30

diogenes-2006-sargent-11-7_1

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

John Lennon’s “Imagine” (and how it shows a utopian society)

It’s pretty much an Argument type essay that has something to do with "UTOPIA".. I’m doing the topic on John Lennon’s song "Imagine". My main argument being that John Lennon’s song "Imagine" shows a utopian society. -I want to make a point where John Lennon’s song "Imagine" does show a utopian society. In the paper I would like to include definitions of Utopia. (which will be included in the works cited page.) A summary of basically what the paper is about… what john lennon’s song "Imagine".. and what it’s about… when did he write it and etc… and what a utopian society is… etc.. And a synthesis where i would like to tie Lennon’s song "imagine" and it’s message with another source… which is (Lyman Tower Sargent’s "In Defense of Utopia") And finally an analysis / evaluation. so it goes…. -summary -synthesis -analysis/evaluation —- please, no wikipedia for sources… -maximum of 5 sources. -try to interpret the song "imagine".. use quotes etc. I would also love an outline of the essay before the deadline if possible.

http://dio.sagepub.com/
Diogenes

http://dio.sagepub.com/content/53/1/11
The online version of this article can be found at:

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

DOI: 10.1177/0392192106062432

2006 53: 11Diogenes

Lyman Tower Sargent

In Defense of Utopia

Published by:

http://www.sagepublications.com

On behalf of:

International Council for Philosophy and Humanistic Studies

can be found at:DiogenesAdditional services and information for

http://dio.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

http://dio.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

http://dio.sagepub.com/content/53/1/11.refs.htmlCitations:

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

http://dio.sagepub.com/content/53/1/11

http://www.sagepublications.com

http://www.unesco.org/cipsh/

http://dio.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts

http://dio.sagepub.com/subscriptions

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav

http://dio.sagepub.com/content/53/1/11.refs.html

http://dio.sagepub.com/

In Defense of Utopia
Lyman Tower Sargent

In a number of recent and forthcoming articles and papers, I have argued that while
utopia can be dangerous, utopian visions are absolutely essential, that we must
choose utopia.1 Today, I want to try to give you the essence of that argument while
also relating it to some new issues. Let me summarize my argument:

1. Hope/desire for a better life in this life is a central aspect of the human experi-
ence.

2. That hope/desire has often been distorted by ideology and religion.
3. That hope/desire has often been captured to serve the economic and political

ends of the powerful.
4. When that hope/desire is distorted or captured, it can become dangerous.
5. That danger usually comes about because the hope/desire is warped so that the

better life is only for a select few or in-group, thus creating an out-group, an
other, who can be neglected, harmed, even killed to achieve the end. Such
groups have included members of other religions, indigenous peoples, other
ethnic groups, ideologies, and so forth. The boundaries of the other have often
been changed to include some formerly in the in-group.

6. Even so, that hope/desire for a better life is the only effective means of over-
coming such distortion/capture.

Let me give a particularly relevant example, a pattern observable in the Americas:
colonies produce utopias for the colonists and dystopias for the colonized. The
colonized are now effectively using the vision of their own eutopia against the
dystopia they were thrust into. Canada and New Zealand have responded most
positively, but the entire indigenous rights movement is based on utopian visions.

This last point applies to other social movements like the women’s movement,
where many feminist utopias have helped shape the movement. With the exception
of environmentalism, utopian literature is less obvious in other recent social move-
ments, but what I have called social dreaming is quite common.

Think of the great Spanish utopians of the period of colonization, one of whom is

Copyright © ICPHS 2006
SAGE: London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi, http://dio.sagepub.com

DOI: 10.1177/0392192106062432

Diogenes 209: 11–

17

ISSN 0392-1921

DIOGENES

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 11

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

being recognized through this meeting, Bartolomé de Las Casas (1474–1566) and
Vasco de Quiroga (1470–1565). In 1537, Pope Paul III felt the need to declare the
Indians human. Both the utopians Las Casas and Vasco de Quiroga, limited as they
were by their time period and beliefs, wanted to create a world in which the indige-
nous peoples, who were being defined as alien, non-human others, were instead
treated as human beings worthy of respect. Another utopian, Roger Williams (1603?–
83) in colonial North America, reported an Indian saying, ‘We wearne no Clothes,
have many gods, And yet our sinnes are lesse: You are Barbarians, Pagans wild, Your
Land’s the Wilderness’ (Williams, Key into the Language of America [1643] qtd. in
George H. Williams, 1962: 103).

