger? Turning a blind eye to the

    exploits of outlaws and outcasts, thus rendering them ever

    more daring and insolent – or acting unilaterally to counter

    such pariahs, thus undermining the communal legal

    foundation and, possibly, leading to a chaotic situation of

    “might is right”? In other words, when ethics and

    expedience conflict with legality – which should

    prevail?

    Enter the medieval doctrine of “Just War” (justum bellum,

    or, more precisely jus ad bellum), propounded by Saint

    Augustine of Hippo (fifth century AD), Saint Thomas

    Aquinas (1225-1274) in his “Summa Theologicae”,

    Francisco de Vitoria (1548-1617), Francisco Suarez

    (1548-1617), Hugo Grotius (1583-1645) in his influential

    tome “Jure Belli ac Pacis” (“On Rights of War and

    Peace”, 1625), Samuel Pufendorf (1632-1704), Christian

    Wolff (1679-1754), and Emerich de Vattel (1714-1767).

    Modern thinkers include Michael Walzer in “Just and

    Unjust Wars” (1977), Barrie Paskins and Michael Dockrill

    in “The Ethics of War” (1979), Richard Norman in

    “Ethics, Killing, and War” (1995), Thomas Nagel in “War

    and Massacre”, and Elizabeth Anscombe in “War and

    Murder”.

    According to the Catholic Church’s rendition of this

    theory, set forth by Bishop Wilton D. Gregory of the

    United States Conference of Catholic Bishops in his

    Letter to President Bush on Iraq, dated September 13,

    2002, going to war is justified if these conditions are met:

    “The damage inflicted by the aggressor on the nation or

    community of nations [is] lasting, grave, and certain; all

    other means of putting an end to it must have been

    shown to be impractical or ineffective; there must be

    serious prospects of success; the use of arms must not

    produce evils and disorders graver than the evil to be

    eliminated.”

    A just war is, therefore, a last resort, all other peaceful

    conflict resolution options having been exhausted.

    The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy sums up the

    doctrine thus:

    “The principles of the justice of war are commonly held to

    be:

    (1) Having just cause (especially and, according to the

    United Nations Charter, exclusively, self-defense)

    (2) Being (formally) declared by a proper authority

    (3) Possessing a right intention

    (4) Having a reasonable chance of success

    (5) The end being proportional to the means used.”

    Yet, the evolution of warfare – the invention of nuclear

    weapons, the propagation of total war, the ubiquity of

    guerrilla and national liberation movements, the

    emergence of global, border-hopping terrorist

    organizations, of totalitarian regimes, and rogue or failed

    states – requires these principles to be modified by adding

    these tenets:

    (6) That the declaring authority is a lawfully and

    democratically elected government

    (7) That the declaration of war reflects the popular will

    (Extension of 3) The right intention is to act in just cause.

    (Extension of 4) … or a reasonable chance of avoiding an

    annihilating defeat

    (Extension of 5) That the outcomes of war are preferable

    to the outcomes of the preservation of peace.

    Still, the doctrine of just war, conceived in Europe in eras

    past, is fraying at the edges. Rights and corresponding

    duties are ill-defined or mismatched. What is legal is not

    always moral and what is legitimate is not invariably

    legal. Political realism and quasi-religious idealism sit

    uncomfortably within the same conceptual framework.

    Norms are vague and debatable while customary law is

    only partially subsumed in the tradition (i.e., in treaties,

    conventions and other instruments, as well in the actual

    conduct of states).

    The most contentious issue is, of course, what constitutes

    “just cause”. Self-defense, in its narrowest sense (reaction

    to direct and overwhelming armed aggression), is a

    justified casus belli. But what about the use of force to

    (deontologically, consequentially, or ethically):

    (1) Prevent or ameliorate a slow-motion or permanent

    humanitarian crisis

    (2) Preempt a clear and present danger of aggression

    (“anticipatory or preemptive self-defense” against what

    Grotius called “immediate danger”)

    (3) Secure a safe environment for urgent and

    indispensable humanitarian relief operations

    (4) Restore democracy in the attacked state (“regime

    change”)

    (5) Restore public order in the attacked state

    (6) Prevent human rights violations or crimes against

    humanity or violations of international law by the attacked

    state

    (7) Keep the peace (“peacekeeping operations”) and

    enforce compliance with international or bilateral treaties

    between the aggressor and the attacked state or the

    attacked state and a third party

    (8) Suppress armed infiltration, indirect aggression, or

    civil strife aided and abetted by the attacked state

    (9) Honor one’s obligations to frameworks and treaties of

    collective self-defense

    (10) Protect one’s citizens or the citizens of a third party

    inside the attacked state

    (11) Protect one’s property or assets owned by a third

    party inside the attacked state

    (12) Respond to an invitation by the authorities of the

    attacked state – and with their expressed consent – to

    militarily intervene within the territory of the attacked

    state

    (13) React to offenses against the nation’s honor or its

    economy

    Unless these issues are resolved and codified, the entire

    edifice of international law – and, more specifically, the

    law of war – is in danger of crumbling. The contemporary

    multilateral regime proved inadequate and unable to

    effectively tackle genocide (Rwanda, Bosnia), terror (in

    Africa, Central Asia, and the Middle East), weapons of

    mass destruction (Iraq, India, Israel, Pakistan, North

    Korea), and tyranny (in dozens of members of the United

    Nations).

    This feebleness inevitably led to the resurgence of “might

    is right” unilateralism, as practiced, for instance, by the

    United States in places as diverse as Grenada and Iraq.

    This pernicious and ominous phenomenon is coupled with

    contempt towards and suspicion of international

    organizations, treaties, institutions, undertakings, and the

    prevailing consensual order.

    In a unipolar world, reliant on a single superpower for its

    security, the abrogation of the rules of the game could

    lead to chaotic and lethal anarchy with a multitude of

    “rebellions” against the emergent American Empire.

    International law – the formalism of “natural law” – is only

    one of many competing universalist and missionary value

    systems. Militant Islam is another. The West must adopt

    the former to counter the latter.

    Cannibalism and Human Sacrifice
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    “I believe that when man evolves a civilization higher

    than the mechanized but still primitive one he has now,

    the eating of human flesh will be sanctioned. For then

    man will have thrown off all of his superstitions and

    irrational taboos.”

    (Diego Rivera)

    “One calls ‘barbarism’ whatever he is not accustomed

    to.”

    (Montaigne, On Cannibalism)

    “Then Jesus said unto them, Verily, verily, I say unto

    you, Except ye eat the flesh of the Son of man, and drink

    his blood, ye have no life in you. Whoso eateth my flesh,

    and drinketh my blood, hath eternal life; and I will raise

    him up at the last day. For my flesh is meat indeed, and

    my blood is drink indeed.”

    (New Testament, John 6:53-55)

    Cannibalism (more precisely, anthropophagy) is an age-

    old tradition that, judging by a constant stream of

    flabbergasted news reports, is far from extinct. Much-

    debated indications exist that our Neanderthal, Proto-

    Neolithic, and Neolithic (Stone Age) predecessors were

    cannibals. Similarly contested claims were made with

    regards to the 12th century advanced Anasazi culture in

    the southwestern United States and the Minoans in Crete

    (today’s Greece).

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    The Britannica Encyclopedia (2005 edition) recounts how

    the “Binderwurs of central India ate their sick and aged

    in the belief that the act was pleasing to their goddess,

    Kali.” Cannibalism may also have been common among

    followers of the Shaktism cults in India.

    Other sources attribute cannibalism to the 16th century

    Imbangala in today’s Angola and Congo, the Fang in

    Cameroon, the Mangbetu in Central Africa, the Ache in

    Paraguay, the Tonkawa in today’s Texas, the Calusa in

    current day Florida, the Caddo and Iroquois confederacies

    of Indians in North America, the Cree in Canada, the

    Witoto, natives of Colombia and Peru, the Carib in the

    Lesser Antilles (whose distorted name – Canib – gave rise

    to the word “cannibalism”), to Maori tribes in today’s New

    Zealand, and to various peoples in Sumatra (like the

    Batak).

    The Wikipedia numbers among the practitioners of

    cannibalism the ancient Chinese, the Korowai tribe of

    southeastern Papua, the Fore tribe in New Guinea (and

    many other tribes in Melanesia), the Aztecs, the people of

    Yucatan, the Purchas from Popayan, Colombia, the

    denizens of the Marquesas Islands of Polynesia, and the

    natives of the captaincy of Sergipe in Brazil.