The Dutch sociologist F. L. Polak argued that if we lost the vision of eutopia (he
called it ‘positive images of the future’), western civilization would fail, and he con-
tended that we were already moving in that direction when he was writing in the
1950s. The US architect and social critic R. Buckminster Fuller entitled one of his
books Utopia or Oblivion: The Prospects for Humanity. That was in 1969. I want to say
something similar (and I do not limit this to western civilization); if we lose eutopia,
if we lose hope, we lose our humanity. But there are both inclusive and exclusive
utopias, and the differences between the types provide one of the main reasons for
utopia being both necessary and potentially dangerous.

In the 20th century and so far in the 21st century, it is all too easy to make a case
against utopias. In the 20th century, we saw the utopias of communism and fascism
turned into their own dystopias. With the fall of communism, we saw the establish-
ment of a free-market utopia that for many people rapidly became its own dystopia.
And in the 21st century, we seem to be reverting to exclusive utopias that are for
most people inseparable from dystopia. George W. Bush is as much a utopian as the
Taliban and other Islamic extremists, and they are both certain that they are doing
their god’s work. Both of them know that they have the truth, and with power and
the willingness to impose their truth, they create dystopia in the name of utopia.

I have argued for many years that the only way to overcome utopia become
dystopia is with a new eutopia, but we have seen the communist utopia/dystopia
replaced with the free-market utopia/dystopia and should recognize that something
more has to be said. One of the problems can be seen in the relationship between
utopia and ideology, but not as used by Karl Mannheim.2 Ideology, as most com-
monly used today, refers, with variations on the basic themes, to:

. . . a system of values and beliefs regarding the various institutions and processes of
society that is accepted as fact or truth by a group of people. An ideology provides the
believer with a picture of the world both as it is and as it should be, and, in doing so, organ-
izes the tremendous complexity of the world into something fairly simple and under-
standable. (Sargent, 2006: 3)

As such, every ideology contains a utopia, and the problem with utopia arises when
it becomes a system of beliefs rather than what it is in almost all cases, a critique
of the actual through imagining a better alternative. I think of utopia as a carnival/
funfair mirror in reverse; we hold the distorted contemporary society up to the
mirror and it shows us a better possibility.

Diogenes 209

12

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 12

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

One thing that constantly irritates me in writing about utopias is the use of the
words ‘perfect’ and ‘perfection’. In English the words mean finished, completed,
without future change. Thomas More did not pretend that the society in his Utopia
was perfect; Edward Bellamy’s eutopia Looking Backward is changing, and did
change in that he wrote a sequel that had differences. H. G. Wells says that the
eutopia in Men Like Gods is rapidly changing. The only utopias that I can think of that
can be said to be perfect are some myths of an earthly paradise and some of the
depictions of heaven that were popular in the late 19th century.

The overwhelming majority of utopias were not written as depictions of unchang-
ing perfection. I think of them as like a photograph which captures a moment in time
that has had a past and will have a future, and that future will be different, although
less so than the past. Northrop Frye wrote that ‘most utopias have built-in safe-
guards against radical alteration of the structure . . .’ (1967: 31) and saw this as a
problem, but it strikes me as simply to be expected. If you have finally gotten some-
thing to work, you want safeguards against ‘radical’ – and the word radical is impor-
tant – changes in the structure, but that does not suggest that the utopia should be
considered perfect. Change is possible, even expected, just not radical change.

Think of the originating text, More’s Utopia (1516) and its imposition of slavery for
leaving town without permission, or A Pleasant Dialogue betweene a Lady called Listra,
and a Pilgrim (1579), probably by Thomas Nicholas, which has a peculiarly vicious
system of punishment to enforce honesty; for example, a judge found to have taken
a bribe has his leg sawn off with a wooden saw. J. C. Davis, in discussing his defini-
tion of utopia, says ‘The utopian is more ‘realistic’ or tough-minded in that he
accepts the basic problem as it is: limited satisfactions exposed to unlimited wants’
(1981: 37) and later says, ‘The utopian mode is one which accepts deficiencies in
men and nature and strives to contain and condition them through organisational
controls and sanctions’ (370).3

The examples of the utopia become dystopia of communism and fascism led
thinkers like Karl R. Popper in The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945) and Jacob L.
Talmon in Utopianism and Politics (1957) to argue, as Talmon put it:

Utopianism is based upon the assumption that reason alone – not habit, or tradition, or
prejudice – can be the sole criterion in human affairs. But the end of this assumption is that
reason, like mathematics, must command universal consent, since it has sole and exclusive
truth. In fact, reason turns out to be the most fallible and precarious of guides; because
there is nothing to prevent a variety of ‘reasons’ from cropping up, each claiming sole and
exclusive validity, and between which there can be no compromise, no arbiter except force.
(13)

And there is a case here. Too much reason, be it in the 16th or the 20th century, can
produce dystopia. But so can too little reason. The dystopias that are bedeviling us
in the 21st century are based on faith and tradition not reason. If I simply replace
reason with faith and tradition in the statement by Talmon just quoted, the result is
the same. It is not utopianism that is at fault, it is the insistence that a particular
utopia is the only correct way of living that is the problem.