    From Congo and Central Africa to Germany and from

    Mexico to New Zealand, cannibalism is enjoying a

    morbid revival of interest, if not of practice. A veritable

    torrent of sensational tomes and movies adds to our

    ambivalent fascination with man-eaters.

    Cannibalism is not a monolithic affair. It can be divided

    thus:

    I. Non-consensual consumption of human flesh post-

    mortem

    For example, when the corpses of prisoners of war are

    devoured by their captors. This used to be a common

    exercise among island tribes (e.g., in Fiji, the Andaman

    and Cook islands) and is still the case in godforsaken

    battle zones such as Congo (formerly Zaire), or among the

    defeated Japanese soldiers in World War II.

    Similarly, human organs and fetuses as well as mummies

    are still being gobbled up – mainly in Africa and Asia – for

    remedial and medicinal purposes and in order to enhance

    one’s libido and vigor.

    On numerous occasions the organs of dead companions,

    colleagues, family, or neighbors were reluctantly ingested

    by isolated survivors of horrid accidents (the Uruguay

    rugby team whose plane crashed in the Andes, the boat

    people fleeing Asia), denizens of besieged cities (e.g.,

    during the siege of Leningrad), members of exploratory

    expeditions gone astray (the Donner Party in Sierra

    Nevada, California and John Franklin’s Polar expedition),

    famine-stricken populations (Ukraine in the 1930s, China

    in the 1960s), and the like.

    Finally, in various pre-nation-state and tribal societies,

    members of the family were encouraged to eat specific

    parts of their dead relatives as a sign of respect or in order

    to partake of the deceased’s wisdom, courage, or other

    positive traits (endocannibalism).

    II. Non-consensual consumption of human flesh from a

    live source

    For example, when prisoners of war are butchered for the

    express purpose of being eaten by their victorious

    enemies.

    A notorious and rare representative of this category of

    cannibalism is the punitive ritual of being eaten alive. The

    kings of the tribes of the Cook Islands were thought to

    embody the gods. They punished dissent by dissecting

    their screaming and conscious adversaries and consuming

    their flesh piecemeal, eyeballs first.

    The Sawney Bean family in Scotland, during the reign of

    King James I, survived for decades on the remains (and

    personal belongings) of victims of their murderous sprees.

    Real-life serial killers, like Jeffrey Dahmer, Albert Fish,

    Sascha Spesiwtsew, Fritz Haarmann, Issei Sagawa, and

    Ed Gein, lured, abducted, and massacred countless people

    and then consumed their flesh and preserved the inedible

    parts as trophies. These lurid deeds inspired a slew of

    books and films, most notably The Silence of the Lambs

    with Hannibal (Lecter) the Cannibal as its protagonist.

    III. Consensual consumption of human flesh from live

    and dead human bodies

    Armin Meiwes, the “Master Butcher (Der

    Metzgermeister)”, arranged over the Internet to meet

    Bernd Jurgen Brandes on March 2001. Meiwes amputated

    the penis of his guest and they both ate it. He then

    proceeded to kill Brandes (with the latter’s consent

    recorded on video), and snack on what remained of him.

    Sexual cannibalism is a paraphilia and an extreme – and

    thankfully, rare – form of fetishism.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/serialkillers.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/factoidg.html

    The Aztecs willingly volunteered to serve as human

    sacrifices (and to be tucked into afterwards). They firmly

    believed that they were offerings, chosen by the gods

    themselves, thus being rendered immortal.

    Dutiful sons and daughters in China made their amputated

    organs and sliced tissues (mainly the liver) available to

    their sick parents (practices known as Ko Ku and Ko

    Kan). Such donation were considered remedial. Princess

    Miao Chuang who surrendered her severed hands to her

    ailing father was henceforth deified.

    Non-consensual cannibalism is murder, pure and simple.

    The attendant act of cannibalism, though aesthetically and

    ethically reprehensible, cannot aggravate this supreme

    assault on all that we hold sacred.

    But consensual cannibalism is a lot trickier. Modern

    medicine, for instance, has blurred the already thin line

    between right and wrong.

    What is the ethical difference between consensual, post-

    mortem, organ harvesting and consensual, post-mortem

    cannibalism?

    Why is stem cell harvesting (from aborted fetuses)

    morally superior to consensual post-mortem cannibalism?

    When members of a plane-wrecked rugby team, stranded

    on an inaccessible, snow-piled, mountain range resort to

    eating each other in order to survive, we turn a blind eye

    to their repeated acts of cannibalism – but we condemn the

    very same deed in the harshest terms if it takes place

    between two consenting, and even eager adults in

    Germany. Surely, we don’t treat murder, pedophilia, and

    incest the same way!

    As the Auxiliary Bishop of Montevideo said after the

    crash:

    “… Eating someone who has died in order to survive is

    incorporating their substance, and it is quite possible to

    compare this with a graft. Flesh survives when

    assimilated by someone in extreme need, just as it does

    when an eye or heart of a dead man is grafted onto a

    living man…”

    (Read, P.P. 1974. Alive. Avon, New York)

    Complex ethical issues are involved in the apparently

    straightforward practice of consensual cannibalism.

    Consensual, in vivo, cannibalism (a-la Messrs. Meiwes

    and Brandes) resembles suicide. The cannibal is merely

    the instrument of voluntary self-destruction. Why would

    we treat it different to the way we treat any other form of

    suicide pact?

    Consensual cannibalism is not the equivalent of drug

    abuse because it has no social costs. Unlike junkies, the

    cannibal and his meal are unlikely to harm others. What

    gives society the right to intervene, therefore?

    If we own our bodies and, thus, have the right to smoke,

    drink, have an abortion, commit suicide, and will our

    organs to science after we die – why don’t we possess the

    inalienable right to will our delectable tissues to a

    discerning cannibal post-mortem (or to victims of famine

    in Africa)?

    When does our right to dispose of our organs in any way

    we see fit crystallize? Is it when we die? Or after we are

    dead? If so, what is the meaning and legal validity of a

    living will? And why can’t we make a living will and

    bequeath our cadaverous selves to the nearest cannibal?

    Do dead people have rights and can they claim and invoke

    them while they are still alive? Is the live person the same

    as his dead body, does he “own” it, does the state have

    any rights in it? Does the corpse stll retain its previous

    occupant’s “personhood”? Are cadavers still human, in

    any sense of the word?

    We find all three culinary variants abhorrent. Yet, this

    instinctive repulsion is a curious matter. The onerous

    demands of survival should have encouraged cannibalism

    rather than make it a taboo. Human flesh is protein-rich.

    Most societies, past and present (with the exception of the

    industrialized West), need to make efficient use of rare

    protein-intensive resources.

    If cannibalism enhances the chances of survival – why is it

    universally prohibited? For many a reason.

    I. The Sanctity of Life

    Historically, cannibalism preceded, followed, or

    precipitated an act of murder or extreme deprivation (such

    as torture). It habitually clashed with the principle of the

    sanctity of life. Once allowed, even under the strictest

    guidelines, cannibalism tended to debase and devalue

    human life and foster homicide, propelling its

    practitioners down a slippery ethical slope towards

    bloodlust and orgiastic massacres.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/death.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/human.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/torturepsychology.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html

    II. The Afterlife

    Moreover, in life, the human body and form are

    considered by most religions (and philosophers) to be the

    abode of the soul, the divine spark that animates us all.

    The post-mortem integrity of this shrine is widely thought

    to guarantee a faster, unhindered access to the afterlife, to

    immortality, and eventual reincarnation (or karmic cycle

    in eastern religions).

    For this reason, to this very day, orthodox Jews refuse to

    subject their relatives to a post-mortem autopsy and organ

    harvesting. Fijians and Cook Islanders used to consume

    their enemies’ carcasses in order to prevent their souls

    from joining hostile ancestors in heaven.

    III. Chastening Reminders

    Cannibalism is a chilling reminder of our humble origins

    in the animal kingdom. To the cannibal, we are no better

    and no more than cattle or sheep. Cannibalism confronts

    us with the irreversibility of our death and its finality.

    Surely, we cannot survive our demise with our cadaver

    mutilated and gutted and our skeletal bones scattered,

    gnawed, and chewed on?

    IV. Medical Reasons

    Infrequently, cannibalism results in prion diseases of the

    nervous system, such as kuru. The same paternalism that

    gave rise to the banning of drug abuse, the outlawing of

    suicide, and the Prohibition of alcoholic drinks in the

    1920s – seeks to shelter us from the pernicious medical

    outcomes of cannibalism and to protect others who might

    become our victims.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/animal.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/factoidpq.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/suicide.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/factoidpq.html

    V. The Fear of Being Objectified

    Being treated as an object (being objectified) is the most

    torturous form of abuse. People go to great lengths to seek

    empathy and to be perceived by others as three

    dimensional entities with emotions, needs, priorities,

    wishes, and preferences.

    The cannibal reduces others by treating them as so much

    meat. Many cannibal serial killers transformed the organs

    of their victims into trophies. The Cook Islanders sought

    to humiliate their enemies by eating, digesting, and then

    defecating them – having absorbed their mana (prowess,

    life force) in the process.

    VI. The Argument from Nature

    Cannibalism is often castigated as “unnatural”. Animals,

    goes the myth, don’t prey on their own kind.

    Alas, like so many other romantic lores, this is untrue.

    Most species – including our closest relatives, the

    chimpanzees – do cannibalize. Cannibalism in nature is

    widespread and serves diverse purposes such as

    population control (chickens, salamanders, toads), food

    and protein security in conditions of scarcity

    (hippopotamuses, scorpions, certain types of dinosaurs),

    threat avoidance (rabbits, mice, rats, and hamsters), and

    the propagation of genetic material through exclusive

    mating (Red-back spider and many mantids).

    Moreover, humans are a part of nature. Our deeds and

    misdeeds are natural by definition. Seeking to tame nature

    is a natural act. Seeking to establish hierarchies and

    subdue or relinquish our enemies are natural propensities.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/abuse.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/empathy.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/serialkillers.html

    By avoiding cannibalism we seek to transcend nature.

    Refraining from cannibalism is the unnatural act.

    VIII. The Argument from Progress

    It is a circular syllogism involving a tautology and goes

    like this:

    Cannibalism is barbaric. Cannibals are, therefore,

    barbarians. Progress entails the abolition of this practice.

    The premises – both explicit and implicit – are axiomatic

    and, therefore, shaky. What makes cannibalism barbarian?

    And why is progress a desirable outcome? There is a

    prescriptive fallacy involved, as well:

    Because we do not eat the bodies of dead people – we

    ought not to eat them.

    VIII. Arguments from Religious Ethics

    The major monotheistic religions are curiously mute when

    it comes to cannibalism. Human sacrifice is denounced

    numerous times in the Old Testament – but man-eating

    goes virtually unmentioned. The Eucharist in Christianity

    – when the believers consume the actual body and blood

    of Jesus – is an act of undisguised cannibalism:

    “That the consequence of Transubstantiation, as a

    conversion of the total substance, is the transition of the

    entire substance of the bread and wine into the Body and

    Blood of Christ, is the express doctrine of the Church

    ….”

    (Catholic Encyclopedia)

    “CANON lI.-If any one saith, that, in the sacred and

    holy sacrament of the Eucharist, the substance of the

    bread and wine remains conjointly with the body and

    blood of our Lord Jesus Christ, and denieth that

    wonderful and singular conversion of the whole

    substance of the bread into the Body, and of the whole

    substance of the wine into the Blood-the species Only of

    the bread and wine remaining-which conversion indeed

    the Catholic Church most aptly calls

    Transubstantiation; let him be anathema.

    CANON VIII.-lf any one saith, that Christ, given in the

    Eucharist, is eaten spiritually only, and not also

    sacramentally and really; let him be anathema.”

    (The Council of Trent, The Thirteenth Session – The

    canons and decrees of the sacred and oecumenical

    Council of Trent, Ed. and trans. J. Waterworth

    (London: Dolman, 1848), 75-91.)

    Still, most systems of morality and ethics impute to Man a

    privileged position in the scheme of things (having been

    created in the “image of God”). Men and women are

    supposed to transcend their animal roots and inhibit their

    baser instincts (an idea incorporated into Freud’s tripartite

    model of the human psyche). The anthropocentric

    chauvinistic view is that it is permissible to kill all other

    animals in order to consume their flesh. Man, in this

    respect, is sui generis.

    Yet, it is impossible to rigorously derive a prohibition to

    eat human flesh from any known moral system. As

    Richard Routley-Silvan observes in his essay “In Defence

    of Cannibalism”, that something is innately repugnant

    does not make it morally prohibited. Moreover, that we

    http://samvak.tripod.com/psychoanalysis.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/psychoanalysis.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/psychoanalysis.html

    find cannibalism nauseating is probably the outcome of

    upbringing and conditioning rather than anything innate.

    Euthanasia and the Right to Die
    By: Dr. Sam Vaknin

    I. Definitions of Types of Euthanasia

    Euthanasia is often erroneously described as “mercy

    killing”. Most forms of euthanasia are, indeed, motivated

    by (some say: misplaced) mercy. Not so others. In Greek,

    “eu” means both “well” and “easy” and “Thanatos” is

    death.

    Euthanasia is the intentional premature termination of

    another person’s life either by direct intervention (active

    euthanasia) or by withholding life-prolonging measures

    and resources (passive euthanasia), either at the express

    or implied request of that person (voluntary euthanasia),

    or in the absence of such approval (non-voluntary

    euthanasia). Involuntary euthanasia – where the

    individual wishes to go on living – is an euphemism for

    murder.

    To my mind, passive euthanasia is immoral. The abrupt

    withdrawal of medical treatment, feeding, and hydration

    results in a slow and (potentially) torturous death. It took

    Terri Schiavo 13 days to die, when her tubes were

    withdrawn in the last two weeks of March 2005. It is

    morally wrong to subject even animals to such gratuitous

    suffering. Moreover, passive euthanasia allows us to

    evade personal responsibility for the patient’s death. In

    active euthanasia, the relationship between the act (of

    administering a lethal medication, for instance) and its

    consequences is direct and unambiguous.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cv.html

    As the philosopher John Finnis notes, to qualify as

    euthanasia, the termination of life has to be the main and

    intended aim of the act or omission that lead to it. If the

    loss of life is incidental (a side effect), the agent is still

    morally responsible but to describe his actions and

    omissions as euthanasia would be misleading.

    Volntariness (accepting the foreseen but unintended

    consequences of one’s actions and omissions) should be

    distinguished from intention.

    Still, this sophistry obscures the main issue:

    If the sanctity of life is a supreme and overriding value

    (“basic good”), it ought to surely preclude and proscribe

    all acts and omissions which may shorten it, even when

    the shortening of life is a mere deleterious side effect.

    But this is not the case. The sanctity and value of life

    compete with a host of other equally potent moral

    demands. Even the most devout pro-life ethicist accepts

    that certain medical decisions – for instance, to administer

    strong analgesics – inevitably truncate the patient’s life.

    Yet, this is considered moral because the resulting

    euthanasia is not the main intention of the pain-relieving

    doctor.

    Moreover, the apparent dilemma between the two values

    (reduce suffering or preserve life) is non-existent.

    There are four possible situations. Imagine a patient

    writhing with insufferable pain.

    1. The patient’s life is not at risk if she is not medicated

    with painkillers (she risks dying if she is medicated)

    2. The patient’s life is not at risk either way, medicated or

    not

    3. The patient’s life is at risk either way, medicated or not

    4. The patient’s life is at risk if she is not medicated with

    painkillers

    In all four cases, the decisions our doctor has to make are

    ethically clear cut. He should administer pain-alleviating

    drugs, except when the patient risks dying (in 1 above).

    The (possible) shortening of the patient’s life (which is

    guesswork, at best) is immaterial.

    II. Who is or Should Be Subject to Euthanasia? The

    Problem of Dualism vs. Reductionism

    With the exception of radical animal rights activists, most

    philosophers and laymen consider people – human beings

    – to be entitled to “special treatment”, to be in possession

    of unique rights (and commensurate obligations), and to

    be capable of feats unparalleled in other species.

    Thus, opponents of euthanasia universally oppose the

    killing of “persons”. As the (pro-euthanasia) philosopher

    John Harris puts it:

    ” … concern for their welfare, respect for their wishes,

    respect for the intrinsic value of their lives and respect

    for their interests.”

    Ronald Dworkin emphasizes the investments – made by

    nature, the person involved, and others – which euthanasia

    wastes. But he also draws attention to the person’s “critical

    interests” – the interests whose satisfaction makes life

    http://samvak.tripod.com/animal.html

    better to live. The manner of one’s own death may be such

    a critical interest. Hence, one should have the right to

    choose how one dies because the “right kind” of death

    (e.g., painless, quick, dignified) reflects on one’s entire

    life, affirms and improves it.

    But who is a person? What makes us human? Many

    things, most of which are irrelevant to our discussion.

    Broadly speaking, though, there are two schools of

    thought:

    (i) That we are rendered human by the very event of our

    conception (egg meets sperm), or, at the latest, our birth;

    or

    (ii) That we are considered human only when we act and

    think as conscious humans do.

    The proponents of the first case (i) claim that merely

    possessing a human body (or the potential to come to

    possess such a body) is enough to qualify us as “persons”.

    There is no distinction between mind and abode – thought,

    feelings, and actions are merely manifestations of one

    underlying unity. The fact that some of these

    manifestations have yet to materialize (in the case of an

    embryo) or are mere potentials (in the case of a comatose

    patient) does not detract from our essential,

    incontrovertible, and indivisible humanity. We may be

    immature or damaged persons – but we are persons all the

    same (and always will be persons).

    Though considered “religious” and “spiritual”, this notion

    is actually a form of reductionism. The mind, “soul”, and

    http://samvak.tripod.com/human.html

    “spirit” are mere expressions of one unity, grounded in

    our “hardware” – in our bodies.

    Those who argue the second case (ii) postulate that it is

    possible to have a human body which does not host a

    person. People in Persistent Vegetative States, for instance

    – or fetuses, for that matter – are human but also non-

    persons. This is because they do not yet – or are unable to

    – exercise their faculties. Personhood is complexity. When

    the latter ceases, so does the former. Personhood is

    acquired and is an extensive parameter, a total, defining

    state of being. One is either awake or asleep, either dead

    or alive, either in a state of personhood or not

    The latter approach involves fine distinctions between

    potential, capacity, and skill. A human body (or fertilized

    egg) have the potential to think, write poetry, feel pain,

    and value life. At the right phase of somatic development,

    this potential becomes capacity and, once it is

    competently exercised – it is a skill.

    Embryos and comatose people may have the potential to

    do and think – but, in the absence of capacities and skills,

    they are not full-fledged persons. Indeed, in all important

    respects, they are already dead.

    Taken to its logical conclusion, this definition of a person

    also excludes newborn infants, the severely retarded, the

    hopelessly quadriplegic, and the catatonic. “Who is a

    person” becomes a matter of culturally-bound and

    medically-informed judgment which may be influenced

    by both ignorance and fashion and, thus, be arbitrary and

    immoral.

    Imagine a computer infected by a computer virus which

    cannot be quarantined, deleted, or fixed. The virus

    disables the host and renders it “dead”. Is it still a

    computer? If someone broke into my house and stole it,

    can I file an insurance claim? If a colleague destroys it,

    can I sue her for the damages? The answer is yes. A

    computer is a computer for as long as it exists physically

    and a cure is bound to be found even against the most

    trenchant virus.

    The definition of personhood must rely on objective,

    determinate and determinable criteria. The anti-euthanasia

    camp relies on bodily existence as one such criterion. The

    pro-euthanasia faction has yet to reciprocate.

    III. Euthanasia and Suicide

    Self-sacrifice, avoidable martyrdom, engaging in life
    risking activities, refusal to prolong one’s life through
    medical treatment, euthanasia, overdosing, and self-
    destruction that is the result of coercion – are all closely
    related to suicide. They all involve a deliberately self-

    inflicted death.

    But while suicide is chiefly intended to terminate a life –
    the other acts are aimed at perpetuating, strengthening,

    and defending values or other people. Many – not only

    religious people – are appalled by the choice implied in

    suicide – of death over life. They feel that it demeans life

    and abnegates its meaning.

    Life’s meaning – the outcome of active selection by the

    individual – is either external (such as “God’s plan”) or

    internal, the outcome of an arbitrary frame of reference,

    such as having a career goal. Our life is rendered

    meaningful only by integrating into an eternal thing,

    process, design, or being. Suicide makes life trivial

    because the act is not natural – not part of the eternal

    framework, the undying process, the timeless cycle of

    birth and death. Suicide is a break with eternity.

    Henry Sidgwick said that only conscious (i.e., intelligent)

    beings can appreciate values and meanings. So, life is

    significant to conscious, intelligent, though finite, beings –

    because it is a part of some eternal goal, plan, process,

    thing, design, or being. Suicide flies in the face of

    Sidgwick’s dictum. It is a statement by an intelligent and

    conscious being about the meaninglessness of life.

    If suicide is a statement, than society, in this case, is
    against the freedom of expression. In the case of suicide,
    free speech dissonantly clashes with the sanctity of a
    meaningful life. To rid itself of the anxiety brought on by
    this conflict, society cast suicide as a depraved or even

    criminal act and its perpetrators are much castigated.

    The suicide violates not only the social contract but, many

    will add, covenants with God or nature. St. Thomas

    Aquinas wrote in the “Summa Theologiae” that – since

    organisms strive to survive – suicide is an unnatural act.

    Moreover, it adversely affects the community and violates

    the property rights of God, the imputed owner of one’s

    spirit. Christianity regards the immortal soul as a gift and,

    in Jewish writings, it is a deposit. Suicide amounts to the

    abuse or misuse of God’s possessions, temporarily lodged

    in a corporeal mansion.

    This paternalism was propagated, centuries later, by Sir

    William Blackstone, the codifier of British Law. Suicide –

    being self-murder – is a grave felony, which the state has a

    right to prevent and to punish for. In certain countries this

    still is the case. In Israel, for instance, a soldier is

    considered to be “military property” and an attempted

    suicide is severely punished as “the corruption of an army

    chattel”.

    Paternalism, a malignant mutation of benevolence, is
    about objectifying people and treating them as
    possessions. Even fully-informed and consenting adults
    are not granted full, unmitigated autonomy, freedom, and
    privacy. This tends to breed “victimless crimes”. The
    “culprits” – gamblers, homosexuals, communists, suicides,
    drug addicts, alcoholics, prostitutes – are “protected from
    themselves” by an intrusive nanny state.

    The possession of a right by a person imposes on others a

    corresponding obligation not to act to frustrate its

    exercise. Suicide is often the choice of a mentally and

    legally competent adult. Life is such a basic and deep set

    phenomenon that even the incompetents – the mentally

    retarded or mentally insane or minors – can fully gauge its

    significance and make “informed” decisions, in my view.

    The paternalists claim counterfactually that no competent
    adult “in his right mind” will ever decide to commit
    suicide. They cite the cases of suicides who survived and
    felt very happy that they have – as a compelling reason to
    intervene. But we all make irreversible decisions for
    which, sometimes, we are sorry. It gives no one the right

    to interfere.

    Paternalism is a slippery slope. Should the state be
    allowed to prevent the birth of a genetically defective

    child or forbid his parents to marry in the first place?

    Should unhealthy adults be forced to abstain from

    smoking, or steer clear from alcohol? Should they be

    coerced to exercise?

    Suicide is subject to a double moral standard. People are
    permitted – nay, encouraged – to sacrifice their life only in
    certain, socially sanctioned, ways. To die on the
    battlefield or in defense of one’s religion is commendable.
    This hypocrisy reveals how power structures – the state,
    institutional religion, political parties, national movements
    – aim to monopolize the lives of citizens and adherents to
    do with as they see fit. Suicide threatens this monopoly.
    Hence the taboo.

    Does one have a right to take one’s life?

    The answer is: it depends. Certain cultures and societies
    encourage suicide. Both Japanese kamikaze and Jewish
    martyrs were extolled for their suicidal actions. Certain
    professions are knowingly life-threatening – soldiers,
    firemen, policemen. Certain industries – like the
    manufacture of armaments, cigarettes, and alcohol – boost

    overall mortality rates.

    In general, suicide is commended when it serves social
    ends, enhances the cohesion of the group, upholds its
    values, multiplies its wealth, or defends it from external
    and internal threats. Social structures and human
    collectives – empires, countries, firms, bands, institutions –
    often commit suicide. This is considered to be a healthy
    process.

    More about suicide, the meaning of life, and related

    considerations – HERE.

    Back to our central dilemma:

    http://samvak.tripod.com/suicide.html

    Is it morally justified to commit suicide in order to avoid

    certain, forthcoming, unavoidable, and unrelenting torture,

    pain, or coma?

    Is it morally justified to ask others to help you to commit

    suicide (for instance, if you are incapacitated)?

    Imagine a society that venerates life-with-dignity by

    making euthanasia mandatory – would it then and there be

    morally justified to refuse to commit suicide or to help in

    it?

    IV. Euthanasia and Murder

    Imagine killing someone before we have ascertained her

    preferences as to the manner of her death and whether she

    wants to die at all. This constitutes murder even if, after

    the fact, we can prove conclusively that the victim wanted

    to die.

    Is murder, therefore, merely the act of taking life,

    regardless of circumstances – or is it the nature of the

    interpersonal interaction that counts? If the latter, the

    victim’s will counts – if the former, it is irrelevant.

    V. Euthanasia, the Value of Life, and the Right to Life

    Few philosophers, legislators, and laymen support non-

    voluntary or involuntary euthanasia. These types of

    “mercy” killing are associated with the most heinous

    crimes against humanity committed by the Nazi regime on

    both its own people and other nations. They are and were

    also an integral part of every program of active eugenics.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/eugenics.html

    The arguments against killing someone who hasn’t

    expressed a wish to die (let alone someone who has

    expressed a desire to go on living) revolve around the

    right to life. People are assumed to value their life, cherish

    it, and protect it. Euthanasia – especially the non-voluntary

    forms – amounts to depriving someone (as well as their

    nearest and dearest) of something they value.

    The right to life – at least as far as human beings are

    concerned – is a rarely questioned fundamental moral

    principle. In Western cultures, it is assumed to be

    inalienable and indivisible (i.e., monolithic). Yet, it is

    neither. Even if we accept the axiomatic – and therefore

    arbitrary – source of this right, we are still faced with

    intractable dilemmas. All said, the right to life may be

    nothing more than a cultural construct, dependent on

    social mores, historical contexts, and exegetic systems.

    Rights – whether moral or legal – impose obligations or
    duties on third parties towards the right-holder. One has a
    right AGAINST other people and thus can prescribe to
    them certain obligatory behaviors and proscribe certain
    acts or omissions. Rights and duties are two sides of the

    same Janus-like ethical coin.

    This duality confuses people. They often erroneously
    identify rights with their attendant duties or obligations,
    with the morally decent, or even with the morally
    permissible. One’s rights inform other people how they
    MUST behave towards one – not how they SHOULD or
    OUGHT to act morally. Moral behavior is not dependent

    on the existence of a right. Obligations are.

    To complicate matters further, many apparently simple
    and straightforward rights are amalgams of more basic

    moral or legal principles. To treat such rights as unities is

    to mistreat them.

    Take the right to life. It is a compendium of no less than
    eight distinct rights: the right to be brought to life, the
    right to be born, the right to have one’s life maintained,
    the right not to be killed, the right to have one’s life
    saved, the right to save one’s life (wrongly reduced to the

    right to self-defence), the right to terminate one’s life, and

    the right to have one’s life terminated.
    None of these rights is self-evident, or unambiguous, or
    universal, or immutable, or automatically applicable. It is
    safe to say, therefore, that these rights are not primary as

    hitherto believed – but derivative.

    Go HERE to learn more about the Right to Life.

    Of the eight strands comprising the right to life, we are

    concerned with a mere two.

    The Right to Have One’s Life Maintained
    This leads to a more general quandary. To what extent can
    one use other people’s bodies, their property, their time,
    their resources and to deprive them of pleasure, comfort,
    material possessions, income, or any other thing – in order

    to maintain one’s life?

    Even if it were possible in reality, it is indefensible to
    maintain that I have a right to sustain, improve, or prolong
    my life at another’s expense. I cannot demand – though I
    can morally expect – even a trivial and minimal sacrifice
    from another in order to prolong my life. I have no right to
    do so.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/life.html

    Of course, the existence of an implicit, let alone explicit,
    contract between myself and another party would change
    the picture. The right to demand sacrifices commensurate
    with the provisions of the contract would then crystallize
    and create corresponding duties and obligations.
    No embryo has a right to sustain its life, maintain, or
    prolong it at its mother’s expense. This is true regardless

    of how insignificant the sacrifice required of her is.

    Yet, by knowingly and intentionally conceiving the
    embryo, the mother can be said to have signed a contract
    with it. The contract causes the right of the embryo to
    demand such sacrifices from his mother to crystallize. It
    also creates corresponding duties and obligations of the
    mother towards her embryo.
    We often find ourselves in a situation where we do not
    have a given right against other individuals – but we do
    possess this very same right against society. Society owes

    us what no constituent-individual does.

    Thus, we all have a right to sustain our lives, maintain,
    prolong, or even improve them at society’s expense – no
    matter how major and significant the resources required.
    Public hospitals, state pension schemes, and police forces
    may be needed in order to fulfill society’s obligations to
    prolong, maintain, and improve our lives – but fulfill them

    it must.

    Still, each one of us can sign a contract with society –
    implicitly or explicitly – and abrogate this right. One can
    volunteer to join the army. Such an act constitutes a
    contract in which the individual assumes the duty or
    obligation to give up his or her life.

    The Right not to be Killed
    It is commonly agreed that every person has the right not
    to be killed unjustly. Admittedly, what is just and what is
    unjust is determined by an ethical calculus or a social
    contract – both constantly in flux.
    Still, even if we assume an Archimedean immutable point
    of moral reference – does A’s right not to be killed mean
    that third parties are to refrain from enforcing the rights of
    other people against A? What if the only way to right
    wrongs committed by A against others – was to kill A?
    The moral obligation to right wrongs is about restoring the

    rights of the wronged.

    If the continued existence of A is predicated on the
    repeated and continuous violation of the rights of others –
    and these other people object to it – then A must be killed
    if that is the only way to right the wrong and re-assert the
    rights of A’s victims.
    The Right to have One’s Life Saved
    There is no such right because there is no moral obligation
    or duty to save a life. That people believe otherwise
    demonstrates the muddle between the morally
    commendable, desirable, and decent (“ought”, “should”)
    and the morally obligatory, the result of other people’s
    rights (“must”). In some countries, the obligation to save a
    life is codified in the law of the land. But legal rights and
    obligations do not always correspond to moral rights and

    obligations, or give rise to them.

    VI. Euthanasia and Personal Autonomy

    The right to have one’s life terminated at will (euthanasia),
    is subject to social, ethical, and legal strictures. In some
    countries – such as the Netherlands – it is legal (and
    socially acceptable) to have one’s life terminated with the
    help of third parties given a sufficient deterioration in the
    quality of life and given the imminence of death. One has
    to be of sound mind and will one’s death knowingly,

    intentionally, repeatedly, and forcefully.

    Should we have a right to die (given hopeless medical

    circumstances)? When our wish to end it all conflicts with

    society’s (admittedly, paternalistic) judgment of what is

    right and what is good for us and for others – what should

    prevail?

    One the one hand, as Patrick Henry put it, “give me

    liberty or give me death”. A life without personal

    autonomy and without the freedom to make unpopular

    and non-conformist decisions is, arguably, not worth

    living at all!

    As Dworkin states:

    “Making someone die in a way that others approve, but

    he believes a horrifying contradiction of his life, is a

    devastating, odious form of tyranny”.

    Still, even the victim’s express wishes may prove to be

    transient and circumstantial (due to depression,

    misinformation, or clouded judgment). Can we regard

    them as immutable and invariable? Moreover, what if the

    circumstances prove everyone – the victim included –

    wrong? What if a cure to the victim’s disease is found ten

    minutes after the euthanasia?

    VII. Euthanasia and Society

    It is commonly accepted that where two equally potent

    values clash, society steps in as an arbiter. The right to

    material welfare (food, shelter, basic possessions) often

    conflicts with the right to own private property and to

    benefit from it. Society strikes a fine balance by, on the

    one hand, taking from the rich and giving to the poor

    (through redistributive taxation) and, on the other hand,

    prohibiting and punishing theft and looting.

    Euthanasia involves a few such finely-balanced values:

    the sanctity of life vs. personal autonomy, the welfare of

    the many vs. the welfare of the individual, the relief of

    pain vs. the prolongation and preservation of life.

    Why can’t society step in as arbiter in these cases as well?

    Moreover, what if a person is rendered incapable of

    expressing his preferences with regards to the manner and

    timing of his death – should society step in (through the

    agency of his family or through the courts or legislature)

    and make the decision for him?

    In a variety of legal situations, parents, court-appointed

    guardians, custodians, and conservators act for, on behalf

    of, and in lieu of underage children, the physically and

    mentally challenged and the disabled. Why not here?

    We must distinguish between four situations:

    1. The patient foresaw the circumstances and provided an

    advance directive, asking explicitly for his life to be

    terminated when certain conditions are met.

    2. The patient did not provide an advanced directive but

    expressed his preference clearly before he was

    incapacitated. The risk here is that self-interested family

    members may lie.

    3. The patient did not provide an advance directive and

    did not express his preference aloud – but the decision to

    terminate his life is commensurate with both his character

    and with other decisions he made.

    4. There is no indication, however indirect, that the patient

    wishes or would have wished to die had he been capable

    of expression but the patient is no longer a “person” and,

    therefore, has no interests to respect, observe, and protect.

    Moreover, the patient is a burden to himself, to his nearest

    and dearest, and to society at large. Euthanasia is the right,

    just, and most efficient thing to do.

    Society can legalize euthanasia in the first case and,

    subject to rigorous fact checking, in the second and third

    cases. To prevent economically-motivated murder

    disguised as euthanasia, non-voluntary and involuntary

    euthanasia (as set in the forth case above) should be

    banned outright.

    VIII. Slippery Slope Arguments

    Issues in the Calculus of Rights – The Hierarchy of

    Rights
    The right to life supersedes – in Western moral and legal
    systems – all other rights. It overrules the right to one’s
    body, to comfort, to the avoidance of pain, or to
    ownership of property. Given such lack of equivocation,

    the amount of dilemmas and controversies surrounding
    the right to life is, therefore, surprising.
    When there is a clash between equally potent rights – for
    instance, the conflicting rights to life of two people – we
    can decide among them randomly (by flipping a coin, or
    casting dice). Alternatively, we can add and subtract

    rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic.

    Thus, if the continued life of an embryo or a fetus
    threatens the mother’s life – that is, assuming,
    controversially, that both of them have an equal right to
    life – we can decide to kill the fetus. By adding to the
    mother’s right to life her right to her own body we

    outweigh the fetus’ right to life.

    The Difference between Killing and Letting Die
    Counterintuitively, there is a moral gulf between killing
    (taking a life) and letting die (not saving a life). The right
    not to be killed is undisputed. There is no right to have
    one’s own life saved. Where there is a right – and only
    where there is one – there is an obligation. Thus, while
    there is an obligation not to kill – there is no obligation to
    save a life.

    Anti-euthanasia ethicists fear that allowing one kind of

    euthanasia – even under the strictest and explicit

    conditions – will open the floodgates. The value of life

    will be depreciated and made subordinate to

    considerations of economic efficacy and personal

    convenience. Murders, disguised as acts of euthanasia,

    will proliferate and none of us will be safe once we reach

    old age or become disabled.

    Years of legally-sanctioned euthanasia in the Netherlands,

    parts of Australia, and a state or two in the United States

    tend to fly in the face of such fears. Doctors did not regard

    these shifts in public opinion and legislative climate as a

    blanket license to kill their charges. Family members

    proved to be far less bloodthirsty and avaricious than

    feared.

    As long as non-voluntary and involuntary types of

    euthanasia are treated as felonies, it seems safe to allow

    patients to exercise their personal autonomy and grant

    them the right to die. Legalizing the institution of

    “advance directive” will go a long way towards regulating

    the field – as would a new code of medical ethics that will

    recognize and embrace reality: doctors, patients, and

    family members collude in their millions to commit

    numerous acts and omissions of euthanasia every day. It is

    their way of restoring dignity to the shattered lives and

    bodies of loved ones.

    T H E A U T H O R

    SHMUEL (SAM) VAKNIN

    Curriculum Vitae

    Click on blue text to access relevant web sites – thank you.

    Born in 1961 in Qiryat-Yam, Israel.

    Served in the Israeli Defence Force (1979-1982) in

    training and education units.

    Education

    Graduated a few semesters in the Technion – Israel

    Institute of Technology, Haifa.

    Ph.D. in Philosophy (major: Philosophy of Physics) –

    Pacific Western University, California, USA.

    My doctoral thesis and other books are available through

    the Library of Congress.

    Graduate of numerous courses in Finance Theory and

    International Trading.

    Certified E-Commerce Concepts Analyst by Brainbench.

    Certified in Psychological Counselling Techniques by

    Brainbench.

    http://philosophos.tripod.com/loc.html

    http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/transcript/public/viewtranscript.xml?pid=781937

    http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/business/aboutbrainbench.xml

    http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/transcript/public/transcript_testdetails.xml?back=1&pid=781937&testid=6149637

    http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/business/aboutbrainbench.xml

    Certified Financial Analyst by Brainbench.

    Full proficiency in Hebrew and in English.

    Business Experience

    1980 to 1983

    Founder and co-owner of a chain of computerised

    information kiosks in Tel-Aviv, Israel.

    1982 to 1985

    Senior positions with the Nessim D. Gaon Group of

    Companies in Geneva, Paris and New-York (NOGA and

    APROFIM SA):

    – Chief Analyst of Edible Commodities in the Group’s

    Headquarters in Switzerland

    – Manager of the Research and Analysis Division

    – Manager of the Data Processing Division

    – Project Manager of the Nigerian Computerised Census

    – Vice President in charge of RND and Advanced

    Technologies

    – Vice President in charge of Sovereign Debt Financing

    1985 to 1986

    Represented Canadian Venture Capital Funds in Israel.

    1986 to 1987

    General Manager of IPE Ltd. in London. The firm

    financed international multi-lateral countertrade and

    leasing transactions.

    http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/transcript/public/viewtranscript.xml?pid=781937

    http://www.brainbench.com/xml/bb/business/aboutbrainbench.xml

    1988 to

    1990

    Co-founder and Director of “Mikbats-Tesuah”, a portfolio

    management firm based in Tel-Aviv.

    Activities included large-scale portfolio management,

    underwriting, forex trading and general financial advisory

    services.

    1990 to Present

    Freelance consultant to many of Israel’s Blue-Chip firms,

    mainly on issues related to the capital markets in Israel,

    Canada, the UK and the USA.

    Consultant to foreign RND ventures and to Governments

    on macro-economic

    matters.

    President of the Israel chapter of the Professors World

    Peace Academy (PWPA) and (briefly) Israel

    representative of the “Washington Times”.

    1993 to 1994

    Co-owner and Director of many business enterprises:

    – The Omega and Energy Air-Conditioning Concern

    – AVP Financial Consultants

    – Handiman Legal Services

    Total annual turnover of the group: 10 million USD.

    Co-owner, Director and Finance Manager of COSTI Ltd.

    – Israel’s largest computerised information vendor and

    developer. Raised funds through a series of private

    placements locally in the USA, Canada and London.

    1993 to 1996

    Publisher and Editor of a Capital Markets Newsletter

    distributed by subscription only to dozens of subscribers

    countrywide.

    In a legal precedent in 1995 – studied in business schools

    and law faculties across Israel – was tried for his role in

    an attempted takeover of Israel’s Agriculture Bank.

    Was interned in the State School of Prison Wardens.

    Managed the Central School Library, wrote, published

    and lectured on various occasions.

    Managed the Internet and International News Department

    of an Israeli mass media group, “Ha-Tikshoret and

    Namer”.

    Assistant in the Law Faculty in Tel-Aviv University (to

    Prof. S.G. Shoham).

    1996 to 1999

    Financial consultant to leading businesses in Macedonia,

    Russia and the Czech Republic. Collaborated with the

    Agency of Transformation of Business with Social

    Capital.

    Economic commentator in “Nova Makedonija”,

    “Dnevnik”, “Makedonija Denes”, “Izvestia”, “Argumenti i

    Fakti”, “The Middle East Times”, “The New Presence”,

    “Central Europe Review”, and other periodicals, and in

    the economic programs on various channels of

    Macedonian Television.

    Нова Македонија – Првиот македонски дневен весник

    http://www.dnevnik.com.mk/

    http://www.pritomnost.cz/index.php?fulltext=vaknin

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    Chief Lecturer in courses organised by the Agency of

    Transformation, by the Macedonian Stock Exchange, and

    by the Ministry of Trade.

    1999 to 2002

    Economic Advisor to the Government of the Republic of

    Macedonia and to the Ministry of Finance.

    2001 to 2003

    Senior Business Correspondent for United Press

    International (UPI).

    Web and Journalistic Activities

    Author of extensive Web sites in:

    – Psychology (“Malignant Self Love”) – An Open

    Directory Cool Site,

    – Philosophy (“Philosophical Musings”),

    – Economics and Geopolitics (“World in Conflict and

    Transition”).

    Owner of the Narcissistic Abuse Announcement and

    Study List and the Narcissism Revisited mailing list (more

    than 4900 members).

    Owner of the Economies in Conflict and Transition Study

    List and the Link and Factoid Study List.

    http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/

    http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/Personality/Narcissistic

    http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/Personality/Narcissistic

    http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/Personality/Narcissistic

    http://philosophos.tripod.com/

    http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/

    http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/

    http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/narcissisticabuse/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/narcissisticabuse/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/narcissisticabuse/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/conflictransition/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/conflictransition/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/conflictransition/

    http://groups.yahoo.com/group/linknfactoid/

    Editor of mental health disorders and Central and Eastern

    Europe categories in various Web directories (Open

    Directory, Search Europe, Mentalhelp.net).

    Editor of the Narcissistic Personality Disorder, the Verbal

    and Emotional Abuse, and the Spousal (Domestic) Abuse

    and Violence topics on Suite 101 and Bellaonline.

    Columnist and commentator in “The New Presence”,

    United Press International (UPI), InternetContent,

    eBookWeb, PopMatters, Global Politician, and “Central

    Europe Review”.

    Publications and Awards

    “Managing Investment Portfolios in States of

    Uncertainty”, Limon Publishers, Tel-Aviv, 1988

    “The Gambling Industry”, Limon Publishers, Tel-Aviv,

    1990

    “Requesting My Loved One – Short Stories”, Yedioth

    Aharonot, Tel-Aviv, 1997

    “The Suffering of Being Kafka” (electronic book of

    Hebrew and English Short Fiction), Prague and Skopje,

    1998-2004

    “The Macedonian Economy at a Crossroads – On the Way

    to a Healthier Economy” (dialogues with Nikola

    Gruevski), Skopje, 1998

    “The Exporters’ Pocketbook”, Ministry of Trade, Republic

    of Macedonia, Skopje, 1999

    http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/

    http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/

    http://dmoz.org/Health/Mental_Health/Disorders/

    http://www.searcheurope.com/

    http://www.mentalhelp.net/poc/view_doc.php/type/doc/id/419

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/npd

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/verbal_emotional_abuse

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/verbal_emotional_abuse

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/verbal_emotional_abuse

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/18046

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/18046

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/18046

    http://www.bellaonline.com/archive/MentalHealth

    http://samvak.tripod.com/briefs.html

    http://www.popmatters.com/columns/archive.shtml

    http://www.globalpolitician.com/search.asp?keyword=Vaknin

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    http://www.yediothsfarim.co.il/catalog1.asp?bID=3621609

    http://samvak.tripod.com/sipurim.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cvng.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cvng.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/cvng.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/exporter.html

    “Malignant Self Love – Narcissism Revisited”, Narcissus

    Publications, Prague and Skopje, 1999, 2001, 2003, 2004

    The Narcissism Series (e-books regarding relationships

    with abusive narcissists), Skopje, 1999-2004

    “After the Rain – How the West Lost the East”, Narcissus

    Publications in association with Central Europe

    Review/CEENMI, Prague and Skopje, 2000

    Winner of numerous awards, among them Israel’s Council

    of Culture and Art Prize for Maiden Prose (1997), The

    Rotary Club Award for Social Studies (1976), and the

    Bilateral Relations Studies Award of the American

    Embassy in Israel (1978).

    Hundreds of professional articles in all fields of finances

    and the economy, and numerous articles dealing with

    geopolitical and political economic issues published in

    both print and Web periodicals in many countries.

    Many appearances in the electronic media on subjects in

    philosophy and the sciences, and concerning economic

    matters.

    Contact Details:

    palma@unet.com.mk

    vaknin@link.com.mk

    http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/after.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/aftertherain.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/aftertherain.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/aftertherain.html

    http://www.yediothsfarim.co.il/catalog1.asp?bID=3621609

    http://www.yediothsfarim.co.il/catalog1.asp?bID=3621609

    mailto:palma@unet.com.mk

    mailto:vaknin@link.com.mk

    My Web Sites:

    Economy / Politics:

    http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/

    Psychology:

    http://samvak.tripod.com/index.html

    Philosophy:

    http://philosophos.tripod.com/

    Poetry:

    http://samvak.tripod.com/contents.html

    Return

    http://ceeandbalkan.tripod.com/

    http://samvak.tripod.com/index.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/contents.html

    After the Rain
    How the West

    Lost the East

    The Book

    This is a series of articles written and published in 1996-2000 in Macedonia, in Russia,

    in Egypt and in the Czech Republic.

    How the West lost the East. The economics, the politics, the geopolitics, the

    conspiracies, the corruption, the old and the new, the plough and the internet – it is all

    here, in colourful and provocative prose.

    From “The Mind of Darkness”:

    “‘The Balkans’ – I say – ‘is the unconscious of the world’. People stop to digest this

    metaphor and then they nod enthusiastically. It is here that the repressed memories of

    history, its traumas and fears and images reside. It is here that the psychodynamics of

    humanity – the tectonic clash between Rome and Byzantium, West and East, Judeo-

    Christianity and Islam – is still easily discernible. We are seated at a New Year’s dining

    table, loaded with a roasted pig and exotic salads. I, the Jew, only half foreign to this

    cradle of Slavonics. Four Serbs, five Macedonians. It is in the Balkans that all ethnic

    distinctions fail and it is here that they prevail anachronistically and atavistically.

    Contradiction and change the only two fixtures of this tormented region. The women of

    the Balkan – buried under provocative mask-like make up, retro hairstyles and too

    narrow dresses. The men, clad in sepia colours, old fashioned suits and turn of the

    century moustaches. In the background there is the crying game that is Balkanian

    music: liturgy and folk and elegy combined. The smells are heavy with muskular

    perfumes. It is like time travel. It is like revisiting one’s childhood.”

    The Author

    Sam Vaknin is the author of Malignant Self Love –

    Narcissism Revisited and After the Rain – How the West

    Lost the East. He is a columnist for Central Europe

    Review and eBookWeb , a United Press International

    (UPI) Senior Business Correspondent, and the editor of

    mental health and Central East Europe categories in The

    Open Directory and Suite101 .

    Until recently, he served as the Economic Advisor to the

    Government of Macedonia.

    Visit Sam’s Web site at http://samvak.tripod.com

    mailto:palma@unet.com.mk

    http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/thebook.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/after.html

    http://samvak.tripod.com/after.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    http://www.ce-review.org/authorarchives/vaknin_archive/vaknin_main.html

    http://www.ebookweb.org/

    http://www.upi.com/results.cfm?Keywords=&Byline=Vaknin&DeskCode=All&IPTCCode=All&PubDateFromMonth=1&PubDateFromDay=01&PubDateFromYear=2001

    http://www.upi.com/results.cfm?Keywords=&Byline=Vaknin&DeskCode=All&IPTCCode=All&PubDateFromMonth=1&PubDateFromDay=01&PubDateFromYear=2001

    http://dmoz.org/

    http://www.suite101.com/welcome.cfm/npd

    http://samvak.tripod.com/

    Héctor E. López-Sierra, Ph.D.

    Associate Professo

    r

    Humanistic Studies Facult

    y

    Metropolitan Campus

    Inter American University of Puerto Ric

    o

    1

    Unit 1:

    Studying ethics in contemporary life

    and basic concepts of ethics from a

    scientific point of view

    2

    Introduction

    • Ethics is the discipline relating to right and wrong, moral
    duty and obligation, moral principles and values, and to
    moral character.

    • To many people ethics and morality are synonymous terms,
    both meaning customs in their original Greek and Latin
    respectively.

    • However, the Greek term “ethics” also implies character,
    whereas “mores” refers to social customs. Morals have
    probably been discussed as long as there has been
    language.

    • Although Socrates and Plato discussed moral questions at
    length, it was Aristotle who first made a systematic study of
    moral principles, and he called that ethics.

    3

    Introduction

    • Therefore, it’s vital to make a distinction between
    the terms and use “ethics” to refer to a universal or
    philosophical system of moral principles and
    values, while leaving “morality” to refer to the
    relative standards or values of any social group or
    person.

    • Of course much overlapping can occur. An
    individual’s or culture’s morality may often have
    universal standards, but in many cases they may
    not be universally applied in a philosophical way.

    4

    On what basis do we make moral

    decisions?

    • ―Do what the Bible tells you‖–

    Divine Command Theories

    • ―Follow your conscience‖–The Ethics of Conscienc

    e

    • ―Watch out for #1‖–

    Ethical Egois

    m

    • ―Do the right thing‖–

    The Ethics of

    Duty

    • ―Don’t dis’ me‖–

    The Ethics of Respec

    t

    • ―…all Men are created …with certain unalienable

    Rights‖–The Ethics of

    Rights

    • ―Make the world a better place‖–

    Utilitarianism

    • ―Daddy, that’s not fair‖–

    The Ethics of

    Justice

    • ―Be a good person‖–Virtue Ethics

    5

    Divine Command Theories

    • Being good is equivalent to

    doing whatever the Bible–or

    the Qur’an or some other

    sacred text or source of

    revelation–tells you to do.

    • ―What is right‖ equals ―What

    God tells me to do.‖

    6

    The Ethics of Our Inner Voice

    • Conscience tells us what is right or

    wron

    g

    • Often has a religious source

    • May be founded in a notion of human

    nature

    • Is often negative in character, telling

    us what is not right

    7

    Ethical Egoism

    • Says the only person to look

    out for is yourself

    • Well known for her novel,

    especially Atlas Shrugged

    8

    The Ethics of Duty

    • Begins with the conviction
    that ethics is about doing
    what is right, about doing
    your duty.

    • Duty may be determined by:

    – Reason

    • Kant: Do what any
    rational agent should
    do

    – Professional role

    • A physician’s duty to
    care for the sick

    – Social role

    • A parent’s duty to care
    for his or her children

    9

    The Ethics of Respect

    • Human interactions should be governed

    by rules of respect

    • What counts as respect can vary from

    one culture to another

    – Examples:

    • spitting in the sand

    • showing the soles of one’s shoes–Richardson

    • What is it that merits respect?

    10

    Utilitarianism

    • Seeks to reduce suffering and
    increase pleasure or
    happiness

    • Demands a high degree of
    self-sacrifice—we must
    consider the consequences
    for everyone.

    • Utilitarians claim the purpose
    of morality is to make the
    world a better place.

    11

    The Ethics of Justice

    • Begins early in the family
    with fairness to all family
    members

    • What is fair for one
    should be fair for al

    l

    • Treating people equally
    may not mean treating
    them the same

    12

    Virtue Ethics

    • Concern for character has

    flourished in the West since the

    time of Plato and Aristotle.

    • Their early dialogues explored

    such virtues as courage and piety.

    Strength of character (habit)

    • Involving both feeling and action

    • Seeks the mean between excess

    and deficiency relative to us

    • Promotes human flourishing

    • Integral to the Jesuit tradition

    – The Spiritual Exercises

    13

    Virtue Ethics

    • Seeks to develop individual

    character

    • Assumes good persons will

    make good decisions

    • Provides a way of integrating

    all the theories

    14

    Classroom Application

    E

    x

    t

    r
    e

    m
    e
    l
    y

    V

    e
    r
    y

    A

    v

    e

    r

    a

    g
    e

    L

    i

    t

    t
    l

    e

    N

    o
    t

    a

    t

    a
    l
    l

    Religious Commands

    Conscience

    Selfishness

    Duty

    Respect

    Rights

    Consequences for Everyone

    Justice

    Personal Virtues

    How important are each of the following in your life?

    Your Initial Moral Orientation

    15

    Modern Ethics

    Bibliography

    1. Bauman, Zygmunt. Postmodern Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993.

    2. Bentham, Jeremy. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, in A
    Bentham Reader. Ed. Mary Peter Mack. New York: Pegasus, 1969, 78-144.

    3. Darwin, Charles. The Descent of Man. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 198l.

    4. Dewey, John. Theory of the Moral Life. New York: Holt, 1960.

    5. Glendon, Mary Ann. Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse. New
    York: Free Press, 199l.

    6. Hinman, Lawrence. Ethics: A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory. New York:
    Harcourt Brace, 1998.

    7. McIntyre, Alasdair. Three Versions of Moral Inquiry. Notre Dame: University of Notre
    Dame, 1990.

    8. Midgley, Mary. Can’t We Make Moral Judgments? New York: St. Martin’s, 1991.

    9. Mitchell, Basil. Morality: Secular and Religious. New York: Oxford, 1980.

    10. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Birth of Tragedy and Genealogy of Morals. Garden City:
    Doubleday, 1956.

    11. Rawls, John. Justice as Fairness. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001.

    12. Smith, Thomas. Revaluing Ethics: Aristotle=s Dialectical Pedagogy. Albany: State
    University of New York Press, 2000.

    13. Susman, Warren. A Personality and the Making of Twentieth-Century Culture, in
    Culture as History. New York: Pantheon, 1984, 271-285

    14. Toulmin, Stephen. Return to Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001.

    16

    Ethics’ Alternative Approaches

    Bibliography

    1. Badiou, Alain. Ethics. New York: Verso, 2001.

    2. Baier, Annette. Moral Prejudices. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985.

    3. Blackburn, Simon. Being Good: Introduction to Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.

    4. Dalai Lama. Ethics for a New Millennium. New York: Riverhead, 2001.

    5. Furbank, P.N. Behalf. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 2000.

    6. Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982.

    7. Hallie, Philip. Lest Innocent Blood Be Shed. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1978.

    8. Hyde, Lewis. The Gift: Imagination and the Erotic Life of Property. New York: Random House, 1983.

    9. Katz, Michael and others, eds. Justice and Caring: The Search for Common Grond in Education.
    New York: Teachers College Press, 1999.

    10. Keizer, Garret. Help. San Francisco: Harper, 2004.

    11. Kitagaro, Nishida. A Study of the Good. Tokyo, Bureau of Japanese Government, 1960.

    12. MacIntyre, Alasdair. The Dependent Animal. Chicago: Open Court, 2000.

    13. Margalit, Avishai. The Decent Society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996.

    14. Sandel, Michael. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
    1982.

    15. Selznick, Philip. The Communitarian Persuasion. Washington: Woodrow Wilson Center, 2002.

    17

    Professional Ethics

    Bibliography

    1. Appleman, David and Lawton, Sarah. Ethics and the Professionals. New York: Holt, Reinhart and
    Winston, 1990.

    2. Apter, Terri. Working Women Don’t Have Wives: Professional Success in the l990s. New York: St.
    Martin’s, 1993.

    3. Bayles, Michael. Professional Ethics. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1981.

    4. Gardner, Howard and others. Good Work: When Excellence and Ethics Meet. New York: Basic
    Books, 2002.

    5. Gorlin, Rena. Codes of Professional Responsibility. Washington: Bureau of National Affairs, 1986.

    6. Illich, Ivan. Disabling Professions. Boston: Marion Boyans, 1987.

    7. Jarausch, Konrad. The Unfree Professions: German Lawyers,Teachers, Engineers 1900-1950. New
    York: Oxford University, 1990.

    8. Lebacqz, Karen. Professional Ethics. New York: Abigdon, 1985.

    9. Linowitz, Sol. The Betrayed Profession. New York: Scribner’s, 1994.

    10. Mount, Eric. Professional Ethics in Context. Louisville: Westminster/Knox, 1990.

    11. Reeck, Darrel. Ethics for the Professions. Minneapolis:Augsburg, 1983.

    12. Schmidt, Jeff. Disciplined Minds: A Critical Look at Salaried Professionals and the Soul-Battering
    that Shapes their Lives. Lanham: Littlefield and Rowan, 2000.

    13. Sullivan, William. Work and Integrity: The Crisis and Promise of Professionalism in America. San
    Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 2005.

    14. Windt, Peter et al. Ethical Issues in the Professions.New York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston, 1989.

    Still stressed from student homework?
    Get quality assistance from academic writers!

    Order your essay today and save 25% with the discount code LAVENDER