One of the dominant themes in the writings of Isaiah Berlin serves, in a quotation

Sargent: In Defense of Utopia

13

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 13

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

from Kant, as the epigraph of one of his books – ‘Out of timber so crooked as that
from which man is made nothing entirely straight can be built’. Berlin puts this
insight into a cultural and national context, saying:

Freedom . . . is . . . to be at home, not to be impinged upon by what is not one’s own, by
alien obstacles to self-realisation whether on the part of individuals or civilisations. The
idea of the earthly paradise, of a golden age for the whole of mankind, of one life which all
men live in peace and brotherhood, the Utopian vision of thinkers from Plato to H.G. Wells,
is not compatible with this. (Berlin, ‘Apotheosis’, 225).

Berlin relates this, in what was the title of one of his essays, to ‘The Decline of
Utopian Ideas in the West’.

As I was working on an earlier version of this essay I came across a book by the
economist Albert O. Hirschman that had a title that seems to me to sum up the
message of utopianism, A Bias for Hope. Certainly, utopias are pervaded with that
bias. And, I argued in the first essay I published on utopias that even dystopias have
a positive message in that they are most often explicitly warnings of what will
happen if we don’t shape up. The dystopian is a Jeremiah telling us of the conse-
quences of our actions but holding out the hope that we can change (Sargent, 1966).

Are there utopians today? Yes, and for good and ill. As I suggested earlier the
Islamic extremists and the neo-conservatives in the United States are both hoping to
impose their visions of the good life on a mostly unwilling world. But, fortunately,
there are also other utopians, ones who believe that these utopias are in fact
dystopias, utopians who are in the model of Las Casas and Vasco de Quiroga.
Oppositional utopianism is essential to keep alive the vision of a world without
‘others’, without an oppressed. And we only need to look around us to see these
utopians alive and well in our world. Some might not agree with all my examples,
but I see utopianism in Liberation Theology, which has spread from its roots in
South America into Black, Womanist and Mujerista in the United States, all of which
keep alive a vision of a world without debilitating divisions based on class, gender,
ethnicity and race. I see it in those Islamic theorists who argue for an inclusive rather
than an exclusive Islam. I see it in the Zapatista movement in Chiapas, which, with
other groups and movements throughout the world, specifically keeps alive the
dream of a world in which indigenous peoples are not suppressed and can live a life
they choose. I see it in the World Social Forum, which provides an outlet for thou-
sands of individuals and groups to meet and develop alternatives to the dominant
ideologies and the movements that would suppress rather than free. I see it in the
continuing relevance of movements like feminism and environmentalism that
remind us of ways we can change our own lives. I see it in the thousands of inten-
tional communities still in existence or being founded where people choose utopia
for their own lives now, and work with others to create their vision. There are more
such communities in existence today than at any time other than the height of the
communal movement in the so-called Sixties. And I see it in the fact that authors still
write positive utopias to hold up a vision to us and dystopias to tell us it is not too
late to change. And these authors are also writing more complex works in which the
utopias are troubled and the dystopias hold out hope.

Diogenes 209

14

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 14

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

Utopia become ideology can be dangerous. A utopia that insists on conformity to
one model can also be used as a tool of repression and has been all too often. Thus,
personally, I opt for what Albert Camus called ‘the relative utopia’ and, much more
recently, John Rawls has called the ‘realistic utopia’ (4–6, 11–12), but it is also my case
that this is the dominant model in utopias and communities. Most utopias aim to
improve the human lot not by repression but by enhancement, and as long as we do
not aim for perfection or eliminate the possibility of change, such utopias can stand
up to the all-too-prevalent dystopias of the present. We need utopias today, and
we need the people who choose to try to live their good life today in experimental
communities, because they just may help us find the way forward out of the morass
brought about by those ideologues willing to impose their version of the good life on
all of us. We must never give up the search for eutopia.

Lyman Tower Sargent
Department of Political Science, University of Missouri-St Louis

Notes

The definitions I use are:
Utopianism – social dreaming.
Utopia – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located in time and space.

In standard usage utopia is used both as defined here and as an equivalent for eutopia (below).
Eutopia or positive utopia – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located

in time and space that the author intended a contemporaneous reader to view as considerably better than
the society in which that reader lived.

Dystopia or negative utopia – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located
in time and space that the author intended a contemporaneous reader to view as considerably worse than
the society in which that reader lived. The first use of this word is usually ascribed to Negley and Patrick’s
‘Introduction’ to their anthology, but there were much earlier uses. Deirdre Ni Chuanacháin has recently
noted a 1747 use by Henry Lewis Younge in his Utopia or Apollo’s Golden Days (Dublin: Ptd. by George
Faulkner) spelled as ‘dustopia’ used as a clear negative contrast to utopia. Before this discovery, the
earliest usage appeared to be in 1782. See Patricia Köster, ‘Dystopia: An Eighteenth Century Appearance’,
Notes & Queries 228 (n. s. 30, no. 1) (February 1983): 65–6, where she says that the first use was in 1782 by
Noel Turner (1739–1826) as dys-topia [first three letters in Greek] in ‘Letter VIII’ of his Candid Suggestions
in Eight Letters to Soame Jenkins, Esq. (London, 1782), 169–72. John Stuart Mill used ‘dys-topian’ in the
House of Commons. Hansard (12 March 1868, page 1517, column 1) reports him saying ‘I may be permit-
ted, as one who, in common with many of my betters, have been subjected to the charge of being Utopian,
to congratulate the Government on having joined that goodly company. It is, perhaps, too complimentary
to call them Utopians, they ought rather to be called dys-topians, or cacotopians. What is commonly called
Utopian is something too good to be practicable, but what they appear to favour is too bad to be practi-
cable.’ According to the OED, Cacotopia was first used by Jeremy Bentham in his Plan of Parliamentary
Reform, in the Form of a Catechism (1818, Bowring edition of his Works, 3: 493).

Utopian satire – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located in time
and space that the author intended a contemporaneous reader to view as a criticism of that contemporary
society.

Anti-utopia – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located in time and
space that the author intended a contemporaneous reader to view as a criticism of utopianism or of some
particular eutopia.

Critical utopia – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located in time and

Sargent: In Defense of Utopia

15

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 15

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

space that the author intended a contemporaneous reader to view as better than contemporary society
but with difficult problems that the described society may or may not be able to solve and which takes a
critical view of the utopian genre.

Critical dystopia – a non-existent society described in considerable detail and normally located in time
and space that the author intended a contemporaneous reader to view as worse than contemporary
society but that normally includes at least one eutopian enclave or holds out hope that the dystopia can
be overcome and replaced with a eutopia.

Intentional community – a group of five or more adults and their children, if any, who come from more
than one nuclear family and who have chosen to live together to enhance their shared values or for some
other mutually agreed-upon purpose (14–15). The term was first used in 1948 with the founding of the
Fellowship of Intentional Communities (with the exception of ‘critical dystopia’, these definitions come
from Sargent 1994).

1. These include Sargent (2003); Sargent (2004a); Sargent (2004b); ‘Choosing Utopia: Utopianism as an
Essential Element in Political Thought and Action’, a paper given at the University of Limerick and
the National University of Ireland Galway in 2003; ‘The Intersection of Utopianism and
Communitarianism’, a paper given at the Utopian Studies Society of Europe, Porto, Portugal, in 2004.
This presentation is based most explicitly on this most recent paper.

2. Unfortunately, when one mentions these terms in tandem, the specter of Mannheim rises from the
grave. Most people aren’t even aware that the book generally available under the title was not
written by Mannheim in the form it exists; it was put together by the first editors/translators from a
book of that title and a miscellany of essays. And while the book as most people have it contains
some valuable insights, Mannheim scholars generally rate it as among his least valuable pieces. Also,
utopian scholars seem to enjoy ripping the concepts out of context and applying them to places they
do not belong.

3. Davis’s approach raises a question not often addressed by students of utopia, the role of law within the
utopia rather than as a means of bringing it about. Miguel Ángel Ramiro Avilés has addressed this
question in his Utopía y derecho and in an exchange in Utopian Studies with Shulamit Almog (2001,
2003).

References

Almog, Shulamit (2001) ‘Literary Legal Utopias – Alexander’s Visit to Kasiah and Law at the End of Days’,
Utopian Studies 12(2): 164–73.

Almog, Shulamit and Amon Reichman (2003) ‘On Law and Utopia: Rules vs. Principles. A Comment on
Ramiro Avilés’s Reply’, Utopian Studies 14(1): 143–8.

Berlin, Isaiah (1990a) ‘The Apotheosis of the Romantic Will: The Revolt Against the Myth of an Ideal
World’, in his The Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters in the History of Ideas, ed. Henry Hardy, pp. 207–
37. London: John Murray. Originally published in Italian in Lettere italiane 27 (1975).

Berlin, Isaiah (1990b) Decline of Utopian Ideas in the West. Tokyo: The Japan Foundation, 1978. Rpt. as ‘The
Decline of Utopian Ideas in the West’ in his The Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters in the History of
Ideas: 20–48.

Camus, Albert (1972) Neither Victims nor Executioners, trans. Dwight Macdonald. Chicago: World Without
War Publications. Originally published in Combat (1946) and trans. in Politics (July–August 1947).

Davis, J[ames] C[olin](1981) Utopia and the Ideal Society: A Study of English Utopian Writing 1516–1700.
Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Frye, Northrop (1967) ‘Varieties of Literary Utopias’, in Utopias and Utopian Thought, ed. Frank E. Manuel.
Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1967; London: Souvenir Press, 1973, pp. 25–49. Originally published in
Daedalus 94(2) (spring 1965): 323–47.

Fuller, R. Buckminster (1969) Utopia or Oblivion: The Prospects for Humanity. New York: Bantam.
Hirschman, Albert O. (1971) A Bias for Hope: Essays on Development and Latin America. New Haven, CT: Yale

University Press.
Diogenes 209

16

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 16

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

Polak, Fred[erick] L[odewijk] (1961) The Image of the Future: Enlightening the Past, Orientating the Present,
Forecasting the Future, trans. Elise Boulding, 2 vols. Leyden: A. W. Sythoff; New York: Oceana
Publications. Originally published as De Toekomst is verleden tijd: Cultuur-futuristische verkenningen, 2
vols, Utrecht: W. de Haan, 1955. Reprinted as The Image of the Future, trans. and abridged Elise
Boulding. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1973.

Ramiro Avilés, Miguel Á[ngel] (2003) ‘On Law and Utopia: A Reply to Shulamit Almog’, Utopian Studies
14(1): 132–42.

Ramiro Avilés, Miguel Á[ngel] (2002) Utopía y derecho: El sistema jurídico en las sociedades ideales. Madrid:
Universidad Carlos III de Madrid, Instituto de Derechos Humanos ‘Bartolomé de Las Casas’/Marcel
Pons Ediciones Jurídicas y Sociales.

Rawls, John (1999) The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Sargent, Lyman Tower (1966) ‘Existentialism and Utopianism: A Reply to Frederick L. Polak’, The

Minnesota Review 6(1): 72–5.
Sargent, Lyman Tower (1994) ‘The Three Faces of Utopianism Revisited’, Utopian Studies 5(1): 1–37.
Sargent, Lyman Tower (2003) ‘The Problem of the “Flawed Utopia”: A Note on the Costs of Utopia’ in

Raffaella Baccolini and Tom Moylan (eds), Dark Horizons: Science Fiction and the Dystopian Imagination,
pp. 225–31. London: Routledge.

Sargent, Lyman Tower (2004b) ‘Utopische Literatur und die Schaffung nationaler und personaler
Identitäten’ [Utopianism and the Politics of Identity], in Jörn Rüsen and Michael Fehr (eds), Die Unruhe
der Kultur: Potentiale des Utopischen. Weilerswist: Velbrueck Publishers.

Sargent, Lyman Tower (2004a) ‘The Necessity of Utopian Thinking: A Cross-National Perspective’, in Jörn
Rüsen, Michael Fehr and Thomas W. Rieger (eds), Thinking Utopia: Steps Into Other Worlds, pp. 1–14.
New York: Berghahn Books.

Sargent, Lyman Tower (2006) Contemporary Political Ideologies: A Comparative Analysis, 13th edn. Belmont,
CA: Wadsworth/Thomson Learning.

Talmon, Jacob (1957) Utopianism and Politics. London: Conservative Political Centre.
Williams, George H[untston] (1962) Wilderness and Paradise in Christian Thought: The Biblical Experience in

the History of Christianity & the Paradise Theme in the Theological Idea of the University. New York: Harper
& Brothers.

Sargent: In Defense of Utopia
17

Diogenes 209 1/12/06 11:32 AM Page 17

at UNIV OF NEVADA LAS VEGAS LIB on September 15, 2011dio.sagepub.comDownloaded from

http://dio.sagepub.com/

Still stressed with your coursework?
Get quality coursework help from an expert